Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-94fs2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T13:27:26.129Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Confutation of Convergent Realism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Larry Laudan*
Affiliation:
University of Pittsburgh

Abstract

This essay contains a partial exploration of some key concepts associated with the epistemology of realist philosophies of science. It shows that neither reference nor approximate truth will do the explanatory jobs that realists expect of them. Equally, several widely-held realist theses about the nature of inter-theoretic relations and scientific progress are scrutinized and found wanting. Finally, it is argued that the history of science, far from confirming scientific realism, decisively confutes several extant versions of avowedly ‘naturalistic’ forms of scientific realism.

The positive argument for realism is that it is the only philosophy that doesn't make the success of science a miracle.

-H. Putnam (1975)

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1981 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am indebted to all of the following for clarifying my ideas on these issues and for saving me from some serious errors: Peter Achinstein, Richard Burian, Clark Glymour, Adolf Grünbaum, Gary Gutting, Allen Janis, Lorenz Krüger, James Lennox, Andrew Lugg, Peter Machamer, Nancy Maull, Ernan McMullin, Ilkka Niiniluoto, Nicholas Rescher, Ken Schaffner, John Worrall, Steven Wykstra.

References

Boyd, R. (1973), “Realism, Underdetermination, and a Causal Theory of Evidence”, Noûs 7: 112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bunge, M. (1970), “Problems Concerning Intertheory Relations”, Weingartner, P. and Zecha, G. (eds.), Induction, Physics and Ethics: 285315. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, A. (1967), “Consistency, Derivability and Scientific Change”, Journal of Philosophy 64: 231ff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grünbaum, Adolf (1976), “Can a Theory Answer More Questions than One of its Rivals?”, British Journal for Philosophy of Science 27: 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hooker, Clifford (1974), “Systematic Realism”, Synthese 26: 409497.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koertge, N. (1973), “Theory Change in Science”, Pearce, G. and Maynard, P. (eds.), Conceptual Change: 167198. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kordig, C. (1971), “Scientific Transitions, Meaning Invariance, and Derivability”, Southern Journal of Philosophy: 119125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krajewski, W. (1977), Correspondence Principle and Growth of Science. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1976), “Two Dogmas of Methodology”, Philosophy of Science 43: 467472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1977), Progress and its Problems. California: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1978), “Ex-Huming Hacking”, Erkenntnis 13: 417435.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Margenau, H. (1950), The Nature of Physical Reality. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1970), “The History and Philosophy of Science: A Taxonomy”, Stuewer, R. (ed.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science V: 1267. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Newton-Smith, W. (1978), “The Underdetermination of Theories by Data”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society: 7191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newton-Smith, W. (forthcoming), “In Defense of Truth”.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, Ilkka (1977), “On the Truthlikeness of Generalizations”, Butts, R. and Hintikka, J. (eds.), Basic Problems in Methodology and Linguistics: 121147. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niiniluoto, Ilkka (1980), “Scientific Progress”, Synthese 45: 427–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. (1959), Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Basic Books.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. (1963), Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1972), Objective Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Post, H. R. (1971), “Correspondence, Invariance and Heuristics: In Praise of Conservative Induction”, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 2: 213255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975), Mathematics, Matter and Method, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1978), Meaning and the Moral Sciences. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. (1963), Science, Perception and Reality. New York: The Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Sklar, L. (1967), “Types of Inter-Theoretic Reductions”, British Journal for Philosophy of Science 18: 190224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Szumilewicz, I. (1977), “Incommensurability and the Rationality of the Development of Science”, British Journal for Philosophy of Science 28: 348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watkins, John (1978), “Corroboration and the Problem of Content-Comparison”, Radnitzky and Andersson (eds.), Progress and Rationality in Science: 339378. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar