Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T03:36:57.006Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Darwinian Algorithms and Indexical Representation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Murray Clarke*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy Concordia University
*
Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, Concordia University, 7141 Sherbrooke Street West, Montreal, Quebec, Canada, H4B 1R6.

Abstract

In this paper, I argue that accurate indexical representations have been crucial for the survival and reproduction of homo sapiens sapiens. Specifically, I want to suggest that reliable processes have been selected for because of their indirect, but close, connection to true belief during the Pleistocene hunter-gatherer period of our ancestral history. True beliefs are not heritable, reliable processes are heritable. Those reliable processes connected with reasoning take the form of Darwinian Algorithms: a plethora of specialized, domain-specific inference rules designed to solve specific, recurrent, adaptive problems in social exchange contexts. Humans do not reason logically, but adaptively.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1996 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Earlier versions of this paper were read at the Canadian Society for the History and Philosophy of Science Annual Meetings and at the Canadian Philosophical Association Annual Meetings. I would like to thank Martin Pate, Elliot Sober, Stephen Stich, Evan Thompson, and audiences at the meetings mentioned for discussion and suggestions. For my parents, Ethel and William Clarke, thanks for support on both sides of the nature/nurture divide.

References

Anderson, J. (1985), Cognitive Psychology and Its Implications 2nd edition. New York: W. H. Freeman.Google Scholar
Clarke, M. (1986a), “Doxastic Voluntarism and Forced Belief, Philosophical Studies 50: 3951.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, J. (1986b), “Reliability and Two Kinds of Epistemic Justification”, in Garver, N. and Hare, P. (eds.), Naturalism and Rationality. Buffalo: Prometheus Press, pp. 159170.Google Scholar
Anderson, J. (1990), “Epistemic Norms and Evolutionary Success”, Synthese 85: 231244.Google Scholar
Anderson, J. (1996), “Natural Selection and Indexical Representation”, in Cohen, R. S. and Marion, M., (eds.), Logic and Philosophy of Science in Quebec, Volume II, in Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Netherlands: Reidel Publishing Company, pp. 5362.Google Scholar
Cosmides, I. (1989), “The Logic of Social Exchange: Has Natural Selection Shaped How Humans Reason? Studies with the Wason selection task”, Cognition 31, No. 3, 187276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. (1992), Consciousness Explained New York: Little and Brown.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. (1989), “The Need to Know”, in Clay, M. and Lehrer, K. (eds.), Knowledge and Scepticism. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, pp. 89100.Google Scholar
Feldman, R. (1985), “Reliability and Justification,” Monist 63, 1: 159174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (1979), “What is Justified Belief?”, in Pappas, G. S. (ed.), Justification and Knowledge Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 123.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (1986), Epistemology and Cognition Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (1992), “Epistemic Folkways and Scientific Epistemology”, in A. Goldman, Liaison: Philosophy Meets the Cognitive and Social Sciences, pp. 155175. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gould, S.J. and Lewontin, R. (1979), “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Program”, Proceedings of the Royal Society, B: 581598.Google Scholar
Harman, G. (1973), Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Jerison, H. (1973), The Evolution of the Brain and Intelligence New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., and Tversky, A. (eds.) (1982), Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Komblith, H. (1993), Induction: Its Natural Ground. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lewontin, R. (1990), “The Evolution of Cognition”, in Osherson, and Smith, (eds.), Thinking: An Invitation to Cognitive Science, Volume 3, 229246. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Nisbett, R. and Ross, I. (eds.) (1980), Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. (1993), The Nature of Rationality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plato, (1961), “Meno”, in Hamilton, and Cairns, (eds.), Plato: The Collected Dialogues. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Pollock, J. (1987), “Epistemic Norms”, Synthese 71, 6195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (1986), Taking Darwin Seriously. London: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sartwell, C. (1992), “Why Knowledge is Merely True Belief', The Journal of Philosophy LXXXIX 4 167180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. (1981), “The Evolution of Rationality”, Synthese 46 95120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. (1984), The Nature of Selection. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stich, S. (1990), The Fragmentation of Reason. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar