Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dk4vv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T06:52:30.832Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Psychology Behind J. S. Mill's ‘Proof’

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 February 2009

G. W. Spence
Affiliation:
Gonville & Caius College, Cambridge.

Extract

Professor J. B. Schneewind's recent excellent volume Mill's Ethical Writings has drawn attention to the necessity of studying Mill's notes to chapter XXIII of his father's Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind for a clear understanding of his theory of the moral sentiments. There are notes, however, by J. S. Mill to other chapters of that work, which should not be forgotten, because they elucidate the associationist theory of motivation which is obscurely appealed to in chapter IV of Utilitarianism. Critics of Mill from F. H. Bradley onwards have made erroneous statements about the psychology that underlies Mill's justification of the principle of utility. But if Mill was going to support his ethics with a psychological theory, he should have expressed that theory at length and unambiguously in his ethical treatise. In what follows, it is pointed out where critics have been unfair to Mill through their apparent ignorance of his notes to the Analysis and of his conception of sympathy; but it is also shown that there is a puzzling inconsistency between the notes and a key passage in Utilitarianism, chapter IV. Finally, the theory of habitual volition, which is expressed at the close of that chapter, is examined. Critics have paid little attention to this theory, but it entails a serious modification of psychological hedonism, and Mill obviously attributed great importance to it.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1968

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 18 note 1 Mill's Ethical Writings, New York, 1965Google Scholar; hereafter cited as ‘MEW’.

page 18 note 2 The English Utilitarians, Oxford, 2nd edition 1958, ch. X, pp. 168–9.Google Scholar

page 19 note 1 Mill, James's Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind, 1869, note to ch. XVII, Vol. II, p. 185.Google Scholar

page 19 note 2 Principia Ethica, Cambridge, 1903, ch. III, sec. 43.Google Scholar

page 19 note 3 Hall, E. W., ‘The “Proof” of Utility in Bentham and Mill’, Ethics, Vol. LX, No. 1, 10 1949, p. 10.Google Scholar

page 19 note 4 Ethical Studies, London, 1876, Essay III, p. 89.Google Scholar

page 19 note 5 Raphael, D. D., ‘Fallacies in and about Mill's Utilitarianism’, Philosophy, Vol. XXX, No. 115, 10 1955, pp. 351 & 354–5.Google Scholar

page 19 note 6 Footnote to Analysis ch. XXIV, Vol. II, p. 374Google Scholar. Cf. An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy, 6th edition 1889, ch. XXVI, MEW, pp. 236–8.Google Scholar

page 19 note 7 Note to Analysis ch. XXII, sec. 1, Vol. II, p. 262Google Scholar. Cf. Examination, ch. XXVI, MEW, p. 255.Google Scholar

page 20 note 1 Ethical Studies, Essay VII, pp. 232–3.Google Scholar

page 20 note 2 John Stuart Mill, A Study of His Philosophy, Edinburgh, 1895, ch. V, pp. 85–6.Google Scholar

page 20 note 3 Analysis, ch. XXI, sec. 2, sub-sec. 2, 2, Vol. II, p. 217.Google Scholar

page 20 note 4 ‘Professor Sedgwick's Discourse on the Studies of the University of Cambridge’, London Review, 04 1835Google Scholar, Dissertations and Discussions, Vol. I, 1859, MEW, p. 89.Google Scholar

page 21 note 1 Footnote to Analysis ch. XXIV, Vol. II, pp. 372–4.Google Scholar

page 21 note 2 MEW, p. 90.Google Scholar

page 21 note 3 Analysis, Vol. II, pp. 308–9Google Scholar, MEW, p. 260.Google Scholar

page 21 note 4 Bain's last note to Analysis ch. XXIII, Vol. II, pp. 305–7.Google Scholar

page 22 note 1 The Emotions and the Will, London, 1859Google Scholar, The Emotions, ch. XII, sees. 2 & 3.

page 22 note 2 ‘Bain's Psychology’, Edinburgh Review, 10 1859Google Scholar, Dissertations, Vol. III, 1867, p. 134.Google Scholar

page 22 note 3 The Emotions, ch. XII, sec. 6.

page 22 note 4 Last note to Analysis ch. XXIII, Vol. II, p. 309Google Scholar, MEW, p. 260.Google Scholar

page 22 note 5 Nature, Essential Works of John Stuart Mill, New York, 1961Google Scholar, edited by Lerner, Max, p. 392.Google Scholar

page 22 note 6 Ethical Studies, Essay III, p. 103Google Scholar. ‘The Alleged Fallacies in Mill's Utilitarianism’, The Philosophical Review, Vol. XVII, No. 5, 09 1908, pp. 481–2.Google Scholar

page 23 note 1 An Examination of the Utilitarian Philosophy, Cambridge, 1870, ch. V, pp. 8990.Google Scholar

page 23 note 2 Utilitarianism, ch. II, MEW, pp. 292–3.Google Scholar

page 23 note 3 Utilitarianism, ch. IV, MEW, p. 313.Google Scholar

page 23 note 4 ‘Definitions, Factual Premises, and Ethical Conclusions’, The Philosophical Review, Vol. LXI, No. 3, 07, 1952, p. 342.Google Scholar

page 23 note 5 MEW, p. 313.Google Scholar

page 24 note 1 Last note to Analysis ch. XXIV, Vol. II, p. 381.Google Scholar

page 24 note 2 MEW, p. 312.Google Scholar

page 24 note 3 See MEW, p. 275.Google Scholar

page 24 note 4 ‘Bain's Psychology’, p. 122.Google Scholar

page 25 note 1 E.g. Britton, Karl, John Stuart Mill, London, 1953, ch. II, sec. 3, pp. 50–1.Google Scholar

page 25 note 2 ‘J. S. Mill's “Proof” of the Principle of Utility’, Philosophy, Vol. XXXII, No. 121, 04 1957, p. 164.Google Scholar

page 25 note 3 Westminster Review, 10 1852Google Scholar, Dissertations, Vol. II, 1859Google Scholar, MEW, p. 193Google Scholar: ‘How these feelings of natural complacency and natural dread and aversion directed towards actions come to assume the peculiar chaiacter of what we term moral feelings is not a question of ethics but of metaphysics.’

page 25 note 4 Principia Ethica, ch. III, sec. 42.

page 25 note 5 Logic, 8th. edition 1872, Book VI, ch. II, sec. 4Google Scholar, MEW, p. 222.Google Scholar

page 26 note 1 Analysis, ch. XXIV, Vol. II, pp. 355–7.Google Scholar

page 26 note 2 Ibid., pp. 352–3.

page 26 note 3 ‘Bain's Psychology’, pp. 119122.Google Scholar

page 26 note 4 Analysis, ch. XXIV, Vol. II, p. 354.Google Scholar

page 26 note 5 Logic, Book I, ch. III, sec. 5Google Scholar, MEW, pp. 214–5.Google Scholar

page 27 note 1 Cf. letter to Cairnes, J. E., 23 06 1869Google Scholar (The Letters of John Stuart Mill, ed. Elliot, H. S. R., London, 1910, Vol. II, p. 208Google Scholar), where Mill says that he is inclined to agree in what he thinks is Bain's opinion, that volition is not a name for a peculiar state of feeling, but ‘only a name for the immediate and irresistible sequence between the specific action of the efferent nerve fibres as effort, and the internal cause which produces it, and which is either an idea or desire or (as explained for the first time by Bain) the spontaneous activity of the nervous system under the stimulus of nutriment’.

Mill's notion of volition is similar to Schopenhauer's. Schopenhauer argues that, although a man can wish two opposing actions, he can will only one of them, and only his action reveals to him which of the two he has willed, for until the action is performed, the issue is undecided; and that, when the strongest of competing motives has driven the others out of consciousness and determines the will, this outcome is called a resolve, that is, a volition. (On the Freedom of the Will, 1841, translated by Kolenda, K., Library of Liberal Arts, 1960, ch. II, p. 17, and ch. III, p. 37Google Scholar.) (A volition in this sense must not be confused with the intention to perform a certain action later on.) If it is only by the action that the agent himself can distinguish between a wish and a volition, it would indeed be wrong to regard a volition as a state of feeling.

page 27 note 2 Fragment on Mackintosh, London, 1835, Appendix A, p. 402.Google Scholar

page 27 note 3 Utilitarianism, ch. IV, MEW, p. 314.Google Scholar

page 27 note 4 Ibid., p. 315.

page 28 note 1 Ibid., p. 310.

page 28 note 2 Autobiography, Essential Works of John Stuart Mill, edited by Lerner, Max, ch. V, p. 88.Google Scholar