Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T21:48:20.037Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Problem of Known Illusion and the Resemblance of Experience to Reality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Are objects in convex passenger-side mirrors “closer than they appear”? If one adapts to inverting goggles, does the world go back to looking the way it was before, or does the world look approximately the same throughout the course of adaptation, only losing its normative sense of wrongness? The answers to these empirical, introspective questions might help cast light on the classic philosophical debate about the degree of resemblance between our visual experience of reality and things as they are in themselves.

Type
Cognitive and Psychological Sciences
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

For helpful conversation during the course of writing, thanks to Scott Bakker, Robert Briscoe, Brit Brogaard, David Chalmers, Louie Favela, Jack Lyons, Farid Masrour, David Papineau, Kevin Reuter, Susanna Siegel, Houston Smit, Maja Spener, Nathan Westbrook, commenters on relevant posts at The Splintered Mind, and audiences at University of Missouri–St. Louis, as well as the Philosophy of Science Association.

References

de Vos, A. 2000. Non-planar Driver’s Side Rearview Mirrors. US Department of Transportation Report DOT HS 809 149.Google Scholar
Harris, Charles S. 1965. “Perceptual Adaptation to Inverted, Reversed, and Displaced Vision.” Psychological Review 72:419–44.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harris, Charles S. 1980. “Insight or Out of Sight? Two Examples of Perceptual Plasticity in the Human Adult.” In Visual Coding and Adaptability, ed. Harris, Charles S.. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Hurley, Susan, and Noë, Alva. 2003. “Neural Plasticity and Consciousness.” Biology and Philosophy 18:131–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1781/1787/1929. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Smith, Norman Kemp. New York: St. Martin’s.Google Scholar
Klein, Colin. 2007. “Kicking the Kohler Habit.” Philosophical Psychology 20:609–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linden, David E. J., Kallenbach, Ulrich, Heinecke, Armin, Singer, Wolf, and Goebel, Rainer. 1999. “The Myth of Upright Vision: A Psychophysical and Functional Imaging Study of Adaptation to Inverting Spectacles.” Perception 28:469–81.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Locke, John. 1690/1690. Essay concerning Human Understanding. ed. Nidditch, P. H.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schwitzgebel, Eric. 2012. “A Story in Which I Acquire Fisheyes; or, The Paranoid Jeweler and the Sphere-Eye God.” The Splintered Mind (blog), November 27, 2012. http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com/2012/11/a-story-in-which-i-acquire-fisheyes-or.html.Google Scholar
Stratton, George M. 1896. “Some Preliminary Experiments on Vision without Inversion of the Retinal Image.” Psychological Review 3:611–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stratton, George M. 1897a. “Upright Vision and the Retinal Image.” Psychological Review 3:182–87.Google Scholar
Stratton, George M. 1897b. “Vision without Inversion of the Retinal Image.” Psychological Review 4:341–60, 463–81.Google Scholar
Taylor, James G. 1962. The Behavioral Basis of Perception. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Wierwille, Walter W., Schaudt, W. A., Gupta, S., Spaulding, J. M., Bowman, D. S., Fitch, G. M., Wiegand, D. M., and Hanowski, R. J.. 2008. Study of Driver Performance/Acceptance Using Aspheric Mirrors in Light Vehicle Applications. US Department of Transportation Report DOT HS 810 959.Google Scholar