Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T06:41:25.456Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hail! Langdell!

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 December 2018

Abstract

Christopher Columbus Langdell (whose career ended a century ago) achieved fame by devising the case method to turn law into a laboratory science divorced from politics and to make his course so rigorous that it would attract able students seeking to test and prove themselves with the severest academic challenge. The method was adapted by many law teachers who were unpersuaded by the idea of law as apolitical science. These included Langdell's colleagues, James Bradley Thayer and John Chipman Gray, who shared Holmes's disdain for the theory. The method survived and flourished despite its theoretical weakness because it worked in practice. No mere rite of passage, it developed numerous traits and skills useful to lawyers, it revealed a true picture of the political and atomized nature of American law, and it nurtured many of the civic virtues that American law teachers have sought to nurture since the time of George Wythe.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Bar Foundation, 1995 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Langdell resigned as dean in June 1895 and retired as Dane Professor in 1930. Charles Warren, History of the Harvard Law School and of Early Legal Conditions in America 469 (1908, De Capo ed. 1970) (“Warren, History”). He died in 1906. Id. at 479.Google Scholar

2 Quoted in Arthur F. Sutherland, The Law at Harvard: A History of Ideas and Men, 1817-1867 at vii (Cambridge, Mass., 1967) (“Sutherland, JAW at Harvard”).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 Cf. James Barr Ames, Christopher Columbus Langdell, Lectures on Legal History 467 (1913).Google Scholar

4 Cohen, Felix, “Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach,” 35 Colum. L. Reu. 809 (1935); Calvin Woodard, “The Limits of Legal Realism: An Historical Perspective,” 54 Va. L. Reu. 689, 720 (1968); see also Robert Gordon, “Legal Thought and Legal Practice in the Age of American Enterprise 1870-1920,” in L. Stone & G. Geison, eds., Professions and Professional Ideologies in America 1730-1940 (1983). More gently, Willard Hunt described it merely as “in the bad sense, a schoolman's concept.”“Changing Responsibilities of the Law School, 1868-1968,” 1968 Wis. L. Reu. 336, 336 (1968).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5 Grant Gilmore, The Ages of American Law 42 (New Haven, Corn., 1977) (“Gilmore, American Law”).Google Scholar

6 Thomas Grey accurately portrays Langdell's theory as the “indispensable foil, the parental dogma that shapes the heretical growth of a rebellious offspring.” Thomas Grey, “Langdell's Orthodoxy,” 45 U. Pitt. L. Rev. 1, 3 (1983). It was indeed the foil for several generations of offspring.Google Scholar

7 Josef Redlich, The Common Law and The Case Method in American University Law Schools (New York, 1914); Alfred Z. Reed, Training for the Public Profession of he Law: Historical Developments and Principal Contemporary Problems of Legal Education in the United States with Some Account of Conditions in England and Canada (New York, 1921) (“Reed, Training”).Google Scholar

8 There may also be an analogous circularity in Langdell's underlying theory. Grey, 45 U. Pin. L. Reu. at 20-24.Google Scholar

9 For varied, kindly assessments, see Samuel Williston, Life and Law 198-200 (Boston, 1940) (“Williston, Life and Law”); Karl N. Llewellyn, The Study of Law as a Liberal An in Jurisprudence: Realism in Theory ad Practice 377 (Chicago, 1962); Sutherland, Law at Harvard 162-63; Speziale, Marcia, “Langdell's Concept of Law as Science: The Beginnings of Anti-Formalism in American Legal Theory,” 5 Vt. L. Reu. 1 (1980); and Anthony T. Kronman, The Lost Lawyer: Failing Ideals of he Legal Profession 109-21 (Cambridge, Mass., 1993) (“Kronman, Lost Lawyer”).Google Scholar

10 E.g., Duncan Kennedy, “HOW the Law School Fails: A Polemic,” 1 Yale Rev. L. & SOC. Action 71 (1970).Google Scholar

11 Among those who have questioned the effects are Reed, Training (cited in note 7); Herbert Packer & Thomas Ehrlich, New Directions in Legal Education (New York, 1972); Association of American Law Schools Curriculum Study, Training for the Public Professions of the Law (1971), republished as an appendix to Packer & Ehrlich; Robert B. Stevens, Law School: Legal Education in American from the 1850s to the 1980s (Chapel Hill, N.C., 1982) (“Stevens, Law School”).Google Scholar

12 E. g., Jerold S. Auerbach, Unequal Justice: Lawyers and Social Change in Modern America 74-101 (New York, 1976) (“Auerbach, Unequal Justice”) and id., “What Has the Teaching of Law to Do with Justice 53 N.Y.U.L. Rev. 457 (1978); Barnhizer, David, “The Justice Mission of Law Schools,” 40 Cleoe. St. L. Reu. 285, 296301 (1993).Google Scholar

13 Stevens, Law School 279. When that forecast was expressed in an earlier article he added, even more bitterly: “So much for the demise of legal history.”“Two Cheers for 1870: The American Law School,” in B. Bailyn, ed., Law in American History (1976).Google Scholar

14 Grey observed that there was no necessary connection between Langdell's legal theory and his teaching method. 45 U. Pitt. L. Rev. at 2 n.3.Google Scholar

15 Except in a few small colleges, American higher education forsook its religious connections between 1870 and 1910. Laurence R. Veysey, The Emergence of the American University (Chicago, 1970) (“Veysey, Emgence of the University); see esp. 252-59.Google Scholar

16 I take this to be an important theme of Emile Durkheim, Moral Education: A Study in the Theory and Application of the Sociology of Education, trans. E. K. Wilson & H. Schnurer (New York, 1960; orig. pub. 1925). It is empirically demonstrable that agendas influence group judgment and decisions. The case method sets an important part of the agenda for the law school class. I will explore its moral influence more fully in part V.Google Scholar

17 F. S. C. Milsom, Studies in the History of the Common Law 191 (Oxford, 1985).Google Scholar

18 In an article that is a sequel to this, I will report more fully the demise of Langdell's influence on the writing and teaching of 20th-century law teachers, focusing on the state of legal education in Chicago in 1910, “The Missionary Diocese of Chicago,” 44 J. Legal Educ. 467 (1995).Google Scholar

19 For a brief account, see Carrington, Paul D., “The Revolutionary Idea of University Legal Education. 31 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 526 (1990).Google Scholar

20 “Police” in the vernacular of the time meant “Politics”; this usage had Greek derivation.Google Scholar

21 Jefferson wrote Madison on 17 February 1826:Google Scholar

In the selection of our Law Professor, we must be rigorously attentive to his political principles. You will recollect that before the Revolution, Coke on Littleton was the universal elementary book of law students, and a sounder Whig never wrote, nor of profounder learning in the orthodox doctrines of the British constitution, or in what were called English liberties. You remember also that our lawyers were then all Whigs. But when his black-letter text and uncouth but cunning learning got out of fashion, and the honied Mansfieldism of Blackstone became the student's horn-book, from that moment, that profession (the nursery of our own Congress) began to slide into toryism, and nearly all the young lawyers are now of that hue. They suppose themselves, indeed, to be Whigs because they no longer know what whigism or republicanism means. It is in our seminary that the vestal flame is to be kept alive; it is thence to spread anew over our own and the sister States. Albert E. Bergh, ed., 12 Writings of Thomas effeson 455-56 (1907).Google Scholar

22 For an account of the beginnings at Columbia, see Julius Goebel, A History of the School of Law, Columbia University 9-11 (New York, 1955) (“Goebel, History”). Goebel describes the earlier law schools at Yale and William and Mary as adhering to English practice established at Oxford in 1758 with the appointment of Blackstone. Although other historians of American legal education have also assumed that Blackstone was a model, e.g., 1 Warren, History 1-187 (cited in note I), there is no evidence that Blackstone's appointment was in the mind of those creating law professorships in America. Certainly, it was not in the mind of Jefferson, who was no admirer of Blackstone, nor, it seems, in that of Ezra Stiles, the Jeffersonian President of Yale whose efforts were the closest model at hand for the initiative of Hamilton. In every recorded instance prior to the establishment of the Harvard Law School in 1815, the stated purpose of the college in teaching law was to respond to the needs of a democratic society for prudent leadership, which was not a purpose associated with William Blackstone. See generally Carrington, 31 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. There seems to have been an assumption operative in the mind of Warren and to some extent the minds of other New Englanders that all ideas about American law originated in Old England. Langdell seems to have been under this same disability.Google Scholar

23 Among the sources of this misgiving was the widely read work of Charles de Secondat Montesquieu, The Spirit of Laws bk. V. chs. 2-8 (“Montesquieu”), which foretold the doom of republics not led by leadership imbued with the morality of civic virtue.Google Scholar

24 This term is Kronman's (Lost Lawyer 93-101; cited in note 9) but was also in use in the French Revolution.Google Scholar

25 It was the same misgiving that gave rise to the Constitutional Convention of 1787. For a lucid account seen through the text of The Federalist Papers, see Gamy Wills, Inventing America (New York, 1981); for a contemporaneous treatment, see especially 2 John Adams, A Defense of the Constitution of the Government of the United States 504-5 (Boston, 1788).Google Scholar

26 Many Americans reacted as did Edmund Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France (London, 1790). E.g., Hugh Henry Brackenridge, Modern Chivalry, ed. C. M. Newlin, 563-64 (1937; orig. pub. 1804). See generally B. Fay, The Revolutionary Spirit in France and America (New York, 1927). For a contemporized encounter with Judge Brackenridge, see Carrington, Paul D., “Law and Chivalry: An Exhortation from the Spirit of the Hon. Hugh Henry Brackenridge of Pittsburgh (1748-1816),” 53 U. Pin. L. Rev. 705 (1992).Google Scholar

27 Sutherland, Law at Harvard 43-91 (cited in note 2); 1 Warren, History 278-376.Google Scholar

28 The Stiles plan for Yale is described by 1 Warren, History 166-70; and see Frederick Hicks, Yale Law School: The Founders and The Founders' Collection (New Haven, Conn., 1935).Google Scholar

29 See generally Marian C. McKenna, Tapping Reeve and the Litchfield Law School (New York, 1986).Google Scholar

30 Kent Newmyer, Supreme Court Justice Joseph Story 3-36 (Chapel Hill, N.C., 1985).Google Scholar

31 Sutherland, Law at Harvard 92-100 (cited in note 2).Google Scholar

32 From 1829 to 1833, Story was supported by John Hooker Ashmun, who served as Royall Professor of Law. Ashmun had been conducting a proprietary school in Northampton and brought his private students with him to study at Harvard. 1 Warren, History 424-26, 433-61 (cited in note 1). On Ashmun's death, he was succeeded by Simon Greenleaf, who had practiced law in Portland, Maine, for 25 years. Greenleaf was an effective teacher and scholar and remained at the School until 1850, succeeding Story as the Dane Professor. 1 Warren, History 480-543, 2 History 131-32.Google Scholar

33 Carrington, Paul D., “Teaching Law and Virtue at Transylvania University: The George Wythe Tradition in the Antebellum Years,” 41 Mercer L. Rev. 673 (1990).Google Scholar

34 Lieber, Manual of Political Ethics (2 vols., Boston) (“Lieber, Political Ethics”); id., Legal and Political Hermeneutics (Boston) (“Lieber, Hermeneutics”). See generally Carrington, Paul D., “The Aims of Early American Law Teaching: The Patriotism of Francis Lieber,” 42 J. Legal Educ. 339 (1992).Google Scholar

35 For a contemporary account of the qualities required of republican statesmen that strikingly resembles Lieber's, see Kronman, Lost Lawyer 53-108 (cited in note 9).Google Scholar

36 1 Lieber, Political Ethics 386.Google Scholar

37 Walker was a native of Massachusetts and a former student of John Ashmun and Joseph Story. He was active in various law reform movements. His biography is Walter T. Hitchcock, Timothy Walker: Antebellum Lawyer (New York, 1990).Google Scholar

38 This insertion is justified in part because Walker was an early advocate of the rights of women and would have welcomed women into the legal profession. See id. at 228.Google Scholar

39 Introduction to American Law: Designed as a First Book for Students 1-2 (5th ed., 1869). The 11th edition of this work was published in 1905. For an echo of Walker's statement by Langdell's immediate predecessor at Harvard, see Emory Washburn, Law as an Element of Social Science (Boston, 1868).Google Scholar

40 The founding teacher was Benjamin F. Butler, a member of the Jackson and Van Buren cabinets. On the founding of the school, see generally Ronald R. Brown, ed., The Law School Papers of Benjamin F. Butler (New York, 1987). A law department was also established at the same time at Hamilton College, with a Jacksonian as law professor. Jesse H. Cousault, “John Hiram Lathrop,” m Dumas Malone, ed., 6 Dictionary of American Biography 16 (New York, 1935).Google Scholar

41 “To dignify any one calling by styling it a profession seemed undemocratic and un-American.” Roscoe Pound, The Lawyer from Antiquity w Modem Times: with Particular Reference to the Development of Bar Associations in the United States 182 (St. Paul, Minn., 1953) (“Pound, Antiquity”).Google Scholar

42 Samuel Haber, The Quest for Authority and Honor in the American Professions 1750-900 at 209 (1991), described this 1846 constitution as “the institutional expression of a ruinous confusion of justice with politics.” See also Pound, Antiquity 223-42.Google Scholar

43 Goebel, History 44-68 (cited in note 22). Dwight came to Columbia from Hamilton, where he had been teaching law for 13 years.Google Scholar

44 New York law provided for admission to practice of any graduate of law schools designated by the legislature. The diploma privilege was abolished in New York in 1879. The story is told by Goebel, History 104-8, and by William P. LaPiana, Logic and Experience: The Origin of Modem Legal Education 83-88 (New York, 1994) (“LaPiana, Logic and Experience”).Google Scholar

45 Goebel, History 68-89. Stevens erroneously inferred that Dwight was “hostile to nonlaw subjects” being taught in his school. Law School 39 (cited in note 11). Dwight did resist requiring his students to take Lieber's course or courses taught by Lieber's successors. This opposition surely reflected his concern for enrollment, not a preference for depoliticized law teaching.Google Scholar

46 Mary O. Furner, Advocacy and Objectivity: A Crisis in the Professionalization of American Sod Science, 1865-1905 at 27 (Lexington, Ky., 1975) (“Fumer, Advocacy”). (Fumer erroneously refers to Timothy M. Dwight, the grandfather of Theodore.)Google Scholar

47 He actively opposed antitrust legislation. E.g., “The Legality of Trusts,” 3 Pol. Sci. Q. 592 (1888).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

48 The range of Dwight's interest in politics is exhibited in his formidable article, “Harrington and His Influence upon American Political Institutions and Political Thought,” 2 Pol. Sci. Q. 1 (March 1887). On Evarts' reform activities, see Chester L. Barrows, Wm. M. Ewarts: Lawyer, Diplomat, Statesmun 181-96 (Chapel Hill, N.C., 1941).Google Scholar

49 In 1817, the Michigan Territorial Legislature created a university and, at the behest of the Chief Judge of the Territory, Augustus B. Woodward, directed it to teach law. Woodward's model was the Law Department at the College of William and Mary. Elizabeth Gaspar Brown, Legal Education at Michigan 1859-1959 at 4-6 (Ann Arbor, Mich., 1959). An early enactment of the Michigan legislature in 1837 reiterated this mandate, and the directive was uttered again in 1851. Id. at 10. When at last the law department was established, its stated aim was to prepare democratic leaders. James V. Campbell, On the Study of Law (Ann Arbor, Mich., 1859); Address of Thomas McIntyre Cooley and Poem by D. Bethune Duffield on the Dedication of the Law Lecture Hall (Ann Arbor, Mich., 1863). And see Thomas McIntyre Cooley, The Lawyer's Duty to Be Faithful to His Own Manhood (Ann Arbor, Mich., 1878).Google Scholar

50 Alan R. Jones, The Constitutional Conservation of Thom Mclntyre Cooky: A Study in the History of Ideas 20-32 (New York, 1987) (“Jones, Constitutional Conservatism”).Google Scholar

51 A Treatise on he Constitutional Limitations Which Rest upon the Legislative Power of the States of the American Union (Boston, 1868; de Capo ed. New York, 1972) (“Cooley, Limitations”). This work was devoted chiefly to state constitutions that were the source of almost all restraints on state government prior to the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment in 1868.Google Scholar

52 Particularly Civil Liberty and Self-Government (Boston, 1853). Cooley referred to Lieber as “that profound thinker.” Jones, Constitutional Conservatism 109.Google Scholar

53 One bridge between Lieber and Cooley was Andrew Dexter White. White studied at Yale with Theodore Woolsey, “Lieber's most influential disciple.” Dorothy Ross, The Origins of American Sod Science 67 (Cambridge, U.K., 1991) (“Ross, Origins”). On the advice of Francis Wayland, White accepted an appointment at Michigan in 1857, two years before the arrival of Cooley. Cooley arrived in 1859, a raw but well-read intellect who shared many interests with White. White left Ann Arbor in 1867 to become the founding president of Cornell University but left behind his star pupil, Charles Kendall Adam. Both White and Adam were lifelong proponents of Lieber's historical method of studying politics. This is evident in White's The Greater States of Continental Europe (New York, 1874) and Adams's Democracy and Monarchy in France (New York, 1874). Adam succeeded White as President of Cornell in 1885 and moved on to be President of the University of Wisconsin in 1896, where his leadership foreshadowed the development of “The Wisconsin Idea.” Veysey, Emergence of the University 104 (cited in note 15). Whether White and Adam brought Cooley to Lieber is not certain, but Lieber's influence on Cooley was substantial. Jones, Constitutional Conservatism 104-9.Google Scholar

54 In 1881, Adams founded the School of Political Science earlier designed by White; Cooley succeeded Adams as the dean of that School. Howard H. Peckham, The Making of the University of Michigan 1817-1967 at 56 (Ann Arbor, Mich., 1967). The program bore a strong resemblance to that established by Lieber and Burgess at Columbia.Google Scholar

55 Jones, Constitutional Conservatism 215-16, 252-93.Google Scholar

56 A mugwump was a former Republican who supported Grover Cleveland. See generally Richard Hofstadter, The Age of Reform 131-73 (New York, 1955).Google Scholar

57 For an evaluation of his stellar performance as a regulator, see Henry J. Friendly, The Federal Administrative Agencies: The Need for Better Definition of Standards 29, 31 (Cambridge., Mass., 1962).Google Scholar

58 A partial list is on file with the author. It includes Justices Day and Sutherland of the U.S. Supreme Court, numerous U.S. Senators, and many members of highest state courts.Google Scholar

59 Dwight was born in Catskill, N.Y., in 1822; Cooley in Attica, N.Y., in 1824; Langdell in New Boston, N.H., in 1826. Dwight had started teaching law at Hamilton College in 1846; Cooley at Michigan in 1859.Google Scholar

60 These winds of change are also briefly discussed in Paul D. Carrington, “Butterfly Effects: The Political Influence of Law Teachers,” 41 Duke L.J. 741, 774-86 (1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

61 American Law 41 (cited in note 5). A candle lit during that “night” was the formation of the American Social Science Association in 1865. Charter members included Lieber and Dwight of Columbia; Baldwin, Wayland, and Woolsey of Yale; and Washbum of Harvard, all law teachers. Charles Eliot was also an early member. See Fumer, Advocacy 10-34 (cited in note 46).Google Scholar

62 For contrasting views of the corruption and its sources, see Robert H. Wiebe, The Search for Order 1877-1920 at 27-43 (New York, 1967); 2 James Bryce, The American Commonwealth 136-46 (2d ed. New York, 1913); The Autobiography of Lincoln Steffens (New York, 1931); and William S. McFeely, Grant: A Biography 404-36 (New York, 1982).Google Scholar

63 Cooley seems to have been aware of this. Jones, Constitutional Conservatism 87 (cited in note 50).Google Scholar

64 James Morris, Heaven's Command: An Imperial Progress 196 (New York, 1973).Google Scholar

65 The term is Gary Becker's. Human Capital (New York, 1964).Google Scholar

66 Veysey, Emergence of the University 264-68 (cited in note 15).Google Scholar

67 Harlan B. Phillips, Frankfurter Reminisces 26-27 (New York, 1960).Google Scholar

68 For an encapsulation of this feature of American higher education, see U.S. News & World Rep., 21 March 1994, at 66-74.Google Scholar

69 See Magali S. Larson, The Rise of Professionalism: A Sociological Analysis 141-45 (Berkeley, Cal., 1977).Google Scholar

70 Charles Warren, A History of the American Bar 562 (New York, 1921).Google Scholar

71 See generally Burton J. Bledstein, The Culture of Professionalism: The Middle Class in the Development of Higher Education (New York, 1976).Google Scholar

72 Thorstein Veblen, The Higher Learning in America: A Memorandum on the Conduct of Universities by Business Men 62-98 (New York, 1918).Google Scholar

73 For a similar account, see G. Edward White, Tort Law in America: An Intellectual History 23-26 (New York, 1980).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

74 His Study of Sociology was published in London.Google Scholar

75 Fumer, Advocacy 43-45 (cited in note 46).Google Scholar

76 Collected Essays in Political and Social Science 3-6 (New York, 1885).Google Scholar

77 Inaugural Address ar Harvard College, in 2 Richard Hofstadter & Wilson Smith, American High Education: A Documentary History 601 (New York, 1961).Google Scholar

78 1 Warren, History 357 (cited in note l), quoting Oliver Wendell Holmes, Sr.Google Scholar

79 That repute had been based on “Reports on the Course of Instruction in Yale College by a Committee of the Corporation and the Academic Faculty (1828); published in 15 Am. 1. Sci. & Arts 297 (1829), generally accepted as the ultimate statement of the case for education limited to the classics, “although there was not an original idea in it.” Frederick Rudolph, The American College and University: A History 131 (New York, 1962).Google Scholar

80 See generally George A. Baltsell, ed., The Centennial of the Sheffield School (New Haven, Conn., 1950); Louise L. Stevenson, Scholarly Means to Evangelical Ends: The New Haven Scholars and the Transformation of Higher Learning in America 1830-1890 at 67-86 (Baltimore, 1986).Google Scholar

81 F. H. Hedge, “University Reform: An Address to the Alumni of Harvard at Their Triennial Festival,” 19 July 1866, Atlantic, Sept. 1866, at 296, 299.Google Scholar

82 2 Warren, History 359.Google Scholar

83 ld. at 363.Google Scholar

84 5 Am. L. Rev. 177. The article was likely written by the editor of the Review, Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. See Mark DeWolfe Howe, Oliver Wendell Holmes: The Shaping Years 305 (Cambridge, Mass., 1957). It does, however, refer to a “science of human law” in faintly Langdellian terms.Google Scholar

85 The story of the selection is told in LaPiana, Logic and Experience 10-14 (cited in note 44). On Eliot's influence on Langdell, see Anthony Chase, “The Birth of the Modem Law School,” 23 Am. 1. Legal Hist. 329 (1979).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

86 Sutherland, Law at Harvard 165 (cited in note 2).Google Scholar

87 Parsons on Contracts was published in Boston in 1853.Google Scholar

88 2 Warren, History 360 (cited in note 1).Google Scholar

89 Id. at 360 (quoting Charles O'Conor, a lion of the New York bar).Google Scholar

90 His interest in English history was keen and enduring. Joel Seligman, The High Citadel: The Influence of the Harvard Law School 30 (Boston 1978) (“Seligman, High Citndel”).Google Scholar

91 Williston, Life and Law 200 (cited in note 9). But see Langdell, Christopher C., “The Status of Our New Territories,” 12 Harv. L. Rev. 365 (1899).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

92 Letter to Theodore Woolsey, President of Yale University, 6 Feb. 1871, quoted by LaPiana, Logic and Experience 77. Langdell wrote Woolsey declining appointment to a committee on jurisprudence of the American Social Science Association. He was in this Sense profoundly conservative. Laura Kalman, Legd Realism at Yale, 1927-1960 at 13 (Chapel Hill, N.C., 1986) (“Kalman, Legal Realism”). However, given Langdell's single-minded preoccupation with private law, there was no necessary connection between his legal theory and Social Darwinism or laissez-faire economics. He seems not to have recorded an opinion of social statics or the economics of William Graham Sumner.Google Scholar

93 Quoted in 2 Warren, History 397. The preoccupation of Eliot with the status effects of academic rigor was not exceptional. See Veysey, Emergence of the University 98-197 (cited in note 15).Google Scholar

94 2 Henry James, Charles W. Eliot, President of Harvard University 1869-1909 at 87 (Boston, 1930), quoting Eliot's letter to William James, 20 May 1894.Google Scholar

95 Eliot's view on Langdell is expressed in “Langdell and the Law School,” 33 Harv. L. Rev. 518 (1920). There is an incongruence between Eliot's approval of Langdell's theory and his participation in the work of the American Social Science Association, which was reformist.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

96 “John Marshall: In Answer to a Motion that the Court Adjourn on February 4, 1901, the One Hundredth Anniversary of the Day on Which Marshall Took His Seat as Chief Justice”in Oliver Wendell Holmes, Collected Legal Papers 266, 267 (New York, 1920) (“Holmes, Collected Pup”).Google Scholar

97 Letter to Harold Laski, 9 Dec. 1921, quoted in Richard A. Posner, ed., The Essential Holmes 115 (Chicago, 1990) (“Posner, Essential Holmes”).Google Scholar

98 There were others as well as Sumner. See generally William E. Nelson, The Roots of American Bureaucracy, 1830-1900 at 82-112 (Cambridge, Mass., 1982), and Walt W. Rostow, Theories of Economic Growth from David Hume to the Present (New York, 1990) (“Rostow, Theories of Economic Growth”); Fumer, Advocacy (cited in note 46); and Ross, Origins (cited in note 53).Google Scholar

99 Grey, 45 U. Pitt. L. Reu. (cited in note 6). Grey credits Duncan Kennedy for the term “classical” as applied to Langdellian formalism in America arising as early as 1850 and dying no later than 1940. Id. at 2 n.6. See also Morton Horwitz, The Transformation of American Low 1870-1960 at 9-32 (New York. 1992) (“Horwitz, Transformation”). This would indicate the term “pre-classical” for the more realistic thinking of earlier generations of Americans, Whig theorists being specified. Id. at 38 n.47. I quibble with the term as misleading. It suggests greater durability and strength in the moment of formalism than I perceive. Among thoughtful lawyers, it was a mere fad. l am also disconcerted by the identification of Francis Lieber as a classicist. Id. at 29 n.24. Lieber has far more in common with contemporaries such as Michelman, Sherry, Sunstein. and Kronman than with Langdell. See Carrington, 42 j. Legal Edw. (cited in note 34).Google Scholar

100 The origins of the term are explored in Fritz Schulz, Roman Legal Science 63-72 (2d ed. Oxford, 1967).Google Scholar

101 On the use of the term in antebellum America, see LaPiana, Logic and Experience 38-54 (cited in note 44).Google Scholar

102 Quoted in Sutherland, Low at Harvard 175 (cited in note 2).Google Scholar

103 Kalman, Legal Realism 13 & 120-21 (cited in note 92), is among those who identify Langdell with political conservatism.Google Scholar

104 Williston, Life and Law 205 (cited in note 9). For closer analysis of Langdell's view of precedent, see Grey, 45 U. Pin. L. Rev. at 24-27 (cited in note 6).Google Scholar

105 “In short, [New England intellectual life] was still colonial forty years after Bunker Hill. English culture had a right of way that no one thought of challenging, and every Boston boy was taught to regard Pope and Burke as unapproachable.” Van Wyck Brooks, The Flowering of New England 1815-1865 at 10 (New York, 1936).Google Scholar

106 Samuel Eliot Morison, Three Centuries of Harvard, 1636-1936 at 225-28 (Cambridge, Mass., 1936).Google Scholar

107 Langdell was certainly aware of Austin at the end of his career. See his “Classification of Rights and Wrongs,” 13 Harv. L. Rev. 537 (1900). Holmes saw Hegelian influence in Langdell, but was careful not to suggest that Langdell had ever read Hegel. Book Note, 14 Am. L. Reu. 223 (1880).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

108 “The existence of law is one thing, its merit or demerit another.” John Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, ed H. L. A. Hart, at 184 (London 1955) (“Austin, Province of Jurisprudence”). The work was first published in 1835 but was not circulated in the United States until 1861.Google Scholar

109 Norman Silber & Geoffrey Miller, “Toward ‘Neutral Principles’ in the Law: Selections from the Oral History of Herbert Wechsler,” 93 Colum. L. Rev. 854, 858 (1993). Duncan Kennedy seems to fancy that there are many surviving specimens; he alleges that the Langdell fallacy is “the intellectual core of the ideology” of contemporary legal education. Kennedy, “Legal Education and the Reproduction of Hierarchy,” 32 1. Legal Edw. 591, 596 (1982). The allegation appears to rest on a conflation of those who think law is not politics with those who think law is not merely politics. And see Posner, Richard A., “Legal Scholarship Today,” 45 Stan. L. Reu. 1647 (1993); id., “The Deprofessionalization of Legal Teaching and Scholarship,” 91 Mich. L. Reu. 921 (1993). Judge Posner attributes to all professionalism in law a “deep-seated belief in the autonomy of law as a subject of thought and practice.”CrossRefGoogle Scholar

110 2 Warren, History 376 (cited in note 1).Google Scholar

111 Cooley did not try. In A Treatise on the Low of Torts or the Wrongs Which Arise Independent of Contracts 635 (Chicago, 1879) (“Cooley, Torts”), he emphasized the “high importance” of the social policy underlying the rule.Google Scholar

112 2 Warren, History 409-13.Google Scholar

113 Langdell, Christopher C., “The Status of Our New Territories,” 12 Harv. L. Reu. 371 (1899); see also id., “The Northern Securities Case and the Sherman Anti-Trust Act,” 16 Harv. L. Rev. 539 (1903).Google Scholar

114 Langdell, , “Dominant Opinion in England during the Nineteenth Century in Relation to Legislation as Illustrated by English Legislation, or The Absence of It, during That Period,” 19 Harv. L. Reu. 151 (1906).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

115 Charles Warren, Centennial Histmy of the Harvard Law School 1817-1917 at 34-35 (Cambridge, Mass., 1917) (“Warren, Harvard Centennial”); Franklin G. Fessenden, “Rebirth of the Harvard Law School,” 33 Haw. L. Rev. 493, 497-501 (1920).Google Scholar

116 For a review of their arguments against final examinations, see Seligman, High Cita-del 32-33 (cited in note 90). The first examinations were administered in 1872; 45 students first-year students sat for them and 3 failed. 2 Warren, History 385. Those who failed were advised that they would not receive a degree, although they could remain a second year. A majority of the students did not sit for the examinations but left school without a degree. This, however, was no change from past custom. Id. at 382 n.1.Google Scholar

117 The background of Ames's appointment is described by LaPiana, Logic and Experience 15-16 (cited in note 44). As LaPiana suggests, it may have been part of Eliot's purpose thus to weaken the influence of the profession on the professional school.Google Scholar

118 Sutherland, Law at Hmvard 185 (cited in note 2). William A. Keener of the Class of 1877 was appointed in 1881 and joined Ames and Langdell in its use. Holmes was appointed in 1882 and for a brief time used the case method in reaching Torts. 2 Warren, History 428-32.Google Scholar

119 On the early difficulties of securing publishers for casebooks, see John Henry Schlegel, “Between the Harvard Founders and the American Legal Realists: The Professionalization of the American Law Professor,” 35 1. Legal Educ. 311, 317-18 (1985).Google Scholar

120 As did Roscoe Pound at Harvard as late as 1889-90. For an account of his year, see Paul Sayre, The Life of Roscoe Pound 78-84 (Iowa City, 1948).Google Scholar

121 2 Warren, History 409-13 (cited in note 1).Google Scholar

122 In 1871, tuition was $150 for the first year, $100 for the second, and $50 for the third. Sutherland, Law at Harvard 180.Google Scholar

123 Stevens, Law School 58-59 (cited in note 11). Warren writes even of “bitter opposition.” 2 Warren, History 382.Google Scholar

124 The gender requirement had been dropped by most of the public law schools during Langdell's time. See Paul D. Carrington, “One Law: The Role of Legal Education in the Opening of the Legal Profession since 1776,” 44 Fla. L. Rev. 501, 551 (1993).Google Scholar

125 2 Warren, History 468-69.Google Scholar

126 Seligman, High Citadel 41-42 (cited in note 90).Google Scholar

127 See generally McManis, Charles R., “The History of First Century American Legal Education: A Revisionist Perspective,” 59 Wash. U.L.Q. 597 (1981); Currie, Brainerd P., “The Materials of Law Study,” 31 J. Legd Educ. 331 (1950).Google Scholar

128 In his inaugural address, Professor Story advised his law students “to addict [themselves] to the study of philosophy, of rhetoric, of history, of human nature.” W. Story, ed., The Miscellaneous Writings of Joseph Story 529 (Boston, 1852) (“Story, Writings of Joseph Story”). Currie, 31 J. Legal Educ. at 361-67, observed that the teaching of the Harvard Law School in Story's time was limited to the reading of legal materials and the performance of professional tasks. He accordingly concluded that Story was responsible for the narrowness of Harvard legal education in later decades. It is true, as Currie observed, that the Harvard program was less broad than the teaching being done in Story's time at the University of Maryland or Transylvania University, but in its previous iteration, the Harvard Law School had failed for want of students and the students coming in Story's time seldom stayed for long enough to secure the broad education he described in his inaugural lecture. Story's advice had been taken seriously by at least some of his students. Charles Sumner, one of Story's favorite students, made himself a pedant in an effort to maintain Story's favor. See David Donald, Charles Sumner and he Coming of the Civil Was 22-35 (Cambridge, Mass., 1967).Google Scholar

129 Rostow, Theories of Economic Growth 153-55 (cited in note 98). See also Fumer, Advocacy 278-312 (cited in note 46), and Ross, Origins 172-218 (cited in note 53).Google Scholar

130 Thomas L. Haskell, The Emergence of Professional Social Science: The American Social Science Association and the Nineteenth Century Crisis of Authority (Urbana, Ill., 1977).Google Scholar

131 Auerbach, Unequal Justice 102-29 (cited in note 12); Richard L. Abel, American Lawyers 40-73 (New York, 1989) (“Abel, American Lawyers”).Google Scholar

132 On the contemporary consequences of elevated admission standards, see Carl Auerbach, ''Legal Education and Some of Its Discontents,” 34J. Legal Educ. 43 (1984).Google Scholar

133 Carrington, 44 Fla. L. Rev. at 563-67.Google Scholar

135 Cf. “Address of Chief Justice Holmes at the Dedication of the Northwestern University Law School Building,” Chicago, 20 Oct. 1902, m Holmes, Collected Papers 272, 277 (cited in note 96): “I almost fear that the intellectual ferment of the better schools may be too potent an attraction to young men and seduce into the profession many who would be better elsewhere.”Google Scholar

136 Holmes to Sir Frederick Pollock, 10 April 1881, 1 Holmes-Pollock Letters 17 (Boston, 1941).Google Scholar

137 Shattuck had been a law school classmate of Langdell and had been consulted by Eliot in making the Langdell appointment. LaPiana, Logic and Experience 12 (cited in note 44). He was also later a mentor to Holmes.Google Scholar

138 White, G. Edward, “Revisiting James Bradley Thayer,” 88 Nw. U.L. Rev. 48, 6063 (1993).Google Scholar

139 Thayer, James Bradley, “Law and Logic,” 14 Harv. L. Rev. 139 (1900).Google Scholar

140 Holmes taught Constitutional Law in Harvard College during the first years of Langdell's administration of the law school. 2 Warren, History 431 (cited in note 1).Google Scholar

141 Cases on Constitutional Law (2 vols., Boston, 1895).Google Scholar

142 This characterization of Cooley will surprise some readers. Because his 1868 work was cited by the Supreme Court in the line of cases leading to its decision in Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905), the conventional view among 20th-century historians has been that Cooley was a social Darwinist or at least a libertarian in contemporary parlance. For a recent expression of that assessment, see Kermit Hall, The Magic Mirror Law in American History 222-23 (New York, 1989). Cooley was, however, a “bamburner”-a radical adherent of Andrew Jackson. As his writings did indeed reflect, he mistrusted legislative regulation of the economy. But, as Jackson's opposition to the Bank of the United States reflected, early populists, of whom Cooley was one, opposed most government intervention in economic matters because they supposed that, in the end, the government's efforts will mostly enrich the wealthy and empower the powerful. He found evidence confirming this view in the performance of the federal government led by Ulysses Grant and his successors. Our own time is not without examples. Cooley strongly favored antitrust laws and public health regulations, and concluded his career as an aggressive regulator of railroads. It is not likely that he would as a judge have voted within the majority in Lochner. For further discussion with particular reference to Cooley's views on professional licensing, see Carrington, Paul D., “Legal Education for the People: Populism and Civic Virtue,” 43 Kan. L. Rev. 1 (1994).Google Scholar

143 Jones, Constitutional Conservatism 247 (cited in note 50) (quoting letter of Thayer to Cooley, 24 March 1885).Google Scholar

