Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T08:02:28.793Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hume's Logical Objection to the Argument From Design Based on the Uniqueness of the Universe

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

Extract

Arguments from design in Hume's day were often cast as arguments from analogy. For instance, a very simple version might read like this: ‘The universe resembles a machine; machines are the products of intelligent design; therefore, the universe is (probably) the product of intelligent design.’ Design arguments (usually of a more sophisticated sort) were put forward by some of the greatest scientists of the time, including Robert Boyle and Isaac Newton. Such arguments were generally thought to be on a par with the conclusions of physics: Hume raised a number of well-known objections to such design arguments. I am going to discuss one of these objections, the claim that the uniqueness of the universe is, in itself, a bar to our drawing any conclusion about its cause or origin. This objection is raised by Hume at the end of ‘Of a Particular Providence’ and in Part II of the Dialogues.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1992

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Noxon, James, Hume's Philosophical Development (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973), p. 67.Google Scholar

2 Hume, David, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, edited by Steinberg, Eric (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1977), p. 93.Google Scholar

3 Hume, Enquiry, pp. 101–2.Google Scholar

4 Hume, Enquiry, p. 102.Google Scholar

5 Hume, David, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, ed. Popkin, Richard (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1980), p. 15.Google Scholar

6 Hume, Dialogues, pp. 16 and 19.Google Scholar

7 Hume, Dialogues, p. 21.Google Scholar

8 Hume, loc. cit.Google Scholar

9 Hume, Dialogues, p. 22.Google Scholar

10 Flew, Antony, David Hume, Philosopher of Moral Science (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986), p. 66.Google Scholar

11 Flew, op. cit. p. 64.Google Scholar

12 Gaskin, J. C. A., Hume's Philosophy of Religion, 2nd ed. (Atlanta Highlands: Humanities Press International, 1988), p. 25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

13 Noxon, op. cit. p. 106.Google Scholar

14 Noxon, op. cit. p. 108.Google Scholar

15 These hypotheses are found in the Dialogues, Parts VI and VII.Google Scholar

16 McPherson, Thomas, The Argument from Design (New York: St Martin's Press, 1972), p. 60.CrossRefGoogle ScholarNelson Pike makes much of the same point in the commentary which follows his edition of Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1970), p. 151.Google Scholar

17 Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. Selby—Bigge, L. A. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1888 and 1964), p. 142.Google Scholar

18 Hume's particular target is the Newtonian design argument, but his argument here applies equally to any theory of the origin of the universe, even a purely materialistic account. Hume regards all such theories as mere conjectures, though Philo seems to concede a slight advantage to design in Part XII of the Dialogues. On Newtonian design arguments, see Hurlbutt, Robert, Hume, Newton, and the Design Argument, rev. ed. (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1985), pp. 135–49.Google Scholar On Hume's opposition to other origin theories see the discussion by Heath, Peter, ‘The Incredulous Hume’, American Philosophical Quarterly, xiii (1976), 159–63.Google Scholar The controversy about Philo's apparent concession to design is discussed at length by Pike, Nelson, Hume's Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1970), pp. 204–38.Google Scholar

19 Hawking, Stephen, ‘The Edge of Spacetime’ in Davies, Paul, ed., The New Physics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), pp. 61–9 at p. 64.Google Scholar

20 Barbour, Ian, Religion in an Age of Science (New York: Harper and Row, 1990), p. 125.Google Scholar

21 Davies, Paul, God and the New Physics (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1983), pp. 20–4.Google Scholar

22 Hawking, loc. cit.Google Scholar

23 Revisiting the Big Bang’, U.S. News and World Report, 29 01 1990, 4650.Google Scholar

24 Barbour, op. cit. p. 126.Google Scholar

25 Davies, Paul, ‘The New Physics: A Synthesis’ in Davies, The New Physics, pp. 16 at p. 4.Google Scholar

26 Hume, Dialogues, Part VII.Google Scholar

27 Hawking, op. cit., p. 62.Google Scholar

28 Stoeger, William R., , S. J., ‘Contemporary Cosmology and Its Implications for the Science—Religion Dialogue’ in Russell, Robert John et al. (eds.) Physics, Philosophy and Theology (Vatican City State: Vatican Observatory, 1988), pp. 219–47 at pp. 228–30.Google Scholar

29 Swinburne, Richard, ‘The Argument from Design’, Philosophy, xliii (1968), pp. 199212 at p. 208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar The same point is made in McPherson, op. cit. p. 73. (Swinburne defends a version of the design argument, but not one based on modern cosmology.)

30 Flew, op. cit. p. 66.Google Scholar

31 Gaskin, op. cit. p. 26.Google Scholar

32 Davies, Paul, God and the New Physics (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1983), and many other works.Google ScholarLeslie, John, ‘Anthropic Principle, World Ensemble, Design’, American Philosophical Quarterly, xix (1982), 141–51 and other works, including ‘How to Draw Conclusions from a Fine—Tuned Cosmos’, in Russell, op. cit. 297–311.Google Scholar A useful summary of the literature is found in Davis, John Jefferson, ‘The Design Argument, Cosmic “Fine Tuning,” and the Anthropic Principle’, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, xxii (1987), pp. 139–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

33 Davies, Paul, God and the New Physics, p. 179.Google Scholar

34 Davies, , God and the New Physics, pp. 186–8.Google Scholar

35 Davies, , God and the New Physics, p. 189.Google Scholar

36 Ian Hacking points out that the oscillating universe theory, unlike the many worlds theory, makes the presence of life in this universe strictly a matter of chance. There may be infinitely many oscillations, but as far as we know this universe might be the first of them. Life did turn up here, but it was not inevitable. By contrast, the appearance of life is inevitable in the many worlds theory, since all possible universes in that theory are actualized. See The Inverse Gambler's Fallacy: the Argument from Design. The Anthropic Principle Applied to Wheeler Universes’, Mind, lxxvi (1987), pp. 331–40.Google Scholar

37 The hypothesis of‘intelligent design’ considered here is usually expressed in some mental metaphor. For instance, it is said that the universe shows evidence of having been ‘carefully thought out’, it seems to have been ‘expecting us’, and so on. The point of this hypothesis is that the universe is purposely constructed so as to allow for the appearance of life, and this in turn suggests that the universe is controlled by some cosmic mind. None of this amounts to anything like a complete theology, but then no one should expect to take a complete theology from the design argument. The historic function of design arguments, from Plato and the Stoics, to Boyle, Newton, and Paley, has been to support a teleological conception of the world against a purely naturalistic or materialistic interpretation. This is also its function here. Of course, nothing prevents us from elaborating the design hypothesis into a theology that also draws from other sources. Many people (perhaps including Paul Davies) will wish to do so.