Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T09:09:39.647Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Heuristic for Conceptual Change

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Frank Arntzenius*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy University of Southern California

Abstract

One of our more fundamental beliefs is that causal chains are continuous in time: we believe that every influence from the past upon the future runs through the present. I argue that this tenet, given certain data, can force conceptual changes upon us. I attempt to formulate a heuristic for discovery, based as explicitly as possible upon this tenet, and illustrate it by means of several examples, one of which is Mendel's discovery of genes.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, University of Southern California, 3709 Trousdale Parkway, Los Angeles, CA 90089-0451.

References

Buchanan, B., and Wilkins, D. (eds.) (1993), Knowledge Acquisition and Learning. San Mateo: Morgan Kaufman.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. (1989), A Neurocomputational Perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, P. and Feigenbaum, E. (eds.) (1982), The Handbook of Artificial Intelligence, Volume 3. Reading: Addison Wesley.Google Scholar
Garber, D. (1983), “Old Evidence and Logical Omniscience in Bayesian Confirmation Theory”, in Testing Scientific Theories, Earman, J. (ed.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 99131.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. (1965), Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. (1966), Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Howson, C. (ed.) (1976), Method and Appraisal in the Physical Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C. and Urbach, P., Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach. La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
Kelly, K. (forthcoming), The Logic of Reliable Inquiry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kelly, K. and Glymour, C. (1992): “Inductive Inference from Theory Laden Data”, Journal of Philosophical Logic 21: 391444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. (eds.) (1970), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. London: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langley, P., Simon, H., Bradshaw, G., and Zytkow, J. (1987), Scientific Discovery. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olby, R. (1985), The Origins of Mendelism. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1959), The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchison.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1938), Experience and Prediction. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Rummelhart, D. and McClelland, J. (eds.) (1986), Parallel Distributed Processing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., and Scheines, R. (1993), Causation, Prediction, and Search. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thagard, P. (1992), Conceptual Revolutions. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zabell, S. (1992), “Predicting the Unpredictable”, Synthese 90: 205232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zahar, E. (1989), Einstein's Revolution. La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar