Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T03:18:03.106Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Logic of Explanation in Malinowskian Anthropology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Leon J. Goldstein*
Affiliation:
Brandeis University

Extract

In a contribution to a symposium on “Causality in the Social Sciences,” Lewis Feuer remarks in passing that “Functionalism, in the form which Malinowski gave it, affirms that culture is an ‘organic unity’; it is the principle that in every culture, each custom, belief, and behavioral form ‘represents an indespensible part within a working whole.’” That culture is an integrated and organic unity is a view found quite often in the writings of Malinowski, though he does not maintain it with full consistency. Sometimes he seems to say that a culture is made up of a number of grand institutions, each of which is an integrated unity, though the totality need not be. But whether affirmed or denied this thesis is not the doctrine, characteristic of almost every attempt made by Malinowski to explain cultural phenomena during the last quarter century of his life, which may be properly called “Malinowskian functionalism.” And that the doctrine cited by Feurer is sometimes formulated in such a way that the term “functional” or some variant is used, as in “culture is a functionally integrated organic unity,” makes no difference to my claim. I am not at all certain that the addition of the word “functionally” does anything for the view in question; it surely makes no difference to its scientific sterility. But that apart, the point I wish to make here is that a good many scholars who make references to Malinowski's functionalism have never bothered to discover just what in the world this is. They have been all too ready to cite the vague programmatic pronouncements in which Malinowski's writings abound, while seemingly oblivious to the fact that with rare exception every major attempt by Malinowski to account systematically for some kind of sociocultural phenomena reveals one and the same pattern of explanation. And it is this pattern alone which may be spoken of as Malinowski's method of functional analysis.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1957, The Williams & Wilkins Company

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Feuer, L. S., “Causality in the Social Sciences,” Journal of Philosophy, 1954, 51: 681–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
2. Gardiner, P., The Nature of Historical Explanation, London, 1952.Google Scholar
3. Gluckman, M., An Analysis of the Sociological Theories of Bronislaw Malinowski (The Rhodes-Livingstone Papers No. 16), Capteown, London, New York, 1949.Google Scholar
4. Hempel, C. G., Fundamentals of Concept Formation in Empirical Science (International Encyclopedia of United Science, vol. 2, no. 7), Chicago, 1952.Google Scholar
5. Idem., “The Function of General Laws in History,” in Feigl and Sellars, eds., Readings in Philosophical Analysis, New York, 1949, pp. 459–71.Google Scholar
6. Hempel, C. G., and Oppenheim, Paul, “The Logic of Explanation,” in Feigl and Brodbeck, eds., Readings in the Philosophy of Sciences, New York, 1953, pp. 319–52.Google Scholar
7. Hogbin, H. I., Law and Order in Polynesia, London, 1934.Google Scholar
8. Homans, G. C., The Human Group, New York, 1950.Google Scholar
9. Kant, I., Kant's Critique of Teleological Judgment, tr. and ed. by J. C. Meredith, Oxford, 1928.Google Scholar
10. Kroeber, A. L., Anthropology, new ed., rev., New York, 1948.Google Scholar
11. Levy, Marion J. Jr., The Structure of Society, Princeton, 1952.Google Scholar
12. Lowie, R. H., The History of Ethnological Theory, New York, 1937.Google Scholar
13. Malinowksi, B., Coral Gardens and Their Magic, 2 vols., London, 1935.Google Scholar
14. Idem., The Dynamics of Culture Change, New Haven, 1945.Google Scholar
15. Idem., The Foundations of Faith and Morals (Riddell Memorial Lectures, 7th Series), London, 1936.Google Scholar
16. Idem., “The Group and the Individual in Functional Analysis,” American Journal of Sociology, 1939, 44: 938–93.Google Scholar
17. Idem., “Magic, Science and Religion,” in J. Needham, ed., Science, Religion and Reality, New York, 1925; reprinted in Malinowski, Magic, Science and Religion and Other Essays, Boston and Glencoe, 1948.Google Scholar
18. Idem., Myth in Primitive Psychology (Psyche Miniatures, General Series No. 6), London, 1926.Google Scholar
19. Idem., “The Problem of Meaning in Primitive Languages,” in Ogden and Richards, The Meaning of Meaning, [1st ed.], New York and London, 1923.Google Scholar
20. Idem., A Scientific Theory of Culture and Other Essays, Chapel Hill, 1944.Google Scholar
21. Idem., Sex and Repression in Savage Society, London and New York, 1927.Google Scholar
22. Idem., The Sexual Life of Savages in North-Western Melanesia, 3rd ed., London, 1932.Google Scholar
23. Morris, C. W., Signs, Language and Behavior, New York, 1946.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
24. Ortiz, F., Cuban Counterpoint: Tobacco and Sugar, New York, 1947.Google Scholar
25. Parsons, T., Essays in Sociological Theory, [1st ed.), Glencoe, 1949.Google Scholar
26. Popper, K. R., The Open Society and Its Enemies, Princeton, 1950.Google Scholar
27. Radcliffe-Brown, A. R., Structure and Function in Primitive Society, London, 1952.Google Scholar