Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dk4vv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T08:15:34.013Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Criteria of Truth in Science and Theology1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

Mary Hesse
Affiliation:
Professor of Philosophy of Science, University of Cambridge

Extract

Faced with what he saw as the danger to society in the ascendancy of natural science and decline in religion and morals, the great French sociologist Emile Durkheim sought the origins of both religion and science in their function in primitive societies as guarantors of social solidarity. In contrast to Frazer, Tylor, and other early anthropologists, he looked for the internal intelligibility of myth and ritual in social terms, rather than regarding them just as failed attempts to state objective truths about the natural world of the same kind as those later arrived at by natural science. One does not have to accept Durkheim's ultimately atheistic identification of God with Society, nor the politically authoritarian consequences which have some-times been held to follow from this identification, to see that Durkheim has raised a set of issues of crucial importance for a discussion of science and the myths and doctrines of religion. For what he has done is to reintroduce a third factor into the perennial and by now rather frustrating dichotomy between science and religion, namely society and the sciences of man. It is some consequences of this approach that I want to explore in this paper.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1975

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 385 note 2 Especially in The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life, English ed. London, 1915.Google Scholar

page 386 note 1 Works, ed. Spedding, J. and Ellis, R. L., London, Vol. IV, p. 32.Google Scholar

page 387 note 1 Works, ed. Spedding, J. and Ellis, R. L., London, Vol. IV, p. 365.Google Scholar

page 388 note 1 For useful discussions see Rationality, ed. Wilson, B. R., Oxford, 1970Google Scholar, and Modes of Thought, ed. Horton, R. and , R. Finnegan, London, 1973.Google Scholar Philosophical presuppositions of the concept of ‘truth within a system’ have been developed in the work of W. v. O. Quine: see especially Ontological Relativity and other Essays, New York, 1969.Google Scholar

page 388 note 2 The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed.Chicago, 1970.Google Scholar

page 389 note 1 For a similar interpretation of natural science, see , J. Habermas, Knowledge and Human Interests, English ed., London, 1972Google Scholar, especially chaps. 5, 6 and Appendix. I have attempted to develop in more detail the concept of scientific truth implied in this paper in my Structure of Scientific Inference, London, 1974.Google Scholar

page 394 note 1 For useful discussions of objectivity and value in the social sciences, see Readings in the Philosophy of the Social Sciences, ed. Brodbeck, M., New York and London, 1968Google Scholar, part two; , R. Dahrendorf, Homo Sociologicus, London, 1973Google Scholar; MacIntyre, A., Against the Self-images of the Age, London, 1971Google Scholar; Mannheim, K., Ideology and Utopia, London, 1936Google Scholar; Myrdal, G., Objectivity in Social Research, London, 1970Google Scholar; Rex, J., Key Problems of Sociological Theory, London, 1970.Google Scholar

page 394 note 2 English ed., London, 1972.

page 396 note 1 As presented in Althuser, L. and Balibar, E., Reading Capital, English ed., London, 1970.Google Scholar

page 387 note 3 The Order of Things, English ed., London, 1970, p. 385.Google Scholar