Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-94fs2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-13T02:31:41.819Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Flight to Reference, or How Not to Make Progress in the Philosophy of Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Michael A. Bishop*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Iowa State University
Stephen P. Stich*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Rutgers University

Abstract

The flight to reference is a widely-used strategy for resolving philosophical issues. The three steps in a flight to reference argument are: (1) offer a substantive account of the reference relation, (2) argue that a particular expression refers (or does not refer), and (3) draw a philosophical conclusion about something other than reference, like truth or ontology. It is our contention that whenever the flight to reference strategy is invoked, there is a crucial step that is left undefended, and that without a defense of this step, the flight to reference is a fatally flawed strategy; it cannot succeed in resolving philosophical issues. In this paper we begin by setting out the flight to reference strategy and explaining what is wrong with arguments that invoke the strategy. We then illustrate the problem by considering arguments for and against eliminative materialism. In the final section we argue that much the same problem undermines Philip Kitcher's attempt to defend scientific realism.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1998

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Send requests for reprints to S. Stich, Department of Philosophy, Rutgers University, 26 Nichol Ave., New Brunswick, NJ 08901–2882; e-mail: stich@ruccs.rutgers.edu

Earlier versions of the arguments developed in this paper were presented to the philosophy of science discussion group at Canterbury University in Christchurch, New Zealand, the Beijing Forum for Philosophy of Science at the Institute of Philosophy of the Chinese Academy of Social Sciences, the Philosophy Colloquium at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York, and at conferences at the University of Utah and Humboldt University in Berlin. We are grateful to all of these audiences for much valuable feedback. Special thanks are due to Philip Catton, Steve Downes, Hartry Field, Heimir Geirsson, Philip Kitcher and an anonymous referee for Philosophy of Science.

References

Bishop, M. and Stich, S. (in preparation), “Moral Realism and the Flight to Reference”.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. (1984), “The Current Status of Scientific Realism”, in Leplin, Jarrett (ed.), Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 4182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1984), Matter and Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1978), Brainstorms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. (1981), Designation. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, G. (1983), “The causal theory of names”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 47: 187208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H. (1986), “The Deflationary Concept of Truth” in G. MacDonald and C. Wright (eds.), Fact, Science, and Value. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 55117.Google Scholar
Field, H. (1994), “Deflationist Views of Meaning and Content”, Mind 103: 249285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grosser, M. (1962/1979). The Discovery of Neptune. New York: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
Harman, G. (1967), “Quine on Meaning and Existence I”, Review of Metaphysics 21: 125151.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. (1990), Truth. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1978), “Theories, Theorists and Theoretical Change”, Philosophical Review 87: 519547.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1993), The Advancement of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1972), Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1984), Science and Values. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1970), “How to Define Theoretical Terms”, Journal of Philosophy 67: 1725.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1972), “Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50: 249258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, W. (1988), Judgement and Justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
McGinn, C. (1991), “Mental States, Natural Kinds and Psychophysical Laws”, in The Problem of Consciousness. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 126152.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975), “The meaning of ‘Meaning’”, in Mind, Language and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 215271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1978), Meaning and the Moral Sciences. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Quine, W.V. (1951), “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”, Philosophical Review 60: 2043.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. (1919), “Descriptions”, in Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., pp. 167180.Google Scholar
Searle, J. (1958), “Proper Names”, Mind 67: 166173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. (1982), “On the Ascription of Content”, in Woodfield, A. (ed.), Thought and Object. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 153206.Google Scholar
Stich, S. (1983), From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stich, S. (1996), “Deconstructing the Mind”, in Deconstructing the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 390.Google Scholar
Smart, J.J.C. (1968), Between Science and Philosophy. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
White, M. (1950), “The Analytic and the Synthetic: An Untenable Dualism” in S. Hook (ed.), John Dewey: Philosopher of Science and Freedom. New York: Dial Press, pp. 316330.Google Scholar