Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T19:18:37.051Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

By ye divine arm: God and substance in De gravitatione

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 September 2012

HYLARIE KOCHIRAS*
Affiliation:
New Europe College Institute for Advanced Study, Strada Plantelor 21, Bucharest, 023971, Romania e-mail: kochiras@nec.ro

Abstract

This article interprets Newton's De gravitatione as presenting a reductive account of substance, on which divine and created substances are identified with their characteristic attributes, which are present in space. God is identical to the divine power to create, and mind to its characteristic power. Even bodies lack parts outside parts, for they are not constructed from regions of actual space, as some commentators suppose, but rather consist in powers alone, maintained in certain configurations by the divine will. This interpretation thus specifies Newton's meaning when he writes that bodies subsist ‘through God alone’; yet bodies do qualify as substances, and divine providence does not extend so far as occasionalism.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2012 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bennett, J. & Remnant, P. (1978) ‘How matter might first be made’, in Jarrett, C. E., King-Farlow, J., & Pelletier, F. J. (eds) New Essays on Rationalism and Empiricism, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 4: 111.Google Scholar
Biener, Zvi & Smeenk, Christopher (2011) ‘Cotes' Queries: Newton's empiricism and conceptions of matter’, in Janiak, A. & Schliesser, E. (eds) Interpreting Newton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 105137.Google Scholar
Brading, Katherine (2011) ‘Newton's law-constitutive approach to bodies: a response to Descartes’, in Janiak, A. & Schliesser, E. (eds) Interpreting Newton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1332.Google Scholar
Cohen, I. B. (1999). A guide to Newton's Principia (with contributions by M. Nauenberg, & G. Smith), in Newton, I., The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Cohen, I. B., & Whitman, A. (tr.) (Berkeley: University of California Press), 1370.Google Scholar
Conn, Christopher H. (1999) ‘Two Arguments for Lockean four-dimensionalism’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 7, 429446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dempsey, Liam (2006) ‘Written in the flesh: Isaac Newton on the mind–body relation’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 37, 420441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Descartes, René (1985) The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, I–II, Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R., & Murdoch, D. (trs) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). (Abbreviated CSM.)Google Scholar
Gabbey, Alan (2002) ‘Newton, active powers, and the mechanical philosophy’, in Cohen, I. Bernard & Smith, George E. (eds) Cambridge Companion to Newton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 329357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gabbey, Alan (2011) ‘The term materia in Newton and in the Newtonian tradition’, in Materia: XIII Colloquio Internazionale, Roma, 7-8-9 gennaio 2010. Atti a cura di Delfina Giovannozzi e Marco Veneziani, Lessico Intellettuale Europeo 113 (Florence: Leo S. Olschki Editore), 423445.Google Scholar
Gorham, Geoffrey (2011a) ‘How Newton solved the mind–body problem’, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 28, 2144.Google Scholar
Gorham, Geoffrey (2011b) ‘Newton on God's relation to space and time: the Cartesian framework’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 93, 281320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grant, Edward (1981) Much Ado about Nothing: Theories of Space and Vacuum from the Middle Ages to the Scientific Revolution (New York: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hall, A. R. & Hall, Marie Boas (1962) ‘Introduction to Part II’, in Isaac Newton, Unpublished Scientific Papers of Isaac Newton, Hall, A. R. and Hall, Marie Boas (eds) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 7588.Google Scholar
Henry, John (1986) ‘A Cambridge Platonist's materialism: Henry More and the concept of soul’, Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, 49, 172195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henry, John (1979) ‘Francesco Patrizi da Cherso's concept of space and its Later influence’, Annals of Science, 36, 549575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henry, John (2011) ‘Gravity and De gravitatione: the development of Newton's ideas on action at a distance’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 42: 1127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, Benjamin (2003) ‘Newton's De gravitatione et aequipondio fluidorum and Lockean four-dimensionalism’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 11, 309321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, James (2004) ‘Locke's Account of cohesion and its philosophical significance’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 12, 611630.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hooke, Robert (1678) Lectures ‘De Potentia Restitutiva’, or of Spring, Explaining the Power of Springing Bodies (London: John Martyn, Printer to the Royal Society).Google Scholar
Janiak, Andrew (2008) Newton as Philosopher (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kochiras, Hylarie (2009) ‘Gravity and Newton's substance counting problem’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 40, 267280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kochiras, Hylarie (2011) ‘Gravity's cause and substance counting: contextualizing the problems’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 42(1), 167184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kochiras, Hylarie (2012) ‘Spiritual presence and dimensional space beyond the cosmos’, Intellectual History Review, 22, 4168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koyre, Alexander (1957) From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press).Google Scholar
Locke, John (1975) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Nidditch, Peter H. (ed.) (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Mcguire, J. E. (1978). ‘Existence, actuality and necessity: Newton on space and time’, Annals of Science, 35, 463508.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mcguire, J. E. & Slowik, Edward (forthcoming) ‘Newton's ontology of omnipresence and infinite space’, Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy.Google Scholar
Mcguire, J. E. & Tamny, Martin (1983) Certain Philosophical Questions: Newton's Trinity Notebook (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
More, Henry (1925) Philosophical Writings of Henry More, MacKinnon, F. I. (ed.) (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Newton, Isaac (1952) Opticks, or A Treatise of the Reflections, Refractions, Inflections and Colors of Light, based on the 4th edn of 1730 (New York: Dover).Google Scholar
Newton, Isaac (1959–1971) Correspondence of Isaac Newton, 7 vols, Turnbull, H. W., Scott, J. F., Hall, A. R., & Tilling, L. (eds) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newton, Isaac (1962) Unpublished Scientific Papers of Isaac Newton, Hall, A. R., & Hall, M. B. (eds & trs) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Newton, Isaac (1999) The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Cohen, I. B., & Whitman, A. (tr.) (Berkeley: University of California Press).Google Scholar
Newton, Isaac (2004) Newton: Philosophical Writings, Janiak, A. (ed.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nolan, Lawrence (1997) ‘Reductionism and nominalism in Descartes's theory of attributes’, Topoi, 16, 129140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Francesco, Patrizi, (1943): ‘On physical space’ (De Spacio Physico), Benjamin Brickman (tr. and commentary), Journal of the History of Ideas, 4, 224245.Google Scholar
Reid, Jasper (2008) ‘The spatial presence of spirits among the Cartesians’, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 46, 91117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slowik, Edward (2009) ‘Newton's metaphysics of space: a “tertium quid” betwixt substantivalism and relationism, or merely a “god of the (rational mechanical) gaps”?’, Perspectives on Science, 17, 429456.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stein, Howard (2002) ‘Newton's metaphysics’, in Bernard Cohen, I. and Smith, George (eds), The Cambridge Companion to Newton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 256307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar