Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T04:19:26.902Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Trouble with Homunculus Theories

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Joseph Margolis*
Affiliation:
Temple University

Abstract

The so-called post-Wittgensteinian Oxford philosophers are often criticized not only for failing to provide for the causal explanation of human behavior and psychological states, but also for failing to recognize that psychological explanations require appeal to sub-personal or molecular processes. Three strategies accommodating this criticism appear in so-called homunculus theories and include: (1) that the sub-systems be assigned intentional or informational content purely heuristically; (2) that the intentional or informational content of molar states be analyzed without remainder in terms of molecular processing; (3) that the entire or salient range of mental or informational molar states be accessible at the molecular level, or vice versa. Option (2) proves to be the most radical and is favored by Dennett. (1) relevantly requires a reduction of the intentional. (3) is illustrated in various ways by the views of Freud, Chomsky, Fodor. (2) is shown to depend on (1) or to be idle; and (3) embraces at least in part an appeal to molar-level explanation. The argument developed attempts to show the sense in which discourse about molar and molecular-level phenomena in the psychological context is fundamentally different from macroscopic and microtheoretical-level discourse about physical phenomena. The conclusion drawn is that neither a molar nor a sub-personal level theory is suitably explanatory in the psychological sense: a psychological theory is committed rather to a set of sub-personal components of such systems, that serve to explain molar phenomena.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1980

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Brentano, F. (1973), “The Distinction between Mental and Physical Phenomena” in Psychology From an Empirical Standpoint; Oskar Kraus and Linda L. McAlister (eds.), English edition. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Chisholm, R. (1967), “On Some Psychological Concepts and the ‘Logic’ of Intentionality,” in Hector-Neri Castaneda (comp.), Intentionality, Minds and Perception. Detroit: Wayne State University Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N (1957), Syntactic Structures, 's-Gravehage: Mouton, ch. 3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. (1959), “Review of B. F. Skinner,” Verbal Behavior, Language 35.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. (1972), Language and Mind (revised), New York: Harcourt Brace and Javanovich.Google Scholar
Cornman, J. (1962), “The Intentional and the Intensional,” Philosophical Quarterly 12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cornman, J. (1968a), “On the Elimination of ‘Sensations’ and Sensations,” Review of Metaphysics 22.Google Scholar
Cornman, J. (1968b), “Mental Terms, Theoretical Terms and Materialism,” Philosophy of Science 34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1963), “Actions, Reasons, and Causes,” Journal of Philosophy 60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. (1969), Content and Consciousness., London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1978), “A Cure for the Common Code?,” “Artificial Intelligence as Philosophy and Psychology,” “Intentional Systems (pp. 3–4, 7),” “Toward a Cognitive Theory of Consciousness,” in Brainstorms. Montgomery, VT.: Bradford Books.Google Scholar
Feigl, H. (1967), The “Mental” and the “Physical”; The Essay and a Postscript. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. (1963), “Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem,” Review of Metaphysics 17.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1975), The Language of Thought, New York: Thomas Y. Crowell.Google Scholar
Freud, S. (1961), The Ego and the Id, Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, translated by Strachey, James, et al., Vol. 19. London: The Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psychoanalysis.Google Scholar
Freud, S. (1962), The Interpretation of Dreams, Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Vol. 5, corrected.Google Scholar
Kenny, A. J. P. (1963), Action, Emotion and Will in Holland's “Studies in Philosophical Psychology.” London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, A. (1958), The Unconscious, in Holland's “Studies in Philosophical Psychology,” London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Margolis, J. (1977), “The Stubborn Opacity of Belief Contexts” in Theoria 43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Margolis, J. (1978a), Persons and Minds, Dordrecht: Reidel, ch. 13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Margolis, J. (1978b), “Reconciling Freud's Scientific Project and Psychoanalysis” in Englehardt, H. Tristram Jr. and Cailhan, Daniel (eds.), Morals, Science and Sociality, The Foundations of Ethics and Its Relationship to Science Vol. III. Hastings-on-Hudson: Hastings Institute.Google Scholar
Margolis, J. (forth.), “The Concept of Consciousness,” Philosophic Exchange.Google Scholar
Melden, A. I. (1961), Free Action in Holland's “Studies in Philosophical Psychology,” London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Noble, D. (1966–67), “Charles Taylor on Teleological Explanation,” Analysis 27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peters, R. S. (1958), The Concept of Motivation in Holland's “Studies in Philosophical Psychology,” London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1960), Word and Object, Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. (1963), “Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man” in Science, Perception and Reality. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Skinner, B. F. (1953), Science and Human Behavior, New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Skinner, B. F. (1957), Verbal Behavior, New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, C. (1964), The Explanation of Behavior in Holland's “Studies in Philosophical Psychology.” London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Winch, P. (1958), The Idea of a Social Science in Holland's “Studies in Philosophical Psychology.”Google Scholar
Woodfield, A. (1976), Teleology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar