Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T23:14:43.006Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Mixed-Effects Modeling and Nonreductive Explanation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

This essay considers a mixed-effects modeling practice and its implications for the philosophical debate surrounding reductive explanation. Mixed-effects modeling is a species of the multilevel modeling practice, where a single model incorporates simultaneously two (or even more) levels of explanatory variables to explain a phenomenon of interest. I argue that this practice makes the position of explanatory reductionism held by many philosophers untenable because it violates two central tenets of explanatory reductionism: single-level preference and lower-level obsession.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am thankful to Xiang Huang, Chuang Liu, and Wei Wang for comments on earlier drafts of this article. This research was supported by the Ministry of Education of China’s Humanities and Social Sciences Youth Fund.

References

Batterman, Robert. 2013. “The ‘Tyranny of Scales.’” In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Physics, ed. Batterman, Robert, 255–86. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Batterman, Robert. 2018. “Autonomy of Theories: An Explanatory Problem.” Noûs 52 (4): 858–73..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, William. 2010. “The Downs and Ups of Mechanistic Research: Circadian Rhythm Research as an Exemplar.” Erkenntnis 73:313–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, William. 2017. “Explicating Top-Down Causation Using Networks and Dynamics.” Philosophy of Science 84:253–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bickle, John. 2003. Philosophy and Neuroscience: A Ruthlessly Reductive Account. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bourrat, Pierrick. 2016. “Generalizing Contextual Analysis.” Acta Biotheoretica 64 (2): 197217..CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brigandt, Ingo. 2010. “Beyond Reductionism and Pluralism: Toward an Epistemology of Explanatory Integration in Biology.” Erkenntnis 73 (3): 295311..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brigandt, Ingo. 2013a. “Explanation in Biology: Reduction, Pluralism, and Explanatory Aims.” Science and Education 22:6991.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brigandt, Ingo. 2013b. “Integration in Biology: Philosophical Perspectives on the Dynamics of Interdisciplinarity.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 44:461–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, Carl. 2007. Explaining the Brain: Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, Carl, and Bechtel, William. 2007. “Top-Down Causation without Top-Down Causes.” Biology and Philosophy 22:547–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freedman, David. 1999. “Ecological Inference and the Ecological Fallacy.” In International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, Vol. 6, ed. Smelser, Neil and Baltes, Paul, 4027–30. New York: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Green, Sara. 2013. “When One Model Isn’t Enough: Combining Epistemic Tools in Systems Biology.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 44:170–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, Sara, and Batterman, Robert. 2017. “Biology Meets Physics: Reductionism and Multi-Scale Modeling of Morphogenesis.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 61:2034.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gross, Fridolin, and Green, Sara. 2017. “The Sum of the Parts: Large-Scale Modeling in Systems Biology.” Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology 9 (10).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heck, Ronald, and Thomas, Scott. 2015. An Introduction to Multilevel Modeling Techniques. 3rd ed. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David. 1972. “Reductionism in Genetics: Biology or Philosophy?Philosophy of Science 39 (4): 491–99..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hüttemann, Andreas, and Love, Alan. 2011. “Aspects of Reductive Explanation in Biological Science: Intrinsicality, Fundamentality, and Temporality.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 62 (3): 519–49..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaiser, Marie. 2015. Reductive Explanation in the Biological Sciences. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knuuttila, Tarja. 2011. “Modelling and Representing: An Artefactual Approach to Model-Based Representation.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A 42:262–71.Google Scholar
Luke, Douglas. 2004. Multilevel Modeling. London: Sage.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maxwell, Sophie, Reynolds, Katherine, Lee, Eunro, Subasic, Emina, and Bromhead, David. 2017. “The Impact of School Climate and School Identification on Academic Achievement: Multilevel Modeling with Student and Teacher Data.” Frontiers in Psychology 8:2069.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mitchell, Sandra. 2003. Biological Complexity and Integrative Pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, Sandra. 2009. Unsimple Truths: Science, Complexity, and Policy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, Sandra, and Gronenborn, Angela. 2017. “After Fifty Years, Why Are Protein X-Ray Crystallographers Still in Business?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 68 (3): 703–23..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, Celeste M., and Bissell, Mina J.. 2006. “Of Extracellular Matrix, Scaffolds, and Signaling: Tissue Architecture Regulates Development, Homeostasis, and Cancer.” Annual Review of Cell and Developmental Biology 22:287309.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nezlek, John. 2008. “An Introduction to Multilevel Modeling for Social and Personality Psychology.” Social and Personality Psychology Compass 2 (2): 842–60..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Noble, Daniel. 2012. “A Theory of Biological Relativity: No Privileged Level of Causation.” Interface Focus 2 (1): 5564..CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
O’Malley, Maureen A., Brigandt, Ingo, Love, Alan C., Crawford, John W., Gilbert, Jack A., Knight, Rob, Mitchell, Sandra D., and Rohwer, Forest. 2014. “Multilevel Research Strategies and Biological Systems.” Philosophy of Science 81:811–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, Alex. 2006. Darwinian Reductionism; or, How to Stop Worrying and Love Molecular Biology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarkar, Sahotra. 1998. Genetics and Reductionism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schagen, I. P. 1990. “Analysis of the Effects of School Variables Using Multilevel Models.” Educational Studies 16:6173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shawky, Joseph, and Davidson, Lance. 2015. “Tissue Mechanics and Adhesion during Embryo Development.” Developmental Biology 401 (1): 152–64..CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sober, Elliot. 1999. “The Multiple Realizability Argument against Reductionism.” Philosophy of Science 66:542–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wang, Yau-De, and Hsieh, Hui-Hsien. 2012. “Toward a Better Understanding of the Link between Ethical Climate and Job Satisfaction: A Multilevel Analysis.” Journal of Business Ethics 105:535–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waters, C. Kenneth. 2008. “Beyond Theoretical Reduction and Layer-Cake Antireduction: How DNA Retooled Genetics and Transformed Biological Practice.” In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Biology, ed. Ruse, Michael, 238–62. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weber, Marcel. 2005. Philosophy of Experimental Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar