Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-13T03:35:27.024Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Shared intentionality and divine persons: explorations in empirical psychology and ramified natural theology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 September 2023

Dennis P. Bray*
Affiliation:
St Mary's College, School of Divinity, University of St Andrews, St Andrews, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article explores the intersection of two developing fields of study: the psychological field of shared intentionality and the philosophy of religion field of ramified natural theology. In shared intentionality, agents share mental states and cooperate to achieve a common goal. Many psychologists in this field believe that of all the primates, only humans share intentionality – humans alone form a ‘we’. Ramified natural theology is the project of presenting philosophical evidences for core doctrines of the Christian faith. In this article I investigate some applications of shared intentionality for Christian natural theology. In the Anselmian tradition I offer two deductive arguments that deploy shared intentionality to argue that there are multiple divine persons. I then suggest that analogical arguments – often overlooked by philosophers of religion – provide a better fit for psychological findings, such as shared intentionality. After sketching some fundamental features of analogical arguments, I advance two arguments by analogy for the conclusion that God, like humans, shares intentionality. These arguments show that the psychology of shared intentionality, and empirical psychology more generally, is a promising source for theological reflection.

Type
Original Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided that no alterations are made and the original article is properly cited. The written permission of Cambridge University Press must be obtained prior to any commercial use and/or adaptation of the article.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Overview

This article explores the intersection of two developing fields of study, the psychological field of shared intentionality and the philosophy of religion field of ramified natural theology. Shared intentionality is the phenomenon in which agents have in common specific goals, knowledge, and other mental states, and cooperate to achieve those shared goals. While some non-human primates engage in limited cooperation, many psychologists agree that only humans share intentionality − humans alone form a ‘we’. Ramified natural theology is the project of presenting philosophical evidences for core doctrines of the Christian faith.

In this article I bring the two recent research programmes into conversation. Taking theological engagement with the sciences seriously, this article has two main aims. First, I apply findings from empirical psychology in ramified natural theology arguments. While a few practitioners of ramified natural theology are concerned that their work be compatible with the sciences, no one to date includes the sciences as part of their work. The arguments I propose are not meant as full defences, but rather as initial surveys of the plausibility and fruitfulness for deploying findings from the psychological sciences, such as shared intentionality, into the project of ramified natural theology.

As a second aim, I take soundings for where an important piece of scientific methodology finds organic fit in natural theology. John Perry and Joanna Leidenhag have recently commented that, ‘Oftentimes a method will open-up new roads of inquiry’ (Perry and Leidenhag (Reference Perry and Leidenhag2021), 249). I investigate this thesis by deploying analogical argumentation – an important tool in many scientific endeavours – for reasoning about divine persons.

A study like this one, which stands at the intersection of two cutting-edge fields, is itself quite novel. Therefore, I stress that the aims of this article are primarily exploratory. This article takes first steps towards a judicious and effective ‘employ[ment of] scientific theories and findings’, such as shared intentionality, ‘in constructive and concrete theological debates’, such as ramified natural theology (Perry and Leidenhag (Reference Perry and Leidenhag2021), 249).

Outline

The article takes the following steps. In the first section I sketch the project of ramified natural theology. As science-engaged theologians know (and also theology-engaged-scientists), one of the greatest hurdles in productive interdisciplinary discussion is the ability to speak the language of other disciplines. Since the fields discussed in this article are highly specialized, the tendency for isolation is pressing. Perry and Leidenhag counsel that science-engaged theologians ‘remain always ready to explain the larger picture that lies behind their concepts, as well as to listen to scientists as they explain the foreign world that lies behind seemingly familiar language’ (Perry and Leidenhag (Reference Perry and Leidenhag2023), 46). Taking this advice to heart, in the next section I outline the core elements of shared intentionality, giving special care to understand what psychologists mean when they discuss this phenomenon.

In the following section I apply the findings of shared intentionality in a pair of deductive arguments for multiple divine persons. We find that Anselmian-type reasoning can utilize the notion of shared intentionality, but perfect-being theology faces several challenges. Even if these challenges can be overcome, deductive proofs are not the best place to deploy shared intentionality. I suggest that arguments by analogy are a much better fit for utilizing the findings of the psychological sciences. The subsequent section provides some necessary ground clearing. There I give a short introduction to the field of analogical reasoning, which does not seek necessary conclusions. Instead, an analogical argument demonstrates that its conclusion is probable and, importantly, that the conclusion is philosophically (and theologically, and psychologically) worthwhile, demonstrating that it merits serious investigation. In the penultimate section I offer two analogical arguments for divine shared intentionality. The final section concludes with brief reflections on how divine shared intentionality aids the philosophical defence of Christian theism, and is well-positioned for judicious integration with biblical, historical, and philosophical sources of trinitarian theology.

Ramified natural theology

Natural theology, traditionally conceived, is the project of reflecting on God's existence and nature through one's senses and reason. The faculties of physical sensation and reason are deployed with regard to data that is in principle accessible to any human. Those faculties are not deployed with regard to any purported instances of divine (or special) revelation.Footnote 1 This traditional form of natural theology typically results in formal arguments for a minimal (or ‘bare’) theism: the existence of God and God's attributes such as omnipotence, omniscience, and omnibenevolence.Footnote 2 Traditional natural theology is immediately recognizable in well-known examples like Aquinas' five ways, Paley's design argument, and William Lane Craig's version of the Kalam cosmological argument.

Some recent natural theologians have extended the scope of their reasoning beyond that typically sought by traditional natural theology. These thinkers develop natural theological arguments for conclusions that fall squarely within some dogmatic picture of God. Thus, Christian practitioners of this branch of natural theology argue for the truth of specifically Christian claims about God, such as Jesus' resurrection, Jesus' divinity, or God's triunity. Indeed, this project is a particularizing branch, or ramification, of the traditional project and so is commonly referred to as ‘ramified natural theology’ (hereafter RNT).Footnote 3

The most notable contemporary proponent of Christian RNT is Richard Swinburne.Footnote 4 Several features relevant to the present discussion stand out in Swinburne and other recent proponents of Christian RNT.Footnote 5 First, many of the arguments developed by Christian ramified natural theologians are sourced from the Christian tradition, with varying levels of dependence.Footnote 6 For example, in advancing arguments for multiple divine persons, Stephen Davis (Reference Davis2006, 60–78) and William Lane Craig (Moreland and Craig (Reference Moreland and Craig2003), 594–595) both draw from the twelfth-century thinker Richard of St Victor. Similarly, in developing a case for Jesus' resurrection, Gary Habermas and Michael Licona (Reference Habermas and Licona2004, 48–63) draw from Church Fathers not only for early testimony, but also for some powerful lines of argumentation. Second, modern Christian proponents of RNT are often concerned that their arguments be compatible with the best findings of the modern sciences.Footnote 7 Even so, employment of the empirical sciences in RNT arguments is still largely unexplored.Footnote 8

In sum, there is plenty of work to be done in incorporating the sciences into Christian natural theological arguments. To take steps towards this end, in the next section I will give an overview of key findings from the psychological sciences, namely, from the field of shared intentionality.

Shared intentionality

In the past few decades psychologists have developed a sophisticated account of shared intentionality, also referred to as joint and we intentionality. Research in shared intentionality is highly interdisciplinary, standing at the intersection especially of developmental and comparative psychology, but also utilizing insights from evolutionary, cognitive, neurological, and behavioural psychology.Footnote 9 Further, scientists in this field draw key theoretic principles and insights from philosophers, particularly Searle, Gilbert, and Tuomela.Footnote 10 Psychologists readily acknowledge their use of foundational concepts as developed by these and other philosophers. Even so, scientists working in shared intentionality adjust concepts to fit the empirical data, and have therefore developed particular terminological conventions.

Akin to George Bernard Shaw's quip about two nations divided by a common language, psychologists use much of the same terminology as philosophers, but often with different emphases or differing semantic scope altogether.Footnote 11 For this reason, as I outline the core of the view I will take special care to specify what psychologists mean when they discuss shared intentionality.

Leading psychologists in the field include Michael Tomasello and Malinda Carpenter. Shared intentionality, these psychologists argue, is what allows for specifically human cultural activities and separates humans from the other primates. Tomasello and Carpenter summarize a key point this way,

The big Vygotskian idea is that what makes the human condition different is not more individual brainpower, but rather the ability of humans to learn through other persons and their artifacts, and to collaborate with others in collective activities. (Tomasello and Carpenter (Reference Tomasello and Carpenter2007), 121)

In the present article, ‘shared intentionality’ (or SI for short) refers to a social-psychological, collaborative activity in which participants share or have in common certain mental states. In sharing intentions, persons S1 and S2 play a delicate and complex social-cognition game. The scientific literature on this subject is increasingly vast.Footnote 12 Nevertheless, we may identify seven conditions that are essential to SI (as psychologists deploy the notion):

  1. (i) S1 and S2 both have the same intention. In this context ‘intention’ refers to a mental representation of a possible state of affairs – what philosophers often call a ‘mental model’.Footnote 13 An intention is a way the world could be as envisioned by S1 and S2. More specifically, it is a way that S1 and S2 mentally represent their environment as it could be.

  2. (ii) S1 and S2 both desire for the world to be this way. They do not only see their environment as possibly being different, but they also want the change to happen.

Taken together, (i) and (ii) form a ‘concrete goal or purpose by which human beings’, and some other species, ‘guide their behaviour’ (Tomasello (Reference Tomasello, Moore and Dunham1995), 103–130). As psychologists in the field conceive of it, SI is highly teleological since it couples the intention (the telos, end) and the will (volition, desire) to achieve that end. That is, S1 and S2 both share a mental model of their environment, and share a desire that that mental model be realized. In a word, S1 and S2 share a goal. Next,

  1. (iii) S1 and S2 both engage in some behaviour to realize the shared goal. Each subject acts to achieve the state of affairs which each desires.Footnote 14

So far we have a way the world could be modified (from i), the desire for the modification (ii), and the activity to make it so (iii). But a shared goal and simultaneous action are not yet sufficient for truly shared intentionality. For example, two children may both want to kick a ball into a net and attempt to do so within a few yards of each other. In this instance, they share the goal ‘kick the ball into the net’, and they are both trying to achieve that goal at the same time. Yet, without some further ingredients these children are merely engaging in solo-play, though simultaneously and in close proximity. They are not yet playing a game together. Four more elements are still required:

  1. (iv) S1 and S2 both monitor their environment and adjust their behaviour to better achieve their goal. By attending to her action's effects on the environment, S1 regulates her actions and adjusts her action plan.

  2. (v) S1 and S2 both monitor the other's attention to the environment and ongoing activity of other agents. In this ‘joint attention’, S1 attends to S2 and what S2 is doing and attending to. S2 does the same with S1. In this way there is an ongoing feedback circle between a participant, her environment, and the other participants (as they simultaneously attend to the environment and other participants).

Joint attention (element (v)) is an example of what cognitive and other psychologists call ‘theory-of-mind’, or ‘mind reading’.Footnote 15 A subject engages in mind reading when she attributes mental states – such as goals, intentions, beliefs, desires, feelings – to other subjects, thereby allowing her to anticipate the other subject's behaviour.Footnote 16

With the addition of elements (iv) and (v) we can see the beginnings of a collective or social group. Elements (i)–(v) are demonstrated especially by higher primates, such as chimps, who pool their collective attention in group activities like hunting or play (Melis et al. (Reference Melis, Hare and Tomasello2006), 1297–1300). The remaining two elements, though, combine with the previous ones to finally yield shared intentionality. Indeed, as some comparative and developmental psychologists argue, it is the following two conditions that set humans apart from other primates:

  1. (vi) S1 and S2 have mutual knowledge, which can be described in three parts. First, both attend to the same object in the environment, namely, that piece of the world relevant to their shared goal (this is largely a repetition of (i) and (iv)). Second, both know that the other is attending to the same object (an instance of mind reading from (v)). Third, both S1 and S2 know that the other knows.

