Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T08:15:24.908Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The CaML model of pantheism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 January 2020

NIKK EFFINGHAM*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Birmingham, Birmingham, United Kingdom, B30 1AD, UK

Abstract

This article argues for a new understanding of pantheism whereby God is a multi-located mereological simple which constitutes the cosmos. I argue that the traditional theist can more readily accept this version of pantheism than a version identifying God with the cosmos.1

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1.

Thanks to the stipend provided by the Pantheism and Panentheism Project, funded by the John Templeton Foundation. I would also like to thank the anonymous referees of this journal for their helpful advice and comments.

References

Baker, L. (2000) Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baltzly, D. (2003) ‘Stoic pantheism’, Sophia, 42, 333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calosi, C. (2014) ‘Extensionality, multilocation, persistence’, dialectica, 68, 121139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cotnoir, A. (2010) ‘Anti-symmetry and non-extensional mereology’, Philosophical Quarterly, 60, 396405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cotnoir, A. (2017) ‘Mutual indwelling’, Faith and Philosophy, 34, 123151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deng, N. (2019) God and Time (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Effingham, N. & Melia, J. (2007) ‘Endurantism and timeless worlds’, Analysis, 67, 140147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Effingham, N. & Robson, J. (2007) ‘A mereological challenge to endurantism’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85, 633640.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Effingham, N. (2010) ‘Mereological explanation and time travel’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 88, 333345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Effingham, N. (2012) ‘Endurantism and perdurantism’, in Barnard, R. & Manson, N. (eds) The Continuum Companion to Metaphysics (New York: Continuum), 179197.Google Scholar
Effingham, N. (2015a) ‘The location of properties’, Noûs, 49, 846866.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Effingham, N. (2015b) ‘Multiple location and Christian philosophical theology’, Faith and Philosophy, 32, 2544.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Effingham, N. (2020) Time Travel: Probability and Impossibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, K. (2003) ‘The non-identity of a material things and its matter’, Mind, 112, 195234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrest, P. (1997) ‘Pantheism and science’, The Monist, 80, 307319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrest, P. (2016a) ‘Pantheism’, Roczniki Filozoficzne, 64, 6791.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrest, P. (2016b) ‘The personal pantheist conception of God’, in Buckareff, A. & Nagasawa, Y. (eds) Alternative Concepts of God: Essays on the Metaphysics of the Divine (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 2140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Francks, R. (1979) Omniscience, Omnipotence and Pantheism, Philosophy 54, 395399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilmore, C. (2007) ‘Time travel, coinciding objects, and persistence’, Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 3, 177198.Google Scholar
Gilmore, C. (2018) ‘Location and mereology’, in Zalta, E. N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition), <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/location-mereology/>.Google Scholar
Gordon, J. (2018) ‘Rethinking divine spatiality: divine omnipresence in philosophical and theological perspective’, The Heythrop Journal, 59, 534543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, P. (2004) Elements of Pantheism, 2nd edn (Coral Springs FL: Llumina Press).Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. (2006) Metaphysical Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hewitt, S. (2019) ‘God is not a person (an argument via pantheism)’, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 85, 281296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hovda, P. (2013) ‘Tensed mereology’, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42, 241283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hudson, H. (2006a) ‘Confining composition’, The Journal of Philosophy, 103, 631651.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hudson, H. (2006b) ‘Simple statues’, Philo, 9, 4046.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hudson, H. (2009) ‘Omnipresence’, in Flint, T. P. & Rea, M. C. (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 199216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Inman, R. (2017) ‘Omnipresence and the location of the immaterial’, Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, 8, 168206.Google Scholar
Johansson, J. (2009) ‘Constituted simples?’, Philosophia, 37, 8789.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnston, M. (2009) Saving God (Princeton: Princeton University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, M. (1994) Pantheism: A Non-Theistic Concept of Deity (London: Routledge).Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1976) ‘The paradoxes of time travel’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 13, 145152.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986) On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Lowe, E. (1995) ‘Coinciding objects: in defence of the “standard account”’, Analysis, 55, 171178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacBride, F. (1998) ‘Where are particulars and universals?’, dialectica, 52, 203227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mander, W. (2016) ‘Pantheism’, in Zalta, E. N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/pantheism/>.Google Scholar
Mander, W. (2000) ‘Omniscience and pantheism’, The Heythrop Journal, 41, 199208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDaniel, K. (2003) ‘No paradox of multi-location’, Analysis, 63, 309311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDaniel, K. (2007) ‘Extended simples’, Philosophical Studies, 133, 131141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, D. (1989) The Philosophy of John Scottus Eriugena (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mullins, R. (2016) The End of the Timeless God (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagasawa, Y. (2016) ‘Modal panentheism’, in Buckareff, A. & Nagasawa, Y. (eds) Alternative Concepts of God: Essays on the Metaphysics of the Divine (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 91105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nolan, D. (2018) ‘Cosmic loops’, in Bliss, R. & Priest, G. (eds) Reality and its Structure: Essays in Fundamentality (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 91106.Google Scholar
Oakes, R. (1977) ‘Classical theism and pantheism: a victory for process theism?’, Religious Studies, 13, 167173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oakes, R. (2006) ‘Divine omnipresence and maximal immanence: supernaturalism versus pantheism’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 43, 171179.Google Scholar
Parsons, J. (2007) ‘Theories of location’, Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 3, 201232.Google Scholar
Pfeifer, K. (2016) ‘Pantheism as panpsychism’, in Buckareff, & Nagasawa, Y. (eds) Alternative Concepts of God: Essays on the Metaphysics of the Divine (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 4150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pickel, B. (2010) ‘There is no “is” of constitution’, Philosophical Studies, 147, 193211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A. (2007) ‘Materialism and Christian belief’, in van Inwagen, P. & Zimmerman, D. (eds) Persons: Human and Divine (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 99141.Google Scholar
Pruss, A. (2013) ‘Omnipresence, multilocation, the real presence and time travel’, The Journal of Analytic Theology, 1, 6073.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2007) ‘From nihilism to monism’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85, 175191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2010) ‘Monism: the priority of the whole’, Philosophical Review, 119, 3176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skow, B. (2007) ‘Are shapes intrinsic?’, Philosophical Studies, 133, 111130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steinhart, E. (2004) ‘Pantheism and current ontology’, Religious Studies, 40, 6380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomas, E. (2019) ‘The idealism and pantheism of May Sinclair’, Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 5, 137157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomson, J. (1998) ‘The statue and the clay’, Noûs, 32, 149173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vallicella, W. (2019) ‘Divine simplicity’, in Zalta, E. N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/divine-simplicity/>.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, P. (1990) Material Beings (Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar
Vander Laan, D. (2017) ‘Creation and conservation’, in Zalta, E. N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition), <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/creation-conservation/>.Google Scholar
Walters, L. (2019) ‘Are the statue and the clay mutual parts?’, Noûs, 53, 2350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ware, B. (ed.) (2008) Perspectives on the Doctrine of God: 4 Views (Nashville TN: B & H Publishing).Google Scholar
Wasserman, R. (2004) ‘The constitution question’, Noûs, 38, 693710.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zimmerman, D. (1997) ‘Immanent causation’, Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 433471.Google Scholar