Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T09:45:23.849Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Return of the Group

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Kim Sterelny*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy Victoria, University of Wellington

Extract

Once upon a time in evolutionary theory, everything happened for the best. Predators killed only the old or the sick. Pecking orders and other dominance hierarchies minimized wasteful conflict within the group. Male displays ensured that only the best and the fittest had mates. In the culmination of this tradition, Wynne-Edwards (1962, 1986) argued that many species have mechanisms that ensure groups do not over-exploit their resource base. The “central function” of territoriality in birds and other higher animals is “of limiting the numbers of occupants per unit area of habitat” (1986, 6). Species with dominance hierarchies, species with lekking breeding systems, and species with communal breeding regulate their populations. These social mechanisms have population regulation as their “underlying primary function” (1986, 9). Wynne-Edwards argued that these mechanisms evolve through group selection. Populations without such mechanisms are apt to go extinct by eroding their own resource base.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, Victoria University of Wellington, PO Box 600, Wellington, New Zealand; e-mail kimbo@kauri.vuw.ac.nz

Thanks to Richard Dawkins, Dan Dennett, Paul Griffiths, David Hull, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Philip Kitcher, John Maynard Smith, Karen Neander and Jim Woodward for their comments on earlier versions of chunks of this paper. Thanks especially to David Sloan Wilson for very extensive correspondence on all the issues in this paper.

References

Colwell, R. K. (1981), “Group Selection Implicated in the Evolution of Female Biased Sex Ratios”, Nature 290: 401404.10.1038/290401a0CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Damuth, J. (1985), “Selection Among ‘Species': A Formulation in terms of Natural Functional Units”, Evolution 39(3):11321146.Google ScholarPubMed
Damuth, J. and Heisler, L. (1988), “Alternative Formulations of Multilevel Selection”, Biology and Philosophy 3: 407430.10.1007/BF00647962CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1976), The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Second edition 1989.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1982), The Extended Phenotype. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1994), “Burying the Vehicle”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17: 617.10.1017/S0140525X00036207CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1994), “E Pluribus Unum?”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17: 617618.10.1017/S0140525X00036219CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dugatkin, L. A and Reeve, H. K. (1994), “Behavioral Ecology and Levels of Selection: Dissolving the Group Selection Controversy”, Advances in the Study of Behavior 23: 101133.10.1016/S0065-3454(08)60352-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamilton, W. (1975), “Innate Social Aptitudes in Man: An Approach from Evolutionary Genetics”, in Fox, R. (ed.), Biosocial Anthropology. London: Malaby Press, pp. 121160.Google Scholar
Hull, D. (1981), “Units of Evolution: A Metaphysical Essay”, in Jensen, R. and Harre, R. (ed.) The Philosophy of Evolution. Brighton: Harvester, pp. 000000. Reprinted in R. Brandon and R. Burian (ed.) (1984), Genes, Organisms Populations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 121–160.Google Scholar
Hull, D. (1988), Science as a Process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226360492.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, D. (1994), “Taking Vehicles Seriously”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17: 627628.10.1017/S0140525X00036323CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lack, D. (1966), Population Studies of Birds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lloyd, E., (1988), The Structure and Confirmation of Evolutionary Theory. New York: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
Lloyd, E., (1993), “Unit of Selection”, in E. Keller and E. Lloyd, Keywords in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 334340.Google Scholar
Maynard Smith, J. (1964), “Group Selection and Kin Selection”, Nature 201: 11451147.10.1038/2011145a0CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard Smith, J. (1987), “How to Model Evolution”, in Dupre, J. (ed.), The Latest on the Best. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 119131.Google Scholar
Nunney, L. (1989), “The Maintenance of Sex by Group Selection”, Evolution 43: 245257.10.1111/j.1558-5646.1989.tb04225.xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sober, E. (1993), Philosophy of Biology. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (ed.) (1994), Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology (second edition). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sterelny, K. and Kitcher, P. (1988), “The Return of the Gene”, Journal of Philosophy 85: 339360.10.2307/2026953CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wade, M. J. (1978), “A Critical Review of the Models of Group Selection”, Quarterly Review of Biology 53: 101114.10.1086/410450CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wade, M. J. (1985), “Soft Selection, Hard Selection, Kin Selection and Group Selection”, American Naturalist 125: 6173.10.1086/284328CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, G. C. (1966), Adaptation and Natural Selection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, G. C. (1992), Natural Selection: Domains, Levels and Challenges. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, D. S. (1980), The Natural Selection of Populations and Communities. Cummings, CA: Benjamin.Google Scholar
Wilson, D. S. (1983), “The Group Selection Controversy: History and Current Status”, Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 14:159187.10.1146/annurev.es.14.110183.001111CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, D. S. (1989), “Levels of Selection: An Alternative to Individualism in Biology and the Social Sciences”, Social Networks 11: 257272. (Reprinted in Sober 1994).10.1016/0378-8733(89)90005-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, D. S. (1990), “Weak Altruism, Strong Group Selection”, Oikos 59: 135140.10.2307/3545133CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, D. S. (1993), “Group Selection”, in E. Keller and E. Lloyd, Keywords in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 145148.Google Scholar
Wilson, D. S. (forthcoming a), “Group Selection and Human Behavior: A Critique of R. D. Alexander and a Case Study Involving Tolerated Theft”.Google Scholar
Wilson, D. S. (forthcoming b), “Incorporating Group Selection into the Adaptationist Program: A Case Study Involving Human Decision Making”, in Simpson, J. and Kendrick, D. (ed.), Evolutionary Approaches in Personality and Social Psychology. Erlbaum Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, D. S. and Sober, E. (1989), “Reviving the Superorganism”, Journal of Theoretical Biology 136: 332356.10.1016/S0022-5193(89)80169-9CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilson, D. S. and Sober, E. (1994), “Reintroducing Group Selection to Human Behavioral Sciences”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17: 385654.10.1017/S0140525X00036104CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, D. S. and Sober, E. (in preparation), “Altruism: Philosophy, Psychology, Evolution”.Google Scholar
Wynne-Edwards, V. C. (1962), Animal Dispersion in Relation to Social Behavior. Edinburgh: Liver and Boyd.Google Scholar
Wynne-Edwards, V. C. (1986), Evolution through Group Selection. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific.Google Scholar