Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-13T04:01:28.171Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Successor to the Realism/Antirealism Question

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Janet A. Kourany*
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame
*
Send requests for reprints to the author, Department of Philosophy, 336 O'Shaughnessy Hall, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, Indiana 46556–5639.

Abstract

The realism/antirealism controversy has gone on for centuries, and gives every indication that it will continue to go on for centuries. Dismayed, I take a closer look at it. I find that the question it poses—very roughly, whether scientific knowledge is true (approximately true, put forward as true, etc.) or only useful (empirically adequate, a convenient method of representation, etc.)—actually suppresses socially critical thought and discussion about science (e.g., concerning whether scientific knowledge is sexist or racist or socially harmful in other ways, or whether scientific knowledge is useful for achieving the goals we have or the goals we ought to have). I find, as well, that two of the most important responses to the realism/antirealism controversy—that which construes it as concerned with science's aims and that which construes it as concerned with science's results—fail to make sufficient empirical or normative contact with science. As a consequence, they provide representations of science that either do not help scientists (or nonscientists) make informed decisions about science, or actually hinder these individuals from doing so. I conclude that we should either stop engaging in the realism/antirealism controversy entirely, or else engage in it in a more socially responsible way—by gathering the right kinds of empirical and normative data, and framing more helpful versions of the questions we want to ask. I end by responding to the strong objections sure to be voiced by my colleagues in philosophy of science.

Type
Metaphilosophy and the History of the Philosophy of Science
Copyright
Copyright © 2000 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I would like to thank my colleagues Don Howard and Phil Quinn for very helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper, and Beth Eldon of the Notre Dame Biology Department for stimulating discussions relevant to the topics of this paper.

References

Boyd, Richard (1981), “Scientific Realism and Naturalistic Epistemology”, in Asquith, Peter and Giere, Ronald (eds.), PSA 1980, vol. 2. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, 613662.Google Scholar
Churchland, Paul and Hooker, Clifford (eds.) (1985), Images of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cordero, Alberto (1989), “Observation in Constructive Empiricism: Arbitrary or Incoherent?”, Critica XXI: 75101.Google Scholar
Ellis, Brian (1985), “What Science Aims to Do”, in Churchland and Hooker 1985, 4874.Google Scholar
Fine, Arthur (1986), The Shaky Game. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Fine, Arthur. (1991), “Piecemeal Realism”, Philosophical Studies 61: 7996.10.1007/BF00385834CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardner, Michael (1979), “Realism and Instrumentalism in 19th-Century Atomism”, Philosophy of Science 46: 134.10.1086/288848CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardner, Michael. (1983), “Realism and Instrumentalism in Pre-Newtonian Astronomy”, in Earman, John (ed.), Testing Scientific Theories. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 201265.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1984), “Experimentation and Scientific Realism”, in Leplin 1984, 154172.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian. (1986), “Weapons Research and the Form of Scientific Knowledge”, in David Copp (ed.), Nuclear Weapons, Deterrence, and Disarmament. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12: 237260.Google Scholar
Hausman, Daniel (1982), “Constructive Empiricism Contested”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 63: 2128.10.1111/j.1468-0114.1982.tb00083.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard, Don (1996), “Philosophy of Science and Social Responsibility: Some Historical Reflections”, Symposium on Science and Social Responsibility, 1996 meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (unpublished).Google Scholar
Keller, Evelyn Fox (1990), “Physics and the Emergence of Molecular Biology: A History of Cognitive and Political Synergy”, Journal of the History of Biology 23: 389409.10.1007/BF00136376CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Keller, Evelyn Fox. (1992), “Critical Silences in Scientific Discourse: Problems of Form and Re-Form”, in Keller, Evelyn Fox (ed.), Secrets of Life, Secrets of Death: Essays on Language, Gender and Science. New York: Routledge, 7392.Google Scholar
Kourany, Janet A. (1998), “A New Program for Philosophy of Science, in Many Voices”, in Kourany, Janet A. (ed.), Philosophy in a Feminist Voice: Critiques and Reconstructions. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 231262.10.1515/9781400822324CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1962), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1977), “Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice”, in Kuhn, Thomas S. (ed.), The Essential Tension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 320339.10.7208/chicago/9780226217239.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kukla, Andre (1998), Studies in Scientific Realism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry (1981), “A Confutation of Convergent Realism”, Philosophy of Science 48: 1949.10.1086/288975CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, Jarrett (ed.) (1984), Scientific Realism. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.10.1525/9780520337442CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, Jarrett. (1997), A Novel Defense of Scientific Realism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen (1994), “In Search of Feminist Epistemology”, The Monist 77: 472485.10.5840/monist199477428CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen. (1995), “Gender, Politics, and the Theoretical Virtues”, Synthese 104: 383397.10.1007/BF01064506CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen. (1997), “Cognitive and Non-Cognitive Values in Science: Rethinking the Dichotomy”, in Nelson, Lynn Hankinson and Nelson, Jack (eds.), Feminism, Science, and the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 3958.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1984), “A Case for Scientific Realism”, in Leplin 1984, 840.10.1525/9780520337442-003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, Ernan. (1988), “The Goals of Natural Science”, in Hronszky, Imre, Feher, Marta, and Dajka, Balazs (eds.), Scientific Knowledge Socialized. Budapest: Akademiai Kiado, 2758.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan. (1991), “Selective Anti-Realism”, Philosophical Studies 61: 97108.10.1007/BF00385835CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, Alan (1989), “NOA's Ark—Fine for Realism”, Philosophical Quarterly 39: 383398.10.2307/2219825CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary (1975), Mathematics, Matter and Method, vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rooney, Phyllis (1992), “On Values in Science: Is the Epistemic/Non-Epistemic Distinction Useful?”, in Hull, David, Forbes, Micky, and Okruhlik, Kathleen (eds.), PSA 1992, vol. 1. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, 1322.Google Scholar
Rosser, Sue (1990), “Women's Ways of Knowing”, in Rosser, Sue (ed.), Female-Friendly Science. Elmsford, NY: Pergamon Press, 3454.Google Scholar
Schlagel, Richard (1991), “Fine's ‘Shaky Game’ (and Why NOA is No Ark for Science)”, Philosophy of Science 58: 307323.10.1086/289618CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (1963), Philosophy and Scientific Realism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Statistical Abstract of the United States (1997). Washington, DC: U.S. Department of Commerce, Bureau of the Census.Google Scholar
Van Fraassen, Bas C. (1980), The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.10.1093/0198244274.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar