Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T19:23:03.809Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Non-Conceptuality of the Content of Intuitions: A New Approach

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 February 2013

Clinton Tolley*
Affiliation:
University of California, San Diego

Abstract

There has been considerable recent debate about whether Kant's account of intuitions implies that their content is conceptual. This debate, however, has failed to make significant progress because of the absence of discussion, let alone consensus, as to the meaning of ‘content’ in this context. Here I try to move things forward by focusing on the kind of content associated with Frege's notion of ‘sense (Sinn)’, understood as a mode of presentation of some object or property. I argue, first, that Kant takes intuitions to have a content in this sense, and, secondly, that Kant clearly takes the content of intuitions, so understood, to be distinct in kind from that possessed by concepts. I then show how my account can respond to the most serious objections to previous non-conceptualist interpretations.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Kantian Review 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abela, P. (2002) Kant's Empirical Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allais, L. (2007) ‘Kant's Idealism and the Secondary Quality Analogy’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 45/3, 459484.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allais, L. (2009) ‘Kant, Non-Conceptual Content, and the Representation of Space’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 47/3, 383413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allison, H. (2004) Kant's Transcendental Idealism. 2nd edn. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, R. L. (2004) ‘It Adds Up After All: Kant's Philosophy of Arithmetic in Light of the Traditional Logic’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69/3, 501540.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aquila, R. (2003) ‘Hans Vaihinger and Some Recent Intentionalist Readings of Kant’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 41/2, 231250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dickerson, A. B. (2005) Kant on Representation and Objectivity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. (1997) ‘Comments on Wolfgang Künne's Paper’. In W. Künne, M. Siebel and M. Textor (eds), Bolzano and Analytic Philosophy (Amsterdam: Rodopi), pp. 241248.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. (2001) ‘Frege’. In A. P. Martinich and David Sosa (eds), Blackwell Companion to Analytic Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 620.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engstrom, S. (2006) ‘Understanding and Sensibility’. Inquiry, 49/1, 225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frege, G. (1980) Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence. Ed. B. McGuinness. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1984) Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy. Ed. B. McGuinness. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. (1992) Kant and the Exact Sciences. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Universitiy Press.Google Scholar
George, R. (1981) ‘Kant's Sensationism’. Synthese, 47/2, 229255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsborg, H. (2008) ‘Was Kant a Nonconceptualist?’. Philosophical Studies, 137, 6577.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffith, A. (2010) ‘Perception and the Categories’. European Journal of Philosophy, Early view, 130.Google Scholar
Hanna, R. (2005) ‘Kant and Nonconceptual Content’. European Journal of Philosophy, 13/2, 247290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanna, R. (2008) ‘Kantian Nonconceptualism’. Philosophical Studies, 137, 4164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanna, R. (2011) ‘Beyond the Myth of the Myth: A Kantian Theory of Non-Conceptual Content’. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 19/3, 323398.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (1902–) Kants Gesammelte Schriften. Ed. Königlich Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften, vols 1–29. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1991–) The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Ed. P. Guyer and A. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kemp Smith, N. (1918) A Commentary to Kant's ‘Critique of Pure Reason’. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Kremer, M. (2010) ‘Sense and Reference’. In M. Potter and T. Ricketts (eds), Cambridge Companion to Frege (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 220292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langton, R. (1998) Kantian Humility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, John (1984) ‘De re Senses’. Reprinted in (McDowell 1998), pp. 214–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John (1986) ‘Singular Thought and the Extent of Inner Space’. Reprinted in (McDowell 1998), pp. 228–59.Google Scholar
McDowell, John (1991a). ‘Intentionality de re’. Reprinted in (McDowell 1998), pp. 260–74.Google Scholar
McDowell, John (1991b) Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, John (1998) Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, John (2009) Having the World in View. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Natorp, P. (1910) Die logischen Grundlagen der exakten Wissenschaften. Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Parsons, C. (1992) ‘The Transcendental Aesthetic’. In Paul Guyer (ed.), Cambridge Companion to Kant (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 62100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paton, H. J. (1936) Kant's Metaphysic of Experience. London: George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. (2001) ‘Does Perception Have a Nonconceptual Content?’. Journal of Philosophy, 98/5, 239264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pippin, R. (1982) Kant's Theory of Form. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. (1989) Hegel's Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prauss, G. (1971) Erscheinung bei Kant. Berlin: De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rohs, P. (2001) ‘Bezieht sich nach Kant die Anschauung unmittelbar auf Gegenstände?’. Proceedings of the 9th International Kant Congress. Berlin: de Gruyter. vol. 2, pp. 214–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosefeldt, T. (2007) ‘Dinge an sich und sekundäre Qualitäten’. In J. Stolzenberg (ed.), Kant in der Gegenwart (Berlin: de Gruyter), pp. 167212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schellenberg, S. (2011) ‘Perceptual Content Defended’. Nous, 45/4, 714750.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sedgwick, S. (1997) ‘McDowell's Hegelianism’. European Journal of Philosophy, 5/1, 2138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W. (1968) Science and Metaphysics. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Speaks, J. (2005) ‘Is there a Problem about Non-Conceptual Content?’. Philosophical Review, 114/3, 359398.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tolley, C. (2011) ‘Kant on the Content of Cognition’. European Journal of Philosophy. EarlyView.Google Scholar
Vaihinger, H. (1892) Commentar zu Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft, vol. 2. Stuttgart: Union Deutsche Verlagsgesellschaft.Google Scholar
Watkins, E. (2008) ‘Kant and the Myth of the Given’. Inquiry, 51/5, 512531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wenzel, C. (2005) ‘Spielen nach Kant die Kategorien schon bei der Wahrnehmung eine Rolle?’. Kant-Studien, 96, 407426.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Willaschek, M. (1997) ‘Der transzendentale Idealismus und die Idealität von Raum und Zeit’. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, 51/4, 537564.Google Scholar