Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T04:37:07.590Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Scientific Discovery and Maxwell's Kinetic Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Peter Achinstein*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, The Johns Hopkins University

Abstract

By reference to Maxwell's kinetic theory, one feature of hypothetico-deductivism is defended. A scientist need make no inference to a hypothesis when he first proposes it. He may have no reason at all for thinking it is true. Yet it may be worth considering. In developing his kinetic theory there were central assumptions Maxwell made (for example, that molecules are spherical, that they exert contact forces, and that their motion is linear) that he had no reason to believe true. In this paper I develop a position that explains why they were worth considering, and that rejects the retroductive position that a hypothesis is worth considering when, if true, it would explain the observed data.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1987 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This work was supported by the National Endowment for the Humanities. For very helpful suggestions I am indebted to Gary Hatfield and Michael Liston.

References

Achinstein, P. (1983), The Nature of Explanation. New York: Oxford.Google Scholar
Achinstein, P. (1985), “The Method of Hypothesis: What Is It Supposed to Do and Can It Do It?”, in Achinstein, P. and Hannaway, O. (eds.), Observation, Experiment and Hypothesis in Modern Physical Science. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT, pp. 127–145.Google Scholar
Achinstein, P. (1986), “Theoretical Derivations”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 17: 375–414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feynman, R. (1965), The Character of Physical Law. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT.Google Scholar
Hanson, N. R. (1958), Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge, England: Cambridge.Google Scholar
Hanson, N. R. (1983), “The Logic of Discovery”, in Achinstein, P. (ed.), The Concept of Evidence. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 5362.Google Scholar
Hesse, M. (1974), The Structure of Scientific Inference. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joule, J. (1965), “On Matter, Living Force, and Heat”, in Brush, S. G. (ed.), Kinetic Theory, vol. I. Oxford: Pergamon Press, pp. 7888.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maxwell, J. C. (1965), Scientific Papers. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Maxwell, J. C. (1875), Theory of Heat. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.Google Scholar
McLaughlin, R. (1982), “Invention and Appraisal”, in McLaughlin, R. (ed.), What? Where? When? Why? Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 69100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peirce, C. (1960), Collected Papers. Edited by Hartshorne, C. and Weiss, P. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard.Google Scholar