144 19 How. 393 (1857). Thomas Grey also points to the legal tender case, Hepbum v. Griswold, 75 U. S. 608 (1868), as a prime example of Thayer's concern. “Thayer's Doctrine: Notes on Its Origin, Scope and Present Implication,” 88 Nw. U.L. Rev. 28, 32-34 (1993). See also Thayer, James B., “Legal Tender,” 1 Harv. L. Rev. 73 (1887). Mark Tushnet deconstructs Thayer as an advocate for more effective lobbying by industrialists. “Thayer's Target: Judicial Review or Democracy?” 88 Nw. U.L. Rev. 9 (1993).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

145 “The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law,” 7 Haw. L. Rev. 129, 144 (1893).Google Scholar

146 ld. at 156.Google Scholar

147 For presentation of many view of this essay, see Symposium, “One Hundred Years of Judicial Review: The Thayer Centennial Symposium,” 88 Nw. U.L. Rev. 1 (1993).Google Scholar

148 A Preliminary Treatise on Evidence at Common Law (Boston, 1898). This work was in some measure derivative from the earlier work of Simon Greenleaf's, a contemporary and Harvard Law colleague of Joseph Story. See his Treatise on the Law of Evidence (1st ed. 1842).Google Scholar

149 Treatise on Evidence (4 vols., Boston, 1904-5). On the relationship between Thayer and Wigmore, see William Twining, Theories of Evidence 5-9 (Stanford, Cal., 1985).Google Scholar

150 “A People without Law,” 68 Atlantic Monthly 683 (1891).Google Scholar

151 “New Possessions,” 12 Harv. L. Rev. 464, 465-66 (1899). Compare Baldwin, Simeon E., “The Constitutional Questions Incident to the Acquisition and Government by the United States of Island Territory,” 12 Harv. L. Rev. 393 (1899), and Langdell, 12 Hmv. L. Reu. (cited in note 113).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

152 “The Teaching of English Law at Universities,” 9 Hmv. L. Rev. 169, 171 (1894).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

153 Id. at 184.Google Scholar

154 Roland Gray, John Chipman Gray 7 (Boston, 1917) (“R. Gray, Gray”).Google Scholar

155 Compare the teaching of Lieber on the relation of rights to duties. Carrington, 42 I. Legal Educ. (cited in note 34).Google Scholar

156 Address in R. Gray, Gray 50.Google Scholar

157 Quoted m id., at 138.Google Scholar

158 Quoted in id. at 49.Google Scholar

159 Remarks, in id. at 115.Google Scholar

160 Gray wrote Eliot that Langdell's “intellectual arrogance and contempt is astonishing” and his detachment from reality a cause for despair about the future of the school. Letter of 8 Jan. 1883, quoted in Mark DeWolfe Howe, Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes: The Proving Years 158 (Cambridge, Mass., 1963) (“Howe, Holmes: The Proving Years”). See also LaPiana, Logic and Experience 18-20 (cited in note 44).Google Scholar

161 Ezra Ripley Thayer, “John Chipman Gray,” 28 Harv. L. Rev. 539, 543 (1915).Google Scholar

162 In the preface to his first major work, The Rule against Perpetuities v (Boston, 1886) (“Gray, The Rule”), he explained: “In no part of the law is the reasoning so mathematical in its character; none has so small a human element. A degree of dogmatism, therefore, may be permitted here which would be unbecoming in other branches of the law.”Google Scholar

163 Select Cases and Oh Authorities on the Law of Property (4 vols.; Cambridge, Mass., 1888-90).Google Scholar

164 Gray, The Rule iii.Google Scholar

165 Robert S. Summers lists him as the first “instrumentalist.”Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory 23 (Ithaca, N.Y., 1982). But see Alexander, Gregory S., “The Dead Hand and the Law of Trusts in the Nineteenth Century,” 37 Stan. L. Reu. 1189 (1985).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

166 Restraints on the Alienation of Property ix (Boston, 1895).Google Scholar

167 Id. at xi.Google Scholar

168 Id. at x.Google Scholar

169 R. Gray, ed., The Name and Sources of Law 2 (2d ed. Boston, 1921). The first edition was published in 1909 (“Gray, Nature and Sources”).Google Scholar

170 Id. at 4.Google Scholar

171 Id. at 125.Google Scholar

172 This is the characterization given Gray in William Twining, Karl Llewelyn and the Realist Movement 22 (London, 1973) (“Twining, Llewelyn”).Google Scholar

173 Gray, Nature and Sources 222-32.Google Scholar

174 Id. at 85.Google Scholar

175 Id. at 121.Google Scholar

176 Lieber, Hermeneutics (cited in note 34).Google Scholar

177 Cooley, Limitations 38-84, 159-88 (cited in note 51).Google Scholar

178 Gray, Nature and Sources 243 (cited in note 169).Google Scholar

179 91 U. S. 216 (1842).Google Scholar

180 Gray, Nature and Sources 253.Google Scholar

181 304 U. S. 64 (1938). Holmes was not alive to participate in the decision.Google Scholar

182 Gray, Nature and Sources 281-90.Google Scholar

183 In some measure, this applies even to Dwight, although to Dwight, history revealed stable, perhaps permanent, principles. See Inaugural Addresses of Theodore W. Dwight and George P. Marsh in Columbia College 38-40 (1859). And see Gilmore, American Law 34-60 (cited in note 5). “Historical jurisprudence” is a view that abides. E.g., Clark, Robert, “The Interdisciplinary Study of Legal Education,” 90 Yale L. J. 1238 (1981); Young, Stephen B., “Beyond Bork: Historical Jurisprudence in Replacement of the Enlightenment Project,” 35 J. Legal Educ. 333 (1985). Compare Carrington, 41 Duke L.J. (cited in note 60).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

184 Gray, Nature and Sources 239-40.Google Scholar

185 On the distinction between citation and influence, see Carrington, 41 Duke L.J. 850-801 (cited in note 60).Google Scholar

186 “Methods of Legal Education,” 1 Yale L.J. 159, 161 (1891).Google Scholar

187 This feature of the Gray book became almost universal. See Albert James Hamo, Legal Education in the United Stares 69 (Chicago, 1953).Google Scholar

188 Pound's debt to Gray is discussed in Sutherland, Law at Harvard 201-4 (cited in note 2). Pound was like Gray influenced by Savigny; his “sociological jurisprudence” was but a step beyond “historical jurisprudence.” See David Wigdor, Roscoe Pound, Philosopher of Law 161-232 (Westport, Conn., 1974).Google Scholar

189 Frankfurter was also close to Thayer and a powerful influence on his successors at Harvard. Frankfurter reacted against the emphasis on private law, and sought to bring the Harvard Law School back to the traditional aim of American law teachers, training a democratic elite. See Michael E. Parrish, Felix Frankfurter and His Times: The Reform Years (New York, 1982); Levinson, Sanford, “The Democratic Faith of Felix Frankfurter,” 25 Stan. L. Rev. 430 (1973).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

190 His academic standing was undistinguished, but Harvard marks in his time were substantially based on deportment. For discussion, see G. Edward White, Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes: Law and the Inner Self 25-27 (New York, 1993) (“white, Holmes”).Google Scholar

191 Quoted in Liva Baker, The Justice from Beacon Hill 97 (New York, 1991) (“Baker, The Justice).Google Scholar

192 For a full account of Holmes's military experience, see Sheldon Novick, The Life of Oliver Wendell Holmes 29-89 (Boston, 1989).Google Scholar

193 It may be overstatement to say that “[t]he lesson Holmes seems to have derived from his Civil War experience is that all passionate appeals to conscience and morality resulted in the destruction of a fragile social order.” Horwitz, Transformation 116 (cited in note 99). Holmes was not wrong in believing that the abolitionists he knew as a youth were so overwrought by their disgust with slavery that they were irrational in favoring a program, viz., disunion, that would have done nothing to relieve the misery of the slaves.Google Scholar

194 Letter to Frederick Pollock, 30 Aug. 1929, quoted in Posner, Essential Holmes 108-9 (cited in note 97).Google Scholar

195 Letter to Harold Laski, 20 Aug. 1909, quoted in id. at 116.Google Scholar

196 “The Gas Stokers' Strike,” 7 Am. L. Rev. 582, 583 (1873).Google Scholar

197 William James, quoted in Baker, The Justice 268.Google Scholar

198 1 John Torrey Morse, Life and Letters of Oliver Wendell Holmes 63 (Boston, 1896).Google Scholar

199 Quoted in Baker, The Justice 176.Google Scholar

200 Commentaries on American Law (12th ed. Boston, 1873).Google Scholar

201 For a full account of this event, see White, Holmes 124-27 (cited in note 190).Google Scholar

202 Baker, The Justice 208 (cited in note 191).Google Scholar

203 Quoted in id. at 208-9. Holmes's published review of Langdell was less harsh. Book Notice, 6 Am. L. Rev. 354 (1872) and Book Notices, 14 Am. L. Rev. 14 (1880). The latter, a review of the second edition, was unsigned. For attribution of authorship, see Saul Touscer, “Holmes a Hundred Years Ago: The Common Law and Legal Theory,” 10 Hofsna L. Rev. 673, 695 n. 91 (1982).Google Scholar

204 Book Note, 14 Am. L. Rev. 233 (1880).Google Scholar

205 See generally on Holmes's view of Langdell, Howe, Holmes: The Proving Years 155-59 (cited in note 160).Google Scholar

206 Holmes, The Common Law, ed. Mark Dew. Howe, at 32 (Boston, 1963) (“Holmes, The Common Law”).Google Scholar

208 Dicey's review appeared in The Spectator for June 3, 1882; for discussion see White, Holmes 185.Google Scholar

209 White, Holmes 171.Google Scholar

210 In one important respect, Holmes was Austinian. This was in the stem distinction he made between law and morality. See generally his “The Path of the Law,” 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

211 The “Grand Style” of American judicial opinions appeared at the outset. For explanation, see Carrington, 41 Duke L.J. 753-55 (cited in note 60). Slavery litigation contributed to a revival of English formalism in the middle of the 19th century. Nelson, William E., “The Impact of the Anti-Slavery Movement upon Styles of Judicial Reasoning in Nineteenth Century America,” 87 Harv. L. Rev. 513 (1974).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

212 White, Holmes 152 (cited in note 190), notes that Holmes's inadequate citations had the effect of making him appear to be “virtually alone” in his views.Google Scholar

213 William Roalfe, John Henry Wigmore: Schoh and Reformer 78 (Evanston, Ill., 1977) (“Roalfe, Wigmore”).Google Scholar

214 Story, Writings of Joseph Story (cited in note 128).Google Scholar

215 10 Harv. L. Rev. This was a lecture presented at Boston University in 1897. Horwitz, Transformation 142 (cited in note 99), identifies this lecture as the moment from which Langdell's theory of apolitical law “was brought constantly under attack.” This may reflect a somewhat ethnocentric view; I am not certain that Langdell's theory was ever taken seriously enough west of the Hudson River to warrant an attack.Google Scholar

216 St. George Tucker succeeded George Wythe as Professor of Law and Police at the College of William and Mary in 1790. His Americanized version of Blackstone's Commentaries was published in four volumes at Philadelphia in 1803.Google Scholar

217 Among those who have celebrated Holmes's work as an intellectual breakthrough was Felix Frankfurter. Kalman, Legal Realism 55-56 (cited in note 92). Frankfurter was perhaps justly accused of “institutional parochialism” requiring him to celebrate everyone associated with the Harvard Law School. Nevertheless, he was not wrong to see in Holmes almost everything that was later said by Frank, Llewellyn, and Douglas. Where perhaps he erred was in failing to trace those ideas beyond Holmes into earlier antecedents.Google Scholar

218 Cooley, Torts 11-12 (cited in note 111).Google Scholar

219 In Felix Franfurter, ed., Ms. Justice Holmes and the Supreme Court 3 (Cambridge, Mass., 1938).Google Scholar

220 Baker, The Justice 267-68 (cited in note 191).Google Scholar

221 “The Use of Law Schools,” in Holmes, Collected Papers 35 42-46 (cited in note 96) (“Holmes, ‘Use of Law Schools’”).Google Scholar

222 See White, Holmes 202-6 (cited in note 190).Google Scholar

223 Holmes to Felix Frankfurter, 15 July 1913, quoted in id. at 206.Google Scholar

224 “Despondency and Hope,” Remarks at a Dinner of the Chicago Bar Association, 21 Oct. 1902, quoted by Posner, Essential Holmes 150 (cited in note 97).Google Scholar

225 Black & White Taxicab & Transfer Co. v. Brown & Yellow Taxicab & Transfer Co., 276 US. 518 (1921).Google Scholar

226 Grey, , “Holmes and Legal Pragmatism,” 41 Stan. L. Rev. 787 (1989).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

227 Quoted in Baker, Holmes 270.Google Scholar

228 “The Profession of the Law,” Lecture at Harvard University, 17 Feb. 1886, in Holmes, Collected Papers 29 (cited in note 96).Google Scholar

229 Hammond was the founder of two law schools, Iowa and Washington University. Emlin McClain, “William Gardiner Hammond,” in William Draper Lewis, ed., 8 Great American Lawyers 191, 220-21 (1909). He was also the editor of the posthumous edition of Lieber's Hermeneutics (cited in note 34).Google Scholar

230 Pomeroy and his method are described in Thomas Garden Barnes, Hastings College of Law: The First Century 88-116 (San Francisco 1978).Google Scholar

231 See generally Reed, Training 369-85 (cited in note 7); Stevens, Law School 60-63 (cited in note 11).Google Scholar

232 William A. Keener, Harvard Law ‘78, was appointed to the faculty in 1883. He was appointed Story Professor in 1888. 2 Warren, History 432, 443 (cited in note 1). The next year, he resigned in a salary dispute. Williston, Life and Law 129-30 (cited in note 9). He was promptly appointed at Columbia and was soon appointed dean, replacing Dwight in 1891. Goebel, History 135-58 (cited in note 22). In “The Inductive Study of Law,” 28 Am. L. Rev. 713 (1893), he defended the method as a source of “mental discipline,” not scientific law. See also William A. Keener, Preface, Selection of Cares on the Law of Quasi-Contract (New York, 1888).Google Scholar

233 Goebel, History 118-22.Google Scholar

234 Id. at 143.Google Scholar

235 Professor Burgess, who had held a joint appointment in Law and Political Science, was eased out of the law faculty by Keener. But he and several others continued teaching in the Law School. Id. at 148-49. Keener left the deanship in 1901. The Law School returned to the broader intellectual horizons afforded by Kent and Lieber with the appointment of Harlan Fiske Stone as dean in 1910. For the ensuing two decades, it was the cockpit of efforts to blend professional training with wide-ranging inquiry. Id. at 215-305; Currie, Brainerd, “The Materials of Law Study (Part Ill),” 8 J. Legal Educ. 1 (1955).Google Scholar

236 Wigmore was politically active throughout his long career, which he commenced teaching law as a comparatist on the faculty of Keio University in Tokyo. Roalfe, Wigmore 21-31 (cited in note 213).Google Scholar

237 Id. at 61.Google Scholar

238 Charles N. Gregory had been the first emissary from Harvard, but he had failed to persuade most of those teaching there. Richards came as dean a few years later. William R. Johnson, Schooled Lawyers: A Study in the Clash of Professional Cultures 107, 120-33 (1978) (“Johnson, Schooled Lawyers”); W. Scott Van Alstyne, “The University of Wisconsin Law School: An Outline History,” 1968 Wis. L. Reu. 321, 326-27.Google Scholar

239 Gilmore was deeply involved in the Progressive Movement in Wisconsin. He later served as President of the Association of American Law Schools and of the University of Iowa. His views on legal education are set forth in “Some Criticisms of Legal Education,” 7 A.B.AJ. 227 (1921). On the university's role in the state, see Charles McCarthy, The Wirconsin Idea (Madison, Wis., 1912).Google Scholar

240 Henry F. Pringle, The Life and limes of William Howard Taft 125 (New York, 1931).Google Scholar

241 Frederick C. Hicks, William Howard Tab: Yale Professor of Law and New Haven Citizen 46-87 (New Haven, Conn., 1945).Google Scholar

242 Grey denotes Beale as “the philosopher of classical orthodoxy.” 45 U. Pin. L. Rew. at 29 (cited in note 6). See, e.g. Beale, Joseph Henry, “The Developments of Jurisprudence during the Past Century,” 18 Harv. L. Rev. 271 (1905). Yet, upon his return from Chicago in 1904, kale pursued a new interest in public law. The Law of Rate Regulation with Special Reference to American Legislation (Boston, 1906). One wonders whether this reflected the influence on him of his Chicago colleague, Ernst Freund. On the rivalry between the two, see Frank L. Ellsworth, Law on The Midway: The Founding of the University of Chicago Law School 68-74 (Chicago, 1977) (“Ellsworth, Law on the Midway”), and Oscar Kraines, The World and Ideas of Ernst Freund 86 (Tuscaloosa, Ala., 1974) (“Kraines, Freund”). Bealism was the object of scorn in Jerome Frank, Law and the Modern Mind 53-61 (reprint, Gloucester, Mass., 1970), and in Walter Wheeler Cook, The Logical and Legal Bases of the Conflict of Laws (New Haven, Conn., 1942), passim. Google Scholar

243 The story is fully told in Ellsworth, Law on the Midway 60-78.Google Scholar

244 He earned a Columbia doctorate with Frank Goodnow, Lieber's student who was teaching in the program established at Columbia by Lieber.Google Scholar

245 See generally Kraines, Freund. Google Scholar

246 Paul L. Sayre, “A Common Law of Administrative Powers,” 18 Iowa L. Rew. 241, 243 (1933).Google Scholar

247 “Yale Cases” had been printed for use of Yale students as early as 1891, but the method was not used before Rogers's time. Frederick C. Hicks, Yale Law School 1895-1915: Twenty Yean of Hendrie Hall 43-44 (New Haven, Conn., 19381.Google Scholar

248 Charles E. Clark, “Henry Wade Rogers,”in Dumas Malone, ed., 18 Dictionary of American Biography 97 (1926) (“Clark, ‘Rogers’”).Google Scholar

249 Rogers was, however, disesteemed by Corbin and Llewellyn. Twining, Llewelyn 98 & 416-17 n.56 (cited in note 172).Google Scholar

250 Baldwin was the founding spirit of the American Bar Association. He was also a member of the Supreme Court of Connecticut while teaching at Yale and in that role manifested a tendency to formalism common to his age. He was, however, a pioneer of social science and organized a graduate program in law and social science. By the time of Rogers's arrival, Baldwin's role in the law school was marginal to his political career as governor and then senator. Frederick H. Jackson, Simeon Eben Baldwin: Lawyer, Sod Scientist, Statesman 125-32 (New York, 1955) (“Jackson, Baldwin”).Google Scholar

251 Id. at 128. Baldwin had published Illustrative Cases on Railroad Law (New Haven, Conn., 1896).Google Scholar

252 See Simeon E. Baldwin, “Graduate Courses at Law Schools,” 11 1. SOC. Sci. 132 (1879).Google Scholar

253 His most celebrated work was in this field, and it led to the observation that he was “no closet thinker” but “had been through it all.” Letter of Alfred R. Russell to Baldwin, 16 Nov. 1904, quoted by Jackson, Baldwin 147.Google Scholar

254 For an account of his later political travails, see Charles C. Goetsch, Essays on Simon E. Baldwin (Storrs, Conn., 1981).Google Scholar

255 See, e.g., his Modem Political Institution (New York, 1898). And on his aims as a law teacher, see The Relations of Education to Citizenship (New Haven, Conn., 1912). They appear to reflect the influence of Lieber and are in the antebellum tradition.Google Scholar

256 The senior Woolsey, then the Yale President, had edited posthumous editions of Lieber's Civil Liberty and Self Government (Philadelphia, 1874) and his Manual of Political Ethics (Philadelphia, 1875). His son edited a fourth edition of the former work in 1901. Lieber's work was used in teaching Constitutional Law at Yale for over a half-century.Google Scholar

257 The story is told by LaPiana, Logic and Experience 143-47 (cited in note 44).Google Scholar

258 The story is told in Twining, Llewelyn 26-34 (cited in note 172).Google Scholar

259 Gilmore, American Law 79-80 (cited in note 5).Google Scholar

260 “The Higher Legal Education,” 1 Cent. L.J. 540 (1876).Google Scholar

261 14 ABA Proceedings 332 (1892).Google Scholar

262 15 ABA Proceedings 340 (1893).Google Scholar

263 Johnson, Schooled Lawyers 117 (cited in note 238).Google Scholar

264 Reed, Training 274, 382 (cited in note 7).Google Scholar

265 “Why Not a Clinical Law School? 81 U. P4. L. Rev. 908 (1932).Google Scholar

266 See Bamhizer, David, “The University Ideal and Clinical Legal Education,” 35 N.Y.L. School Reu. 87 (1990); see also Seligman, High Citadel 160-75 (cited in note 90).Google Scholar

267 Robert F. Condlin, “The Moral Failure of Clinical Legal Education” in David Luban, ed., The God Lawyer: Lawyers' Roles and Lawyers' Ethics 335 (Totowa, N.J., 1988); but see Redlich, Norman, “The Moral Value of Clinical Legal Education: A Reply,” 33 J. Legal Educ. 613 (1983); see generally Stevens, Law School 240-41 (cited in note 11).Google Scholar

268 See also Robert F. Condlin,”‘Tastes Great, Less Filling': The Law School Clinic and Political Critique,” 36 1. Legal Educ. 45 (1986); Kenny Hegland, “Condlin's Critique of Conventional Clinics: The Case of The Missing Case,” 361. Legal Educ. 427 (1986); Stark, Joseph H., Tegeler, Philip D. & Channels, Noreen L., “The Effect of Student Values on Lawyering Performance: An Empirical Response to Professor Condlin,” 37 J. Legal Educ. 409 (1987).Google Scholar

269 Seligman, High Citadel 36. Cf. Savoy, Paul N., “Toward A New Politics of Legal Education,” 79 Yak L.J. 444 (1970); David Kairys, ed., The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique (New York, 1982) (“Kairys, Politics of Law”).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

270 It is likely that the three-year curriculum, by giving such a prominent place to private law, has had a long-term effect on the political thinking of lawyers. Kennedy, Duncan, “The Political Significance of the Law School Curriculum,” 14 Seton Hall L. Rev. 1 (1983). That is not, however, a direct or necessary consequence of the use of the case method.Google Scholar

271 The reasons for this are stated below, text at notes 347-57.Google Scholar

272 On the differences between alienation and hostility, see Carrington, Paul D. & Conley, James, “The Alienation of Law Students,” 75 Mich. L. Rev. 887 (1977), and id., “Negative Attitudes of Law Students: A Republication of the Alienation and Dissatisfaction Factors,” 76 Mich. L. Rev. 1036 (1978). There was in those studies little to suggest that variations in law school teaching methods could account for either.Google Scholar

273 Auerbach, Unequal Justice (cited in note 12), and see especially “Plague of Lawyers,”Harper's, Oct. 1976, at 37.Google Scholar

274 The villain of John J. Osbome, The Paper Chase (Boston 1971).Google Scholar

275 1 Yale Rev. L. d Soc. Action (cited in note 10).Google Scholar

276 One L (New York, 1977).Google Scholar

277 High Citadel 155 (cited in note 90).Google Scholar

278 Life on the Mississippi 123-24 (Heritage Press ed. New York, 1944) (“Twain, Mississippi”).Google Scholar

279 See Heins, Marilyn, Fahey, Shirley Nichols & Henderson, Roger C., “Law Students and Medical Students: A Comparison of Perceived Stress,” 33 J. Legal Educ. 511 (1983); Bernard L. Diamond, Psychological Problems of Law Students in Looking at Law Schools 19 (Stephen Gillers ed., New York, 1977); Taylor, James S., “Law School Stress and The Deformation Professionelle,” 27 J. Legal Educ. 251 (1975); Stone, Alan A., “Legal Education on the Couch,” 85 Harv. L. Rev. 392 (1971); Watson, Andrew S., “The Quest for Professional Competence: Psychological Aspects of Legal Education,” 37 U. Cin. L. Rev. 93 (1968); Eron, Leonard D. & Redmount, Robert S., “The Effect of Legal Education on Attitudes,” 9 J. Legal Educ. 431 (1957).Google Scholar

280 E.g., G. Andrew Benjamin, Alfred Kozniak, Bruce Sales, & Stephen B. Shenfield, “The Role of Legal Education in Producing Psychological Distress among Law Students and Lawyers,” 1986 A.B.F. Res. J. 225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

281 Faith Dickinson, “Psychological Counseling of Law Students: One Law School's Experience,” 37 J. Legal Educ. 82, 87 (1987).Google Scholar

282 “The Ordinary Religion of the Law School Classroom,” 29 J. Legal Educ. 247 (1978).Google Scholar

283 “The Quest for Meaning: Narrative Accounts of Legal Education,”38 J. Leg & Ed. 577, 585 (1988).Google Scholar

284 E.g., Woodard, 54 Va. L. Rev. at 727 (cited in note 4).Google Scholar

285 The Young Man and the Law 128-29 (New Haven, Conn., 1930).Google Scholar

286 See remarks of Senator John Brown quoted in E. Lee Shepard, “George Wythe,”in W. Hamilton Bryson, ed., Legal Education in Virginia 1779-1979 at 753 (1982).Google Scholar

287 Twain, Mississippi 39-89.Google Scholar

288 Goebel, History 138-39 (cited in note 22).Google Scholar

289 Id. at 118.Google Scholar

290 Sutherland. Law a Harvard 201-3 (cited in note 2).Google Scholar

291 Goebel, History 139-40.Google Scholar

292 Clark, “Rogers” at 97 (cited in note 248).Google Scholar

293 The Bill of Rights 77 (Cambridge, Mass., 1958).Google Scholar

294 Richard Kluger, Simple Justice: The History of Brown v. Board of Education and Black America's Struggle for Equality 127-28 (New York, 1976) (“Kluger, Simple Justice”). On Houston's teaching, see more generally Genna Rae McNeil, Groundwork: Charles Hamilton Houston and the Struggle for Civil Rights 57-128 (Philadelphia, 1983).Google Scholar

295 Kluger, Simple Justice 126.Google Scholar

296 James A. Elkins, “Rites de Passage: Law Students ‘Telling Their Lives,’” 35 J. Legal Educ. 26 (1985); compare Schlegel, John Henry, “Langdell's Legacy, Or The Case of the Empty Envelope,” 34 Stan. L. Rev. 1517 (1984).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

297 Edward J. Phelps, “Methods of Legal Education,” 1 Yale L.J. 139, 143 (1892).Google Scholar

298 Johnson, Schooled Lawyers 115-16 (cited in note 238).Google Scholar

299 In fact, Ames may never have been in this sense a purist, although he sometimes sounded as one. See Grey, 45 U. Pitt. L. Rev. at 29 n.102 (cited in note 6).Google Scholar

300 Warren, Harvard Centennial 81 (cited in note 115).Google Scholar

301 Veysey, Emergence of the University 21-56 (cited in note 15).Google Scholar

302 Granted, the narratives can be desiccated, the litigants almost dehumanized. John T. Noonan, Persons and Masks of the Law: Cardozo, Holmes, Jefferson, and Wythe as Makers of Masks (New York, 1976).Google Scholar

303 But see Kennedy, 32 J. Legal Educ. (cited in note 109).Google Scholar

304 An instance of this brought Langdell into disrepute with his students. Fessenden, 33 Harv. L. Reu. at 501 (cited in note 115).Google Scholar

305 Sandra Pearl Epstein, “Law at Berkeley: The History of Boalt Hall” at 228 (unpub. thesis, 1979) (in Boalt Hall Library).Google Scholar

306 On the enlarged influence of student opinion on law school teaching, see Kissam, Philip C., “The Decline of Law School Professionalism,” 134 U. Pa. L. Rev. 251, 276–80 (1986).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

307 Anthony D'Amato has pointed to this problem. “The Decline and Fall of Law Teaching in the Age of Student Consumerism,” 37 J. Legal Educ. 461 (1987). See also Kissam, 134 U. Pa. L. Reu. Google Scholar

308 The problem is addressed in Wildman, Stephanie M., “The Question of Silence: Techniques to Insure Full Class Participation,” 38 1. Legal Educ. 147 (1988).Google Scholar

309 Compare Hantzis, Catherine W., “Kingsfield and Kennedy: Reappraising the Male Model of Law School Teaching,” 38 J. Legal Educ. 155 (1988).Google Scholar

310 Carrington, 44 Kan. L. Rev. 1 (cited in note 142).Google Scholar

311 This fact has an independent political significance. The American Bar Association has for more than a century striven to match the American Medical Association in elevating professional standards. Because law plays so large a political role in America, they have not enjoyed the same support as has the AMA. Reed, Training (cited in note 7) was a report to the Camegie Foundation concluding that the kind of regulation of medical education achieved pursuant to the Foundation's recommendations would be inappropriate for law. There remains endemic pressure within the organized bar to make legal education much more expensive than it is. E.g., American Bar Association Section on Legal Education and Admission to the Bar Task Force on Law Schools and the Profession, Narrowing the Gap, Legal Education and Professional Development-An Educational Continuum (Chicago, 1992) (“Bar Task Force”). To the extent that such efforts succeed, access to legal education diminishes and the price of services rises.Google Scholar

312 “It does not take a very keen intelligence to see from the 19th century law reports and statute books and from what other documents reveal that in practice men in the United States always have adopted an instrumental view of the law.” Hurst, 1968 Wis. L. Rev. at 336-37 (cited in note 4).Google Scholar

313 For a somewhat contrary view that antebellum treatise writers had already attempted to depoliticize American judge-made law, see Horwitz, Transformations (cited in note 99).Google Scholar

314 Supra text at notes 179-81 & 215.Google Scholar

315 For a brief account of the evolution of this role, see Paul D. Carrington, “Crowded Dockets and the Courts of Appeals: The Threat to the Function of Review and the National Law,” 82 Harv. L. Rev. 542, 580-82 (1969).Google Scholar

316 See Paul D. Carrington, “The Function of the Civil Appeal: A Late Century View,” 38 S.C.L. Rev. 411, 416-28 (1987).Google Scholar

317 The “Brandeis brief' first appeared in Muller v. Oregon, 208 US. 412 (1908). This event confirmed Brandeis's belief that the Court was receptive to consideration of the social and political consequences of its decision. Even the most deplored decision of that era was explained in an opinion that can be condemned as Darwinist but not as blind formalism. Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905).Google Scholar

318 Paul D. Carrington, “Meaning and Professionalism,” 10 Const. Commentary 297 (1993).Google Scholar

319 See LaPiana, Logic and Experience 106-7 (cited in note 44).Google Scholar

320 See Carrington, 41 Duke L.J. at 753-54 (cited in note 60).Google Scholar

321 Story recorded his view in “Address before the Suffolk Bar” (1821) in William Story, ed., Miscellaneous Writings of Joseph Story (Boston, 1845); cf. David Hoffman, Syllabus of A Course of Lectures on Law v. (Baltimore, 1821); 1 James Kent, Commentaries on American Law 441 (1826).Google Scholar

322 Phelps, 1 Yale L.J. at 141 (cited in note 297).Google Scholar

323 The phrase is Clifford Geertz's. Local Knowledge in Interpretive Anthropology (New York, 1983).Google Scholar

324 The word is Karl Llewellyn's. The Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals 17-18 (Boston, 1960).Google Scholar

325 Supra text at note 184.Google Scholar

326 It was precisely for this reason that Langdell's method won enthusiastic applause from A. V. Dicey. See his “Training in English Law at Harvard,” 13 Harv. L. Rev. 412 (1899). Dicey was a believer in the supreme beneficence of judge-made law. Law of the Constitution (Oxford, 1885). And he saw little hope of good in anything that Parliament might be induced to enact. Law and Opinion in England (Oxford, 1905).Google Scholar

327 Federalist 10 (1788); Alexander M. Bickel, The Least Dangerous Branch: The Supreme Court at the Bar of Politics (Indianapolis, 1962).Google Scholar

328 410 U.S. 113 (1973).Google Scholar

329 “The Legacy of Holmes through English Eyes,” 63 B.U.L. Rev. 341 (1983); see also Patrick S. Atiyah & Robert S. Summers, Fan and Substance in Anglo-American Law: A Comparative Study in Legal Rearming, Legal Theory, and Legal Institution 134-50 (1987).Google Scholar

330 The availability of Parliament accounts for the appeal in England of Austin's vision of law. Austin was acutely interested in a theory of legislation, see Austin, Province of Jurisprudence Lectures 2-4 (cited in note 108). And Bentham seems to have been the progenitor of the movement to codify the common law. Charles M. Cook, The American Codification Movement 74-78, 97-104 (Westport, Conn., 1981).Google Scholar

331 19 How. 393 (1858).Google Scholar

332 On other causes of anti-intellectualism in law, see generally Francis A, Allen, Law, lntellect and Education (Ann Arbor, Mich., 1979).Google Scholar

333 See, e.g., Lesnick, Howard, “Legal Education's Concern with Justice: A Conversation with a Critic,” 35 J. Legal Educ. 414 (1985).Google Scholar

334 E.g. Elkins, 35 J. Legal Educ. (cited in note 296).Google Scholar

335 Kronman, Lost Lawyer 156 (cited in note 9).Google Scholar

336 Id. at 113.Google Scholar

337 This was the protest voiced by John Forrest Dillon in his presidential address attacking Langdell, “The True Professional Ideal,” 17 A.B.A. Rep. 420 (1894).Google Scholar

338 For a similar development of this point, see Kronman, Lost Lawyer 110-16, 155-60.Google Scholar

339 Address to Suffolk Bar Association, 5 Feb. 1885, quoted in Posner, Essential Holmes 223-24 (cited in note 97).Google Scholar

340 “The Use of Law Schools,” Harvard Law School, 5 Nov. 1886, at 37-38 (cited in note 221).Google Scholar

341 Compare “Beyond the Ordinary Religion,” 37 J. Legal Educ. 508 (1987).Google Scholar

342 “Teaching Values: A Dilemma,” 371. Legal Educ. 519 (1987).Google Scholar

343 “Reflections on the Religion Called Legal Education,” 37 J. Legal Educ. 522 (1987).Google Scholar

344 Kronman, Lost Lawyer 113-16 (cited in note 9).Google Scholar

345 Bamhizer, 40 Cleve. St. L. Reo. (cited in note 12); and see D'Amato, Anthony, “Rethinking Legal Education,” 74 Marq. L. Reu. 1 (1990).Google Scholar

346 Jefferson was as speculative as any member of his generation, yet he was intensely a pragmatist, and on that account it seems likely that he would have been attracted to the case method. Joyce O. Appleby, Liberalism and Republicanism in the Historical imagination 325-27 (Cambridge, Mass., 1992).Google Scholar

347 Kronman, Lost Lawyer 86 (cited in note 9).Google Scholar

348 The Morality of Law 1-32 (New Haven, Conn., 1964) (“Fuller, Morality of Law”).Google Scholar

349 For a literate and sensitive account of the difficulty of performing that judicial role in contemporary circumstances, see Frank M. Coffin, The Ways of a Judge: Reflections from the Appellate Bench (Boston, 1980).Google Scholar

350 Fuller, Morality of Law at 46-49.Google Scholar

351 Id. at 63-65.Google Scholar

352 Id. at 65-70.Google Scholar

353 Id. at 70-79.Google Scholar

354 Id. at 79-81.Google Scholar

355 Id. at 81-91.Google Scholar

356 Id. at 152-86.Google Scholar

357 Kronman suggests prudence, practical wisdom, and political fraternity as terms that are more precise and more suitable to contemporary discourse. Lost Lawyer 11-108 (cited in note 9).Google Scholar

358 It may have been with such principles in mind that Montesquieu (bk. V, ch. 3; cited in note 23) advised the 18th-century Revolutionaries to revere their law if they would maintain a republic; the wisdom of his counsel has not yet been disproved.Google Scholar

359 Kronman, Lost Lawyer 113.Google Scholar

360 “The Use of Law Schools” at 35, 39-40 (cited in note 221).Google Scholar

361 Id. at 38.Google Scholar

362 This is the point of Carrington, 41 Duke L.J. (cited in note 60).Google Scholar

363 Thayer, 7 Harv. L. Rev. (cited in note 145).Google Scholar

364 See generally Abel, American Lawyers (cited in note 131); Gordon, Robert, “The Independence of Lawyers,” 68 B.U.L. Rev. 1 (1988); David Luban, Lawyers and Justice: An Ethical Study (Princeton, N.J., 1988).Google Scholar

365 I take this as the central point of Kronman's book. Lost Lawyer (cited in note 9). He identifies the academic movements to economic analysis of law and to critical legal studies as “neo-Langdellian” initiatives animated by the desire to liberate legal scholarship from the need to cope with practical realities. Id. at 225-70. Compare Robert Post, “Lani Guinier, Joseph Biden, and the Vocation of Legal Scholarship,” 11 Const. Commentary 185, 193 (1994).Google Scholar

366 For an authoritative statement that this is occurring see Bar Task Force (cited in note 311). As Grey, 45 U. Pitt. L. Rev. at 53 (cited in note 6), among others observes, the growing disjunction is associated with a reduction of the “gap between legal scholarship and the rest of the intellectual world.”Google Scholar

367 For fuller development of this observation, see Edwards, Harry T., “The Growing Disjunction Between Legal Education and the Legal Profession,” 91 Mich. L. Rev. 34 (1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar