Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T12:17:24.383Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chance and Natural Selection

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

John Beatty*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Arizona State University

Abstract

Among the liveliest disputes in evolutionary biology today are disputes concerning the role of chance in evolution—more specifically, disputes concerning the relative evolutionary importance of natural selection vs. so-called “random drift”. The following discussion is an attempt to sort out some of the broad issues involved in those disputes. In the first half of this paper, I try to explain the differences between evolution by natural selection and evolution by random drift. On some common construals of “natural selection”, those two modes of evolution are completely indistinguishable. Even on a proper construal of “natural selection”, it is difficult to distinguish between the “improbable results of natural selection” and evolution by random drift.

In the second half of this paper, I discuss the variety of positions taken by evolutionists with respect to the evolutionary importance of random drift vs. natural selection. I will then consider the variety of issues in question in terms of a conceptual distinction often used to describe the rise of probabilistic thinking in the sciences. I will argue, in particular, that what is going on here is not, as might appear at first sight, just another dispute about the desirability of “stochastic” vs. “deterministic” theories. Modern evolutionists do not argue so much about whether evolution is stochastic, but about how stochastic it is.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1984

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This article was written during the academic year 1982–1983, while I was a fellow at the Center for Interdisciplinary Research at the University of Bielefeld, in Bielefeld, West Germany. I was part of a group research project, organized by Lorenz Krüger, which studied the rise and role of probabilistic thinking in the sciences since 1800. I am very grateful to the staff of the Center, the faculty of the University of Bielefeld, and of course my fellow probabilists for their thoughts and for their friendship.

Robert Brandon, Lorenz Krüger, Elliott Sober, Kenneth Waters, and the referees of Philosophy of Science all helped me to clarify the issues discussed here. The residual unclarity distinguishes my contributions from theirs. Some of the residual unclarity must be attributed to Jonathan Hodge's and Alexander Rosenberg's critiques of the notion of “fitness” used here. Their thoughtful critiques have, I must admit, left me a bit confused about my position.

References

Brandon, R. (1978), “Adaptation and Evolutionary Theory”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 9: 181200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandon, R. (1978), “Evolution”, Philosophy of Science 45: 96109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burian, R. (1983), “Adaptation”, in M. Grene (ed.), Dimensions of Darwinism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Buzzati-Traverso, A., Jucci, C. and Timofeef-Ressovsky, N. W. (1938), “Genetics of Populations”, Ricerca Scientifica, Year 9, Vol. 1.Google Scholar
Cain, A. J. (1979), “Introduction to General Discussion”, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B205: 599604.Google Scholar
Crow, J. F. and Kimura, M. (1970), An Introduction to Population Genetics Theory. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1839), “N Notebook”, in H. E. Gruber and P. H. Barrett, Darwin on Man. New York: Dutton, 1974.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1859), On the Origin of Species. London: Murray. Cambridge: Harvard University Press (facsimile edition), 1959.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. (1887), The Variation of Animals and Plants under Domestication, 2nd ed. (2 vols.). New York: Appleton.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, F. (ed.) (1887), The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin (3 vols.). London: Murray.Google Scholar
Diver, C. (1940), “The Problem of Closely Related Snails Living in the Same Area”, in J. S. Huxley (ed.), The New Systematics. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Dobzhansky, T. (1937), Genetics and the Origin of Species. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Dobzhansky, T. (1970), Genetics of the Evolutionary Process. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Dobzhansky, T. and Pavlovsky, O. (1957), “An Experimental Study of Interaction Between Genetic Drift and Natural Selection”, Evolution 11: 311319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dubinin, N. P. and Romaschoff, D. D. (1932), “The Genetic Structure of Species and their Evolution” (in Russian). Biologichesky Zhurnal 1: 5295.Google Scholar
Eigen, M. and Winkler, R. (1981), Laws of the Game. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Fisher, R. A. (1930), The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, R. A. and Ford, E. B. (1950), “The ‘Sewall Wright Effect‘”, Heredity 4: 117119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Futuyma, D. J. (1979), Evolutionary Biology. Sunderland, Massachusetts: Sinauer.Google Scholar
Ghiselin, M. T. (1969), The Triumph of the Darwinian Method. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Gould, S. J. (1980), “Is a New and General Theory of Evolution Emerging?Paleobiology 6: 119130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, S. J. and Lewontin, R. C. (1979), “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme”, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B205: 581598.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1965), Logic of Statistical Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hagedoorn, A. L. and Hagedoorn, A. C. (1921), The Relative Value of the Processes Causing Evolution. The Hague: Nijoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodge, J. and Kohn, D. (Forthcoming), “The Immediate Origins of the Theory of Natural Selection”, in D. Kohn (ed.), The Darwinian Heritage: A Centennial Retrospect. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kerr, W. E. and Wright, S. (1954), “Experimental Studies of the Distribution of Gene Frequencies in Very Small Populations of Drosophila melanogaster”, Evolution 8: 172177.Google Scholar
Kimura, M. (1981), “Possibility of Extensive Neutral Evolution under Stabilizing Selection with Special Reference to Non-Random Usage of Synonymous Codons”, Journal of Molecular Evolution 17: 121122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimura, M. (1982), “The Neutral Theory as a Basis for Understanding the Mechanism of Evolution and Variation at the Molecular Level”, in M. Kimura (ed.), Molecular Evolution, Protein Polymorphism, and the Neutral Theory. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
King, J. L. and Jukes, T. H. (1969), “Non-Darwinian Evolution”, Science 164: 788798.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lamotte, M. (1959), “Polymorphism of Natural Populations of Cepaea nemoralis”, Cold Spring Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology 24: 6584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lerner, I. M. (1958), The Genetic Basis of Selection. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Lewontin, R. C. (1974), The Genetic Basis of Evolutionary Change. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Mettler, L. E. and Gregg, T. G. (1969), Population Genetics and Evolution. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Mills, S. K. and Beatty, J. (1979), “A Propensity Interpretation of Fitness”, Philosophy of Science 46: 263286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nei, M. (1975), Molecular Population Genetics and Evolution. New York: Elsevier.Google ScholarPubMed
Peirce, C. (1893), “Evolutionary Love”, Monist 3: 176200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Provine, W. B. (1971), The Origins of Theoretical Population Genetics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Provine, W. B. (Forthcoming), Sewall Wright: Geneticist and Evolutionist. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Roughgarden, J. (1979), Theory of Population Genetics and Evolutionary Ecology: An Introduction. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Schweber, S. (1982), “Aspects of Probabilistic Thought in Great Britain During the Nineteenth Century: Darwin and Maxwell”, in A. Shimony and H. Feshback (eds.), Physics and Natural Philosophy. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sheppard, P. M. (1967), Natural Selection and Heredity. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Sheynin, O. B. (1980), “On the History of the Statistical Method in Biology”, Archive for History of the Exact Sciences 22: 323371.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Skyrms, B. (1966), Choice and Chance. Belmont, California: Dickenson.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1980), “Evolutionary Theory and the Ontological Status of Properties”, Philosophical Studies 40: 147161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sulloway, F. J. (1979), “Geographical Isolation in Darwin's Thinking: The Vicissitudes of a Crucial Idea”, Studies in the History of Biology 3: 2365.Google Scholar
Timofeef-Ressovsky, N. W. (1940), “Mutations and Geographical Variation”, in J. S. Huxley (ed.), The New Systematics. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Waddington, C. H. (1968), “The Basic Ideas of Biology”, Towards a Theoretical Biology 1. Chicago: Aldine Publishing Company, pp. 141.Google Scholar
Wilson, E. O. and Bossert, W. H. (1971), A Primer of Population Biology. Sunderland, Massachusetts: Sinauer.Google Scholar
Wilson, E. O. (1975), Sociobiology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, S. (1930), “The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection: A Review”, Journal of Heredity 21: 349356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, S. (1931), “Evolution in Mendelian Populations”, Genetics 16: 97159.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wright, S. (1932), “The Roles of Mutation, Inbreeding, Crossbreeding, and Selection in Evolution”, Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress of Genetics 1: 356366.Google Scholar
Wright, S. (1940), “The Statistical Consequences of Mendelian Heredity in Relation to Speciation”, in J. S. Huxley (ed.), The New Systematics. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Wright, S. (1948), “On the Roles of Directed and Random Changes in Gene Frequency in the Genetics of Populations”, Evolution 2: 279294.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed