Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T09:21:41.120Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Coherence of God-Talk

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

Adel Daher
Affiliation:
Brooklyn College of the City University of New York

Extract

God, as viewed by Muslims, Jews and Christians, is a transcendent being. To say that God is transcendent is to say, among other things, that spatiotemporal predicates do not apply to him. He is disembodied and absolutely immutable. God, nevertheless, is on this same view an agent. He makes things happen, he answers prayers, he judges, he forgives, he punishes, he guides, etc. The concept of God as a being worthy of worship seems to require that God be an absolutely eternal being on the one hand with all that this entails and a being that is absolutely just, merciful, forgiving, loving, good, on the other. It is the predication of such attributes of God that yields the concept of transcendent agency. This means in effect that for a being to be God this being must be, at least, a disembodied agent. But the concept of a disembodied agent, it is argued, is a contradiction in terms.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1976

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 446 note 1 It will be argued in more detail later that the concept of a disembodied action is incoherent.

page 446 note 2 Some philosophers argue that it is not necessary to ascribe non-temporality to the nature of God. This view will be discussed later from Penelhum's point of view. See Penelhum, Terence, Religion and Rationality (Random House, 1971), p. 152.Google Scholar

page 447 note 1 Alston, W. P., ‘The Elucidation of Religious Statements’, in Process and Divinity, edited by Reese, W. L. and Freeman, E. (LaSalle, Illinois, 1964), p. 151.Google Scholar

page 448 note 1 Penelhum, op. cit. p. 151.

page 448 note 2 Ibid. p. 156.

page 448 note 3 Ibid. p. 156.

page 448 note 4 Ibid. p. 150.

page 448 note 5 Ibid.

page 448 note 6 Ibid. p. 151.

page 448 note 7 Ibid.

page 448 note 8 Ibid. p. 151.

page 448 note 9 Ibid.

page 449 note 1 Ibid.

page 449 note 2 Ibid. p. 152.

page 449 note 3 Ibid. pp. 152–3.

page 450 note 1 Ibid. pp. 154–7.

page 450 note 2 Ibid. p. 155.

page 451 note 1 Ibid.

page 451 note 2 Ibid.

page 451 note 3 Ibid. p. 156.

page 451 note 4 Ibid. p. 155.

page 451 note 5 Penelhum, , Survival and Disembodied Existence (New York, Humanities Press, 1970), chap. 5Google Scholar.

page 451note 6 Penelhum, Religion and Rationality, op. cit. p. 156.

page 4510 note 7 Ibid. pp. 156–7.

page 451 note 8 Ibid. p. 157.

page 451 note 9 Ibid.

page 454 note 1 Ibid. p. 151; see also Survival and Disembodied Existence, op. cit. chap. 3.

page 454 note 2 Survival and Disembodied Existence, p. 41.

page 454 note 3 Ibid.

page 454 note 4 Ibid. p. 40.

page 454 note 5 Ibid. p. 38.

page 455 note 1 Ibid. pp. 38–9.

page 455 note 2 Ibid. p. 38.

page 455 note 3 Ibid. p. 39.

page 457 note 1 Hampshire, Stuart, Thought and Action (The Viking Press, 1959), p. 41.Google Scholar

page 458 note 1 Ibid.

page 459 note 1 Penelhum, , Survival and Disembodied Existence, op. cit. p. 25Google Scholar.

page 459 note 2 Ibid.

page 459 note 3 Hampshire, op. cit. p. 42.

page 459 note 4 Ibid.

page 462 note 1 For a lucid and illuminating discussion of these issues see Christian, W. A., Meaning and Truth in Religion (Princeton, 1964), pp. 256–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

page 462 note 2 Ibid.

page 462 note 3 Ibid. p. 256.

page 462 note 4 Ibid. pp. 256–7.

page 462 note 5 Ibid. p. 256.

page 462 note 6 Ibid.

page 464 note 1 Ibid. p. 256.

page 464 note 2 Ibid. p. 257–8.