Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T22:16:31.207Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Forgiveness: An important principle in medical ethics and palliative care?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 August 2022

Aldis H. Petriceks*
Affiliation:
Harvard Medical School, Boston, MA Columbia University Mailman School of Public Health, New York, NY
*
Author for correspondence: Aldis H. Petriceks, Harvard Medical School, 25 Shattuck St, Boston, MA 02115, USA. E-mail: aldis_petriceks@hms.harvard.edu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Essay/Personal Reflection
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

During my first year of medical school, I participated in a course where students gathered to discuss, among other topics, medical ethics. At the time, my classmates and I were introduced to four core principles of the field: beneficence, nonmaleficence, autonomy, and justice. We employed these principles, implicitly or explicitly, while advocating for our stances on a wide range of ethical subjects. I am grateful for the clarity provided by these principles and for the rigor demonstrated by my classmates and instructors.

But years later, having finished a second edition of that course as well as my third year of medical school, I am struck by something that received much less attention during my introduction to medical ethics: forgiveness. I am now in the second half of my undergraduate medical training, but already I have seen the tremendous toll enacted on my peers in their efforts to live up to professional ideals. Those ideals are not, by any means, wrong or misplaced, but it seems safe to suggest that they are not often taught with a view to the ways in which even the most ideal professionals are, in the end, still people. To err is human, the saying goes; but to forgive, divine. Anyone knows this who does enough living. And so, as I reflect on the rates of burnout in medicine and on the fact that, despite our best efforts, we still err, I wonder whether, among all our ethical principles, we might need a greater focus on this virtue (Rotenstein et al., Reference Rotenstein, Torre and Ramos2018).

In the remainder of this essay, I will provide a brief historical background to the idea of forgiveness in medical ethics; discuss why forgiveness should matter to clinicians and ethicists; and argue for its special importance in palliative care. I will not attempt to systematically place forgiveness within a particular set or hierarchy of ethical principles. My hope is simply that palliative care clinicians will take an interest in forgiveness as an important aspect of medical ethics and agree that forgiveness — for clinicians, for patients, and for our imperfect world and health care system — may have an explicit place wherever our professional ethics are discussed.

In a widely read article from 1984, Dr. David Hilfiker describes several medical errors made over the course of his career (Hilfiker, Reference Hilfiker1984). In his reflection, Hilfiker is not primarily interested in the ethical questions with which my classmates and I have grappled in class: Should one always disclose medical error? Should one admit to being personally at fault when errors occur? Hilfiker is more interested in forgiveness itself, and these are not questions about forgiveness but about right and wrong. Hilfiker, who seems quite grounded in his sense of right and wrong, is wrestling with the barriers that prevent us from talking frankly about our mistakes, and the guilt that accumulates behind those barriers.

In a more recent article, Drs. Delbanco and Bell write that clinicians “often suffer alone after making mistakes, agonizing over the harm they have caused, the loss of their patients’ trust, the loss of their colleagues’ respect, their diminished self-confidence, and the potential effects of the error on their careers” (Delbanco and Bell, Reference Delbanco and Bell2007). They argue that the first steps toward resolving such agony “might include creating a structured curricula” and “removing stigma from transparent reporting systems” (Delbanco and Bell, Reference Delbanco and Bell2007). These recommendations do move some distance toward addressing the problems raised by Hilfiker, but in all their language of structure, systems, and experts, there remains something missing from the healing he describes.

Forgiveness might be what is needed. In their study on the process of coping with medical error, Plews-Ogan et al. find forgiveness to be among several core themes that help physicians “cope positively” with their mistakes (Plews-Ogan et al., Reference Plews-Ogan, May and Owens2016). In a recent essay, the Harvard epidemiologist, Dr. Tyler VanderWeele even argues that forgiveness “is important to public health” (VanderWeele, Reference VanderWeele2018). But forgiveness, in these examples, is not mere excuse or pardon. To forgive “is neither amnesiac nor an exacting of payment” but “a dynamic recovery of what is lost”: in this case, the recovery of actual wholeness from the lost ideals of ourselves as perfect or perfectible individuals (Jones, Reference Jones2013). Far from compromising the rest of medical ethics, forgiveness grounds our abstract principles in the raw matter of reality.

In medical training and professional development, such grounding could involve the emphasis that all of us, over the course of our careers, will make mistakes; and this emphasis would, ideally, yield itself to a common culture in which each of us feels confident in attaining forgiveness, both personal and professional, when needed. To begin fostering such a culture, ethical training in medical school, residency, fellowship, and continuing medical education could include assigned readings about the philosophical, psychological, and spiritual traditions surrounding forgiveness: the philosophical difference, for instance, between forgiveness and excuse; the psychological and neuroscientific effects of forgiveness; and the spiritual traditions that treat forgiveness not as a palliative measure for uniquely bad people but as the natural response to our imperfect human conditions. Students and practitioners could also read about, and participate in, the growing literature on forgiveness and health. Finally, explicit policies of forgiveness could be developed in our hospitals and institutions, and communities created in which clinicians offer forgiveness to one another as individuals or in small groups.

The benefits of forgiveness are not restricted to professional circles. In their writing on medical error, Delbanco and Bell suggest that patients and families suffer when the natural process of apology and forgiveness is stifled by institutional policy or the fear of professional repercussions. When providers do not seek forgiveness — whether following medical error or a lapse in ethical judgement — patients and families may go without deeply desired validation and emotional comfort: “What we needed was for someone to reach out and connect with us in human terms” (Delbanco and Bell, Reference Delbanco and Bell2007). The act of disclosure, apology, and asking for forgiveness provides substantive opportunity for such human connection.

We should note, also, that forgiveness offers its own sort of ethical training. Dr. Farr Curlin, in his review of Dr. Nancy Berlinger's book After Harm: Medical Error and the Ethics of Forgiveness, highlights “a complex challenge for the medical profession: how to form medical professionals who will, in the face of real threats to their own reputations, pride, and financial security, willingly disclose medical harm, [apologize] for their errors, and take concrete steps to fairly compensate patients for what has been lost” (Curlin, Reference Curlin2005). This challenge is at least partly answered by a collective focus on forgiveness, because an awareness of forgiveness and its accessibility can (in ways that ethical deliberation on its own cannot) offer the security to openly acknowledge one's mistakes and correct them in the company of others. As VanderWeele suggests, forgiveness offers us not a free pass on ethical judgement, but rather a “space to change” into continually wiser clinicians and people (VanderWeele, Reference VanderWeele2018).

Before concluding, I want to touch on the unique place of palliative care in all this. Palliative care clinicians are, for the most part, familiar with moral injury and moral distress, given the deep ethical and spiritual contexts in which their work takes place (Rushton et al., Reference Rushton, Kaszniak and Halifax2013). In turn, the specialty is no stranger to forgiveness (Leget, Reference Leget2020). Because of this deep connection, I argue that palliative care could lead the medical profession in a deeper exploration of forgiveness within its academic literature and clinical training. Judging from the rich philosophical discourses on forgiveness, palliative care clinician–ethicists would fill a large gap in the medically facing scholarship by examining opportunities for, and obstructions to, forgiveness in modern health care (Hughes and Warmke, Reference Hughes and Warmke2017). How can clinicians and patients seek and receive forgiveness? How do our caregiving institutions facilitate and block this process? How might we train our medical students, residents, and fellows to promote a culture of openness and reconciliation? These are exciting and important questions, and I think that palliative care clinicians would have substantial credibility in answering them.

If the stated aim of our ethics is primarily to do good, to avoid harm, to honor individual decision-making, and to pursue justice, we will eventually find ourselves having failed that aim one way or another, and without forgiveness will be faced with the real distance between our professional philosophies and our historical realities. I would like to see forgiveness integrated throughout training and practice in medical ethics: emphasized by leaders, advocated for in our discourse, and practiced between one another. I think that palliative care clinicians are well-positioned to spark this integration — one that seems, to me, the best way to healing.

Acknowledgment

The author is thankful for the education in medical ethics provided by their institution, its instructors, and students.

Conflict of interest

There are no conflicts of interest.

References

Curlin, FA (2005) After harm: Medical error and the ethics of forgiveness. BMJ 331. doi:10.5840/jsce200828136CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delbanco, T and Bell, SK (2007) Guilty, afraid, and alone — struggling with medical error. New England Journal of Medicine 357(17), 16821683. doi:10.1056/nejmp078104CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hilfiker, D (1984) Facing our mistakes. New England Journal of Medicine 310(2), 118122. doi:10.1056/NEJM198401123100211CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hughes, PM and Warmke, B (2017). Forgiveness. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/forgiveness/ (accessed 9 July 2022).Google Scholar
Jones, H (2013) In solitude for company: Forgiveness, memory, and depth in W.H. Auden's the sea and the mirror. Literature and Theology 27(4), 414425. doi:10.1093/litthe/frt039CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leget, C (2020) Forgiveness and reconciliation in palliative care: The gap between the psychological and moral approaches. Religions 11(440), 110. doi:10.3390/rel11090440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plews-Ogan, M, May, N, Owens, J, et al. (2016) Wisdom in medicine: What helps physicians after a medical error? Academic Medicine 91(2), 233241. doi:10.1097/ACM.0000000000000886CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rotenstein, LS, Torre, M, Ramos, MA, et al. (2018) Prevalence of burnout among physicians. JAMA 320(11), 1131. doi:10.1001/jama.2018.12777CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rushton, CH, Kaszniak, AW and Halifax, JS (2013) A framework for understanding moral distress among palliative care clinicians. Journal of Palliative Medicine 16(9), 10741079. doi:10.1089/jpm.2012.0490CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
VanderWeele, TJ (2018) Is forgiveness a public health issue? American Journal of Public Health 108(2), 189190. doi:10.2105/AJPH.2017.304210CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed