Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T03:19:40.168Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Monism on the One Hand, Pluralism on the Other

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

In this paper, I consider ways of responding to critiques of natural kinds monism recently suggested from the pluralist camp. Even if monism is determined to be untenable in certain domains (say, about species), it might well be tenable in others. Chemistry is suggested to be such a monist-friendly domain. Suggestions of trouble for chemical kinds can be defused by attending to the difference between monism as a metaphysical thesis and as a claim about classification systems. Finally, I consider enantiomers as a test case for the monism/pluralism debate. The question of whether enantiomers differ in kind does not appear easily answerable. I suggest that this legislates for pluralism in chemistry.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This paper owes much to discussions with the Columbia Metaphysicist Society (Andrea Borghini, Chris Haufe, Achille Varzi, Neil Williams, and Dave Wolfe) and extensive comments by Philip Kitcher, Achille Varzi, and two anonymous referees. Roy Sorensen will no doubt feel his influence on Section 5, having taught me much about incongruous counterparts.

References

Armstrong, David M. (1996), “Dispositions as Categorical States”, in Crane, Tim (ed.), Dispositions: A Debate. London: Routledge, 1518.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander (1998), “Dispositions and Antidotes”, Dispositions and Antidotes 48:227234.Google Scholar
Cline, David B. (ed.) (1995), Physical Origin of Homochirality in Life. Woodbury, NY: American Institute of Physics.Google Scholar
Dupré, John (1981), “Natural Kinds and Biological Taxa”, Natural Kinds and Biological Taxa 90:6690.Google Scholar
Dupré, John (1983), “The Disunity of Science”, The Disunity of Science 92:321346.Google Scholar
Dupré, John (1993), The Disorder of Things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Earman, John (1971), “Kant, Incongruous Counterparts, and the Nature of Space and Space-Time”, Kant, Incongruous Counterparts, and the Nature of Space and Space-Time 13:118.Google Scholar
Earman, John (1989), World Enough and Space-Time. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Ellis, Brian (2001), Scientific Essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ellis, Brian (2002), The Philosophy of Nature. Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gundersen, Lars (2002), “In Defence of the Conditional Account of Dispositions”, In Defence of the Conditional Account of Dispositions 130:389411.Google Scholar
Hori, Michio (1993), “Frequency Dependent Natural Selection in the Handedness of Scale Eating Cichlid Fish”, Frequency Dependent Natural Selection in the Handedness of Scale Eating Cichlid Fish 260:216219.Google ScholarPubMed
Jacques, Jean (1993), The Molecule and Its Double. Translated by Scanlon, L.. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Johnston, Mark (1997), “Manifest Kinds”, Manifest Kinds 94:564583.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel ([1783] 1977), Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. Translated by Ellington, James W.. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1984), “Species”, Species 51:308333.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (2001), Science, Truth, and Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
LaPorte, Joe (1996), “Chemical Kind Term Reference and the Discovery of Essence”, Chemical Kind Term Reference and the Discovery of Essence 30:112132.Google Scholar
Lewis, David (1991), Parts of Classes. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, David (1997), “Finkish Dispositions”, Finkish Dispositions 47:143158.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B. (1994), “Dispositions and Conditionals”, Dispositions and Conditionals 44:18.Google Scholar
Nerlich, Graham (1973), “Hands, Knees, and Absolute Space”, Hands, Knees, and Absolute Space 70:337351.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary (1975), “The Meaning of ‘Meaning’”, in Hilary Putnam, Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2, Mind, Language, and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 215271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, Quine Willard Van (1969), Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. London: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raval, Rasmita (2003), “Mirrors in Flatland”, Mirrors in Flatland 425:463464.Google ScholarPubMed
Slater, Matthew H. (2003), “Minimalism and Coincidence”, Minimalism and Coincidence 57:323329.Google Scholar
Sorensen, Roy (2002), “Mirror Imagery and Biological Selection”, Mirror Imagery and Biological Selection 17:409422.Google Scholar
Stanford, P. Kyle, and Kitcher, Philip (2000), “Refining the Causal Theory of Reference for Natural Kind Terms”, Refining the Causal Theory of Reference for Natural Kind Terms 97:99129.Google Scholar
van Cleve, James (1987), “Right, Left, and the Fourth Dimension”, Right, Left, and the Fourth Dimension 96:3368.Google Scholar
Wilkerson, Terence Edward (1995), Natural Kinds. Aldershot, UK: Avebury.Google Scholar