An example of (vi) will prove useful. First, Aimee and Tony both envision that they win the football match (element (i)), and both attend to the field and to each other to achieve this shared goal (element (iv)). Second, Aimee knows that Tony is attending to the field and to the opposing team (the environment), to his actions, and to Aimee's actions. Third, Tony knows that Aimee knows about all this, and Aimee knows that Tony knows. In sum, Aimee and Tony share knowledge not only of their environment and actions, but also of each other's mental states, and so have mutual knowledge in a significant sense.

  1. (vii) S1 and S2 have mutual desire, which can be described in two parts. First, S1 desires that S2 share her goal. Second, S1 desires that S2 pursues a common action plan. Both participants want the other to want the same outcome (viz., the environment to be modified as envisioned in the mental model). Further, both participants want the other to want to act with her in achieving that outcome.

Returning to the previous example, Aimee desires that Tony have two desires of his own: first, she wants Tony to desire the same goal as her; second, she wants Tony to desire to act with her in realizing the envisioned state of affairs. Stated tersely: in shared intentionality, participants want to achieve a goal together.

In sum, elements (i)–(vii) are each necessary and together sufficient for the social psychological phenomenon of shared intentionality. This is important because, according to comparative and evolutionary psychologists, while some primates engage in elements (i)–(v), only humans engage in all seven.Footnote 17 Elements (vi) and (vii) are crucial because they transform a collective of individuals working in tandem into a social whole – a ‘we’. As Tomasello explains,

Although nonhuman animals may engage with one another in complex social interaction in which they know the goals of one another and exploit this, they are not motivated to create shared goals to which they are jointly committed in the same way as humans. (Tomasello, Carpenter, et al. (Reference Tomasello, Carpenter, Call, Behne and and Moll2005), 682)

The point cannot be stressed enough. In much human social activity, the participants do not merely desire some goal, or merely work collectively to achieve that goal. Instead, humans alone are motivated to act together to achieve their goals, where each participant desires that others want to pursue the goal with her.Footnote 18 Thus, element (vii) is the social motivational core of shared intentionality. Using our example: part of Aimee's goal is to win the football game. But this goal is folded into a larger goal, namely, to win the game with Anthony, and to want Anthony to want to win the game with her. It is the human social motivation for mutual desire that, along with the other elements, yields shared intentionality.

These findings about SI already provide anthropological grist for the mills of science-engaged-theologians. Limiting our attention to implications for the present article, we find that SI is critical for understanding uniquely human social activity. Specifically, humans create and develop complex social behaviours and artefacts, such as language and culture (e.g. money, marriage, and government).Footnote 19 However, creation and evolution of culture is dependent on the social motivations and activities described in the seven elements above. That is, the drive and complete package of skills necessary for learning language and first engaging in cultural practices are distinctively human. While not all instances of language and cultural engagement directly employ shared intentionality, a human's ability to learn and initially use language and culture do require it. In short, shared intentionality is a necessary precondition for all instances of language and culture.

To conclude this section, humans alone form a ‘we’, which arises from the complex mental states composing shared intentionality. The ‘we’ thus formed allows for, and is a necessary condition of, the even more complex social-cognitive activities that mark us out as distinctively human.Footnote 20 With these insights into SI from the psychological sciences, we may develop some lines of ramified natural theology, beginning with a SI variation on a traditional Anselmian theme.

Shared intentionality and perfect being theology: a deductive approach

In the rest of this article I consider key applications of the previous discussion for ramified natural theology. To do so, I outline and comment on several lines of argument that deploy the notion of shared intentionality. My aim, however, is not to provide full defences of those arguments. Instead, I want to investigate how the branch of psychology under discussion may most profitably be utilized by philosophers of religion, and test several philosophical-theology methodologies to determine which may be utilized with greatest advantage.

We may first apply SI by deploying it within the task and methods of Anselmian perfect being theology. Modifying a common line of perfect being argumentation, we may reason this way:

A perfect being argument Footnote 21

  1. 1. God is the greatest possible being.

  2. 2. The greatest possible being is one that has all perfections necessarily.

  3. 3. Shared intentionality is a perfection.

  4. 4. Therefore, God has shared intentionality.

  5. 5. If God has shared intentionality, then there are multiple divine persons.

  6. 6. Therefore, there are multiple divine persons.

The key claims in this argument are premises (3) and (5), namely, that shared intentionality is a perfection and that multiple divine persons share intentionality. Directing our attention to (3), we may view SI dispositionally, as a property which its subject is able and willing to act upon, given the appropriate conditions. The claim that SI is a perfection has some intuitive plausibility. For instance, SI is a property that, of all primates, only humans have, affording them the ability to engage in language and culture. Shared intentionality, then, is a valuable good and, arguably, one that a perfect being would necessarily have (i.e. a great-making property).Footnote 22

Premise (5) claims that God's intentionality must be shared among several divine persons. To support this claim, the Anselmian needs to show that God's shared intentionality is maximal, and that shared intentionality among divine and non-divine persons is not maximal. The latter requirement has some force: if God shares intentionality maximally, then no created person could possibly receive or understand – much less mutually share – the fullness of God's thoughts and desires.Footnote 23 However, philosophers of religion have recently questioned whether some divine perfections are the sorts of attributes that can be maximal.Footnote 24 It is not obvious that SI is a boundless property, that it has no upper limit. If SI is not maximal, then the proof fails at step (5).

Clearly I have not attempted a full defence of (3) or (5). Rather, I seek to demonstrate how Anselmian-style natural theology might defend such claims, and I draw out two important difficulties this methodology faces. First, SI may not be a maximal property, the type upon which Anselmian reasoning depends. Second, the perfect being argument deploys the notion of ‘perfections’ or ‘great-making properties’. But reasoning about perfections is subject to serious critique, as Edward Wierenga describes,

A second principle, enunciated by Anselm in Chapter 5 of the Proslogion, is that ‘God is whatever it is better to be than not to be’. In the contemporary idiom, God must possess every ‘great-making’ property. The problem lies in deciding which properties are ‘great-making’. Both in the past, and today, the enumeration of great-making properties has proceeded largely on the basis of intuition. For example, you ‘just see’ that something possessing reason is superior to something which does not . . . I find this plausible . . . but I fear that we can never quite escape the need for intuition. This may just be the nature of things when it comes to values. If you do not see that it is better to be able to do things and to think than not, that a cat is better than a rock, and a human better than a pig, it may be difficult to convince you. (Wierenga (Reference Wierenga2003), 12)

In short, reasoning along Anselmian lines is heavily dependent on intuition, a much-debated method of persuasion.

As a third difficulty, defending claims like those in (3) and (5) presumes that we know quite a bit about what God is like given our natural faculties of sense and reason – a presumption that Barth and other objectors to natural theology reject. In the face of such criticism, our case is strengthened by avoiding appeals to intuition when possible. I conclude that the perfect being argument finds a home in traditional perfect being theology and, given further attention, may prove to be a promising philosophical defence of multiple divine persons. However, because of objections like the three just mentioned, traditional perfect being theology is not universally appealing, and so a more persuasive approach would be welcome if one is available.

I believe that a more cogent approach is available. This approach is still deductive, and involves retaining the core insights of shared intentionality, but it tones down some of the maximality claims typically found in perfect being speculation:

A deductive argument

  1. 7. Shared intentionality is necessary for certain linguistic and cultural abilities.

  2. 8. A divine person has those linguistic and cultural abilities.

  3. 9. Therefore, a divine person has shared intentionality.

  4. 10. If a divine person has shared intentionality, then there are multiple divine persons.

  5. 11. Therefore, there are multiple divine persons.

This argument tempers our use of great-making properties and so is more appealing to contemporary audiences than the previous argument. The core claims are made in premises (7), (8), and (10), and I will say a little more about them.

Premise (7) does nothing more than summarize the findings of psychologists working in the field of shared intentionality, as I detailed in the previous section. The seven characteristics I outlined above constitute a necessary foundation for human language. Language, in turn, is necessary for further cultural activity, such as money, property, governments, and, as Searle (Reference Searle1996, 99–100) points out, meaning. Notice that (7) is stronger than the claim that the ability for shared intentionality is necessary for certain higher order abilities. For example, if it turns out that the great apes have the ability for shared intentionality, but never act on that ability, premise (7) would still be true. We should understand (7) as claiming that SI is a precondition for all language and culture, even if SI is not actively present in every instance of speech or cultural engagement.

Premise (8) is the claim that a divine person engages in at least some of the relevant cognitive and cultural activities. It is worth noting that the term ‘person’ here does not carry very much theological-philosophical-psychological freight. All that is needed for the argument to work is a divine actor or sharer of intentionality.Footnote 25 In regard to (8), we have good reason for thinking that omnipotence allows a divine person to read minds. That is, if there is at least one divine person – and in this article we assume that there is for the sake of argument – then that divine person understands what other agents are thinking, feeling, desiring, etc.Footnote 26 Implied in this reasoning is the conclusion that God has culture, which I have described as complex social behaviours and artefacts.

As another example of divine cognitive-cultural activity, we have good prima facie reasons to believe that God communicates with humans, evidenced by Judaeo-Christian scriptures and many purported cases of divine-to-human speech. Notice that this appeal to testimony is not an appeal to some particular proposition from any holy book, which would step outside the bounds of natural theology. Rather, the appeal is to the general and widespread phenomena of divine speech acts, of which the three monotheistic religions (and many other religions, besides) give putative evidence. Thus, if a divine person speaks with other agents or engages in cultural activity (e.g. instituting traditions like marriage), then a divine person must have shared intentionality with those agents. We see, then, that God communicates or speaks, which is one important cultural artefact. Moreover, if God is the creator of the world, then in an important sense the cosmos, too, is a cultural artefact. God therefore can be said to have culture in ways analogous to humanity.

Premise (10) is the claim that a divine person must share intentionality with at least one other divine person. (10) does not rule out the possibility that a divine person shares intentionality with human persons. Rather, (10) is compatible with (8), which expresses the idea that a divine person engages in ‘we’ relations with humans. Premise (10) extends this idea to other divine persons: if a divine person has ‘we’ or shared intentionality – and we have reason to believe a divine person does as per (8) – then that intentionality reaches beyond divine–human interpersonal relations to divine–divine interpersonal relations. Why think this is so? That is, why believe premise (10)?

One line of support can be offered along the direction developed by the twelfth-century thinker Richard of St Victor. Richard proposes that love for another, or ‘other-love’, is a supreme perfection. It is a perfection so good that God necessarily has it, and has it to the fullest possible degree: it cannot possibly be improved upon or increased in intensity (Angelici (Reference Angelici2011), 116–117; Richard of St Victor, De Trinitate, bk 3.2). In contemporary parlance, divine other-love is maximal.

According to Richard, divine other-love is perfect and so it is well-ordered to its object. Richard calls this caritas ordinata, or ‘ordered charity’. On this view, if a divine person loves the particular human Aimee, then he loves Aimee with the type of love appropriate to her as a human. Thus, a divine person does not love Aimee with the love had for a log or for a dog (nor does the divine person love a dog as if it were a human). Further, a divine person loves Aimee with the love appropriate to Aimee in her particularity as Aimee. Thus, a divine person's love for Aimee takes different shape than the love extended to Anthony or to Nichole. In sum, divine love matches its object according to that object's kind and according to its particularity. Richard concludes that God does not love humans with maximal other-love. Indeed, maximal love is well-ordered only when it is shared between divine persons.

The proponent of the deductive argument could support premise (10) by arguing along a parallel route as Richard. Here we would need to show how divine shared intentionality, like divine other-love, can only be maximal when it is shared among divine persons. However, this line of reasoning once again brings us into talk about maximal attributes – conceptual territory that is contested, as we saw in the perfect being argument. Thus, there are sound deductive arguments available to the natural theologian that deploy the psychology of shared intentionality. However, it is not clear to me that any deductive arguments are available that do need to deploy some sort of maximality thesis.

To conclude this section, the deductive argument attempts to improve upon the perfect being argument by limiting the number of instances in which it relies on intuitions, and as much as possible replaces a priori claims with empirical findings from the psychological field of shared intentionality. Even with these modifications, the deductive argument still uses claims about divine maximality, and so may be a bridge too far.

Looking for another method of reasoning that employs the findings of the psychological sciences more persuasively, one excellent candidate appears to be the relatively neglected field of analogical reasoning. Analogical reasoning is much more common than deduction, and its epistemic criteria are far less demanding. Further, analogical arguments fit more naturally with the field of shared intentionality, and with the psychological sciences generally. Deploying the findings of we intentionality in an argument by analogy may prove to be significantly more promising than traditional, deductive inference.

Below I will develop a line of analogical reasoning about shared intentionality and multiple persons, both human and divine. Before investigating that argument, a few brief notes on analogy and analogical arguments will be useful for understanding this (often neglected) form of reasoning, and for helping us appreciate its power as a tool for natural theology.

Analogies, analogical reasoning, and analogical arguments

We may begin by distinguishing between analogies, analogical reasoning, and analogical arguments (Bartha Reference Bartha2022). An analogy compares two items (the analogues), identifying respects in which they are similar. Most analogies start with an analogue that is more familiar to us (the source analogue) and then make comparisons and conclusions about an analogue that is understood less well (the target analogue).

Analogical reasoning is a mode of inference that employs an analogy. Analogical reasoning is especially pertinent in the present discussion for at least two reasons. First, cognitive scientists widely recognize that analogical reasoning is, by a significant margin, the most common form of human day-to-day reasoning (Gentner and Smith Reference Gentner, Smith and Ramachandran2012). Second, analogies and analogical reasoning play critical roles in scientific thought (Bailer-Jones Reference Bailer-Jones, Machamer and Silberstein2002). Thus in the middle part of the eighteenth century, Joseph Priestley, an early worker in the chemical and electrical sciences, could aver that ‘analogy is our best guide in all philosophical investigations; and all discoveries, which were not made by mere accident, have been made by the help of it’ (Reference Priestley1966, 14). Stated another way, analogies are crucial for deductive, and especially inductive and abductive, reasoning.Footnote 27 For this reason, analogies are not only prevalent in the sciences, but have long been employed in Christian theologizing, and particularly in trinitarian theology.Footnote 28

Analogical arguments are a more explicit, often formalized mode of analogical reasoning. Stated roughly, an analogical argument proceeds in two steps: first, two objects are shown to be the same in some respects; second, from these similarities, it is concluded that the two objects are the same in some further respect. Most textbooks give analogical arguments something like the following basic formalization:

Basic analogical form

  1. 12. Object 1 (the source analogue) has characteristic F and G.

  2. 13. Object 2 (the target analogue) has characteristic F.

  3. 14. Therefore, object 2 has characteristic G.

We will adapt this generalized formulation into a more sophisticated formulation, below. For now, though, the basic form allows us to note a few important features of analogical arguments. First, the objects or class of objects being compared may be a same-domain comparison (such as two groups of planets), or a different-domain comparison (such as planets and atoms). Second, the analogues must share at least one, and possibly many more characteristics (viz., the known similarities). Typically, there is only one characteristic which appears in the conclusion (viz., the inferred similarity).

Third, regarding the conclusion itself, most introductory texts claim that arguments by analogy are purely ampliative, that is, they only generate probable conclusions. However, logicians currently working on the nature and function of analogical arguments challenge the textbook view (Davies Reference Davies and Helman1988), arguing that the force of analogical conclusions is quite varied: the conclusions of analogical arguments may be possible, probable, or epistemically conclusive (though they do not follow of logical necessity, as in deductive arguments).

The preceding three features show up in the analogical arguments presented in the next section. Before turning to those arguments, it is important to note a fourth and final feature. While analogical reasoning can show a conclusion to be plausible or probable, this is a task at which inductive arguments tend to excel. Analogy, though, has a variety of functions, as befits their pervasive use. One of their most important capacities is to show that some conclusion or line of inquiry is fruitful for its field and worthy of further investigation (Bartha Reference Bartha2022). We find that analogical arguments can (to borrow from Kuhn's description of fruitfulness in scientific theory), ‘disclose new phenomena or previously unnoted relationships among those already known’ (Kuhn (Reference Kuhn1977), 322).

One powerful function of analogical arguments is to direct our attention to some trajectory of thought, underscoring its worthiness for further pursuit (Ivani Reference Ivani2019). This is how Thomas Reid deployed his argument by analogy for life on other planets, leading Bartha to conclude: ‘Often the point of an analogical argument is just to persuade people to take an idea seriously’ (Bartha Reference Bartha2022). As Reid did in cosmology, theologians and philosophers of religion may construct fruitful analogical arguments in their own fields. It is in this role that I will deploy shared intentionality to develop some analogical arguments about human and divine persons.

Shared intentionality and divine persons: an analogical approach

To date, analogical reasoning is found in RNT only in arguments for the resurrection of Jesus (Fuller (Reference Fuller1966); McGrew and McGrew (Reference McGrew, McGrew, Craig and Moreland2012), 622–628). These arguments deploy a ‘principle of analogy’ in analogical reasoning, but do not advance any analogical argumentation. Thus, RNT is a field ripe for analogical harvest. Taking initial steps towards this end, I will start with a simple analogical argument following the basic form outlined in the previous section:

Basic analogical argument

  1. 15. Humans engage in (i) mind reading, (ii) speaking, (iii) creating and participating in culture, and (iv) sharing intentions.

  2. 16. God engages in (i) mind reading, (ii) speaking, (iii) creating and participating in culture.

  3. 17. Therefore, (iv) God engages in sharing intentions.

‘Mind reading’ in premise (15) refers to the activity of understanding mental states of others, such as beliefs, intentions, desires, emotions. Mind reading allows for, and perhaps includes, the mind reader's act of anticipating the actions of others. ‘Speaking’ refers to complex communication via symbols which allows for the intentional transmission of information, as well as other perlocutionary acts. ‘Creating and engaging in culture’ – or ‘culturate’ for short – refers to the development of novel forms of culture (such as creating the practice of marriage), developing tokens of cultural activities (such as creating the practice of getting married on a boat), and involvement in cultural practices (such as serving as the bridesmaid in a cruise-ship wedding).

The basic analogical argument given above does a fine job of expressing the main idea: divinity and humanity are both characterized by a network of closely related social and cognitive psychological attributes and relations. Since God and humans have attributes and relations (i) through (iii), we may conclude by analogy that God also has (iv).Footnote 29

Scholars in the field of informal logic have seen that the basic form of analogical arguments can be improved. For instance, the logician André Juthe (Reference Juthe2005) recently advanced a formal structure for analogical arguments which highlights their strengths and their resistance to some common critique. The argument below follows Juthe's formal structure:

Improved analogical argument

  1. 18. God (i) reads minds, (ii) speaks, (iii) creates and engages in culture (i.e. culturates).

  2. 19. Humans (iv) share intentionality in virtue of (i) reading minds, and as a condition for (ii) speaking and (iii) culturating.

  3. 20. Human mind reading, speaking, and creating and engaging in culture are counterparts of God's mind reading, speaking, and culturating.

  4. 21. Therefore, God shares intentionality.

The improved analogical argument retains the essential features of analogical arguments that we encountered in the basic analogical argument, above. For instance, the improved argument begins with particular objects of common experience (viz. humans), to reason by analogy about a particular object which is less commonly experienced (viz. God).Footnote 30 While preserving core features of analogical argumentation, the improved analogical argument uses two concepts not seen in the basic analogical argument, namely, the ‘in virtue of’ relation, and the notion of ‘counterparts’. We will examine these concepts and the argument's more complex structure. We will then evaluate the argument itself.

Premise (19) of the improved analogical argument states that humans share intentionality ‘in virtue of’ mind reading. Typically, ‘in virtue of’ (and ‘on the basis of’ and ‘based on’) is understood as a grounding relation, which is itself a debated notion. Here I seek to avoid any larger discussions about grounding relations, instead limiting my attention specifically to the relationship between shared intentionality and mind reading.

Mind reading relates to shared intentionality in that the former is a necessary condition for the latter. That is, S1's activity in understanding S2's mental states and anticipating S2's actions is required for S1 to share intentionality with S2. Note that the mere ability for mind reading is not sufficient for SI. In terms of dispositions, the disposition for mind reading must be activated for SI to also be activated. Stated again, when S1 is sharing intentionality with S2, S1 is also mind reading with respect to S2. Thus, mind reading is not merely modal. It is a ground for SI as a constitutive condition: SI is constituted, at least in part, by the manifested disposition of mind reading.

Shared intentionality stands at the opposite side of the grounding relation to speaking and culturating as it does to mind reading. Where mind reading is a necessary condition that partially constitutes SI, SI itself is a necessary precondition of speech and culturating. Thus, SI stands at the centre of a complex chain of activities which are uniquely human. Further, each activity in the chain partially constitutes activities later in the chain (see the figures below).

Premise (20) contains a claim about counterparts, which is a condition for the validity of analogical arguments (Weizenfeld Reference Weizenfeld1984). Counterpart features, or simply counterparts, do the heavy lifting in showing that two objects are analogous in some respect. The idea is that two objects are analogous in some way if those two objects are proportionate in certain respects. ‘Proportionate’ here refers to the relational structures had by the two objects. Recall that the source analogue is the object more known by experience, and the target analogue is the object less known. We may conclude that the target analogue shares the assigned predicate with the source analogue by showing that both analogues share a relational structure in which the inferred similarity fits. Specifically, the features of the source analogue under consideration stand in certain relations to each other.

Further, features of the target analogue also stand in certain relations to each other. When the features of the source and target analogues stand in the same relations, those features are properly proportionate to one another and make for a good analogical argument. Stated another way, when the known similarities of the source analogue and of the target analogue are counterparts, then an important condition has been met for the validity of an argument by analogy. As a helpful image, we may imagine two chains, each with ten links. Each link plays a special role in making the chain functional, and each link needs to be in its particular numerically ordered place for the chain to hold together. We regularly use the first chain and so are quite familiar with it. We are less experientially familiar with the second chain because it lies high on an upper shelf where we cannot touch it; we can only see nine of its ten links (all but the fifth link). Comparing the two chains, we see that links one to four and six to ten of the second chain are all quite similar with their counterparts in the first chain. Since the nine links in the second chain match their counterparts in the first chain, we have good reason for thinking the fifth link also matches. Further, since the fifth link in the first chain needs to be there for the chain to function, we have even more reason to think that the second chain has its own similar fifth link that is necessary to the chain's functioning.

The analogy has its limits, of course, but helps us see the basic logic at work in the improved argument: the similar property about which we are inferring sits in the middle of other closely connected relations and properties. We may diagram the general notion of counterparts (Figure 1).

Figure 1. Counterparts.

In this figure the target analogue has counterparts of all the source analogue's features/activities and relations – except, of course, for the target similarity, which is the feature under consideration in the analogy. The solid lines ending with an arrow and the dotted lines indicate types of relations in the structure. The following figure applies this general schema to our improved argument (Figure 2).

Figure 2. Human and divine social-psychological structures.

This figure helps us visualize the cluster of human and divine social-psychological mental states and activities. For example, we see that shared intentionality depends on mind reading; speech and cultural engagement stand in some interesting relation to one another, and both depend on shared intentionality. Further, shared intentionality is situated in the middle of this complex social-psychological cluster. Putting divine shared intentionality to the side for the moment, we also see that all features/activities and relations in the divine structure are structurally proportionate to the human features and their relations. In short, the human features and relations have divine counterparts. This successful analogy yields good reason for concluding that a feature which is had by humans – namely, shared intentionality – is also present in divine psychology.

One asset of the improved argument is that it does not claim that humans and God have a psychology in exactly the same sense. This alerts us to another reason analogical arguments are so well-suited to RNT, and to natural theology generally: analogical reasoning takes no stance on the univocity or analogy of predicates about divinity; the improved analogical argument is sound whether or not our language about God is analogical.Footnote 31 Further, this argument avoids simplistic types of objections often found in textbook, such as Hume's critique of analogical relevancy. Briefly put, logicians are making it increasingly clear that analogical arguments are more sophisticated than previously thought and, when given well-formed expression, are highly resilient to some common critiques (Weizenfeld Reference Weizenfeld1984).

More importantly, and more central to Christian natural theology, we may note that the improved argument does not make claims about the existence of multiple divine persons, but rather advances a more modest conclusion for divine shared intentionality. This conclusion can serve as a basis for further RNT investigation and may be used in several mutually complementary lines of inquiry. For example, the analogy may be extended to include reasoning about the nature of the participants in shared intentionality. Here we might reason along the following analogical trajectory: for any human, she shares intentionality with a similar type of person (viz. other humans); by analogy, we have good reason to believe that any divine person shares intentionality with similar type of persons (viz. other divine persons).

As another line of inquiry, we could draw further from the psychology of we intentionality. Promising psychological resources include the social-psychological motivation for reciprocal, even commensurate social wholes. That is, humans not only form ‘we's, but humans also aim for a we in which the participants share coordinate (or proportionate) intensity of desires, mental acuity, and active contributions to environmental manipulation. Put roughly: people typically desire and work towards collectives in which every member has an equal volitional, emotional, intellectual, and practical share. We may conclude by analogy that a divine person desires collectives in which members have commensurate psychological (volitional, intellective, etc.) stake. But – per Richard of St Victor – a divine person's desires and cognitive capacities can be matched only by other divine persons. Here we have a possible line of argument for multiple divine persons that does not depend on notions of maximality or perfections, but instead reasons by analogy.

Clearly, the two analogies just suggested are initial ‘proof-of-concept’ proposals, and they will need development to be valid analogical arguments and to be at all cogent. But these trajectories do indicate a way forward in trinitarian natural theology that both employs the empirical sciences and does not depend on Anselmian-style perfect being theology. Moreover, they reveal that RNT can incorporate work from the sciences and that such a project evidences some fruitful findings worthy of attention by psychologists, philosophers of religion, and integrative theologians.

Conclusion

My goals in this article have purposefully been quite modest: I have explored a recent philosophical-theological research question (ramified natural theology) that takes certain empirical data seriously (shared intentionality). Towards that end, I introduced some main ideas of the field of SI and explored a deductive and analogical approach for employing these ideas in RNT. The article is exploratory in that it sought to identify a strong fit between the psychology of SI and the discursive methods of RNT. My aim here was to investigate whether shared intentionality presents a fruitful source for thinking about divine social-cognition; that is, whether SI and RNT yield new lines of inquiry, or new ways of thinking about the question of divine plurality. I found that analogical arguments provide a strong medium for deploying SI. The analogical arguments I sketched argued for divine shared intentionality, giving a trajectory for further research into divine personal plurality. Shared intentionality, then, looks to be a promising dialogue partner with natural theologians concerned with philosophical analysis of multiple divine persons.

Acknowledgements

This article is the result of a John Templeton Foundation fellowship for cross-training in the empirical sciences, awarded by the Society of Christian Philosophers. I thank the SCP, particularly Kevin Timpe and Christian Miller, for their patient assistance. I am also grateful to Malinda Carpenter and Gideon Psalter at the University of St Andrews for their teaching and guidance on shared intentionality.

Footnotes

1. William Alston (Reference Alston1991, 289) describes it this way:

Natural theology is the enterprise of providing support for religious beliefs by starting from premises that neither are nor presuppose any religious beliefs . . . in this manner we try to go as far as we can in building up a picture of God without relying on any supposed experience of God or communication from God, or on any religious authority.

2. For a good place to start see Craig and Moreland (Reference Craig and Moreland2012), 1–23.

3. A term coined by Swinburne (Reference Swinburne2004b).

4. The locus classicus is Swinburne (Reference Swinburne2004a).

5. See the RNT themed issue of Philosophia Christi 15.2 (2013).

6. Perhaps more accurate: modern arguments are inspired by their forebearers, since many contemporary arguments bear no obvious dependence relation on the originals. Many of the best examples occurred in the early Boyle Lectures, such as William Derham's early eighteenth-century work, ‘Physico-Theology, or a Demonstration of the Being and Attributes of God from his Works of Creation’ (Burnet Reference Burnet2000) and Robert Hooke's late seventeenth-century Micrographia (Fara Reference Fara2009).

7. One prominent example is John Polkinghorne (Reference Polkinghorne2008, 66‒95; Reference Polkinghorne2003), who advocates for ‘consonance’ between science and theology (of which natural theology is a sub-discipline).

8. Rodney Holder (Reference Holder2021), recently of the Faraday Institute for Science and Religion, uses specific sciences as parallels for certain RNT methods but he does not employ the findings of those sciences in his own arguments.

9. Because shared intentionality is still new and so inter- and intra-disciplinary, it is difficult to say what represents a consensus view. Though there is debate, as is to be expected, the account detailed in this section is very well represented in the scholarly literature and may indeed be the majority position. I primarily follow the accounts developed by Tomasello, Carpenter, et al. (Reference Tomasello, Carpenter, Call, Behne and and Moll2005) and Tomasello and Carpenter (Reference Tomasello and Carpenter2007), who are both pioneers and leading experts in the field, and certainly thinkers with whom any other voices in the conversation must engage.

10. These three philosophers are consistently cited throughout the scientific literature. See Searle (Reference Searle1996); Gilbert (Reference Gilbert1992); Tuomela (Reference Tuomela1995). Also cited often is Bratman (Reference Bratman1999; Reference Bratman2014).

11. To iterate: this article limits its attention to the use of ‘shared intentionality’ developed by proponents working in the psychological sciences. Thus, not everything that could plausibly be called shared intentionality in a general understanding of those terms, or in the technical sense used by analytic philosophers, will count as shared intentionality as I use the term.

12. A fine place to start is the special issue of Behavioral and Brain Sciences (Tomasello et al. Reference Tomasello, Carpenter, Call, Behne and and Moll2005). This article and others cited in the current section reference the studies which provide empirical data for the seven conditions detailed in this section.

13. Psychologists are largely aware of the philosophical use of ‘intention’ as referring to any mental state that has ‘aboutness’. Most often, though, psychologists use the term in reference to the possible state of affairs, that is, the mental model.

14. Shared intentionality may obtain in the absence of element (iii). That is, a group of people can form a ‘we’ in regard to some goal even if they have not yet acted on their shared goals. In such a case we could modify (iii) to read that ‘S1 and S2 both engage, or are disposed to engage, in some behaviour.’ However, activity is critical for a robust understanding of SI because humans often form social wholes (a ‘we’) precisely to achieve some outcome together. Humans are motivated to act together not merely because in so doing their goal is better achieved. Instead, the motivation stems in part from the payoff of working towards a goal together (which includes all seven elements outlined in this section). On the dispositional analysis of we-intentions, see Tuomela (Reference Tuomela1995, 112–170).

15. There is debate among psychologists on whether joint attention is a precursor (a necessary condition) of mind reading, or whether it is an early instance of mind reading itself. I find Tomasello et al.'s proposal for the latter view convincing. However, my project works fine with either view. For the mind reading view, see Tomasello et al. (Reference Tomasello, Kruger and Ratner1993). For an alternative proposal, see Leslie (Reference Leslie1987).

16. It also allows the mind reader to empathize (Morin and Racy (Reference Morin, Racy and Rauthmann2021), 375–376).

17. Thus Tomasello et al.:

in addition to understanding others as intentional, rational agents, humans also possess some kind of more specifically social capacity that gives them the motivation and cognitive skills to feel, experience, and act together with others – what we may call . . . shared (or ‘we’) intentionality. As the key social-cognitive skill for cultural creation and cognition, shared intentionality is of special importance in explaining the uniquely powerful cognitive skills of Homo sapiens. (Tomasello et al. (Reference Tomasello, Carpenter, Call, Behne and and Moll2005), 687)

18. ‘[C]ommunicating only to share interest in things and communicating only to share information seem to be uniquely human’ (Tomasello et al. (Reference Tomasello, Carpenter, Call, Behne and and Moll2005), 687).

19. There is some debate over the relationship between we intentionality, speech, and culture (Gergely and Csibra (Reference Gergely and Csibra2005); Baldwin (Reference Baldwin, Moore and Dunham2016)). Since all participants agree that SI is necessary for language and culture, nothing in my project rides on the debate's outcome.

20. The claim here is not that the cluster of social-cognitive activities is sufficient for human uniqueness; rather, the claim is merely that they are a necessary condition.

21. The following argument is adapted from Murray and Rea (Reference Murray and Rea2008), 132.

22. For a discussion of great-making properties, and of issues about maximality, see the recent article by Mastoridis (Reference Mastoridis2020).

23. A divine person cannot share intentionality with itself, since by definition SI is shared among multiple subjects (as described in elements (i)–(vii) in section 2).

24. See Murphy (Reference Murphy2017); cf. Rea (Reference Rea2018), 63–89.

25. For the purposes of this argument we could just as easily say ‘divine agent’ or ‘divine who’.

26. I take no stance on whether a divine person has this knowledge immediately, as on the classical understanding of God's omniscience, or whether a divine person gains such knowledge discursively or inferentially, as on a process or open view of God's knowledge.

28. The best general treatment of analogy in theology is probably still Woods (Reference Woods1956); see also McFague (Reference McFague1982).

29. One concern might be that theologians could make an analogical argument from human social-psychological activities such as stereotyping, judging biasedly, and gossiping. True, analogical reasoning does not prevent us from using these inputs to reach conclusions about divine bias, gossip, etc. However, the psychological structure in which these activities are embedded is deeply flawed, both internally to the gossiping agent, and externally in the social structure of S1 and S2 speaking ill of S3 without S3 knowing. Minimally, then, such analogies lose significant intuitive force and cogency. (Though analogical arguments do not depend on intuition as do Anselmian-type arguments, intuition and audience background beliefs always play a role in how an argument is understood and evaluated.)

30. Analogical arguments reason particular-to-particular, and so seem to be distinct from deductive arguments which often reason general-to-particular, inductive particular-to-general, and abductive general-to-general. However, analogy, like induction, reasons from that which is more known by experience to that which is less known. For these and other reasons the taxonomy is debated, and nothing in my case rides on whether analogy (or abductive inference, too) is a species of induction.

31. The language used in the premises of the analogical arguments must match for the argument to be valid. That is, if we say that human persons ‘create culture’ or ‘speak’, we must predicate these same actions of divine persons for a well-formed argument. However, though the language or terms used to predicate qualities of divine and human persons is the same, nothing about the argument requires the mode of predication to be univocal. Indeed, it is not true that all humans speak in exactly the same way (some use spoken words, others use sign-language). As I have presented them, the analogical arguments allow for predicates to be used and understood analogically, though the precise sense of analogy (or univocity) must be further worked out in a full presentation of the argument.

References

Alston, W (1991) Perceiving God. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Angelici, R (2011) Richard of Saint Victor, On the Trinity: English Translation and Commentary. Eugene, OR: Cascade Books.Google Scholar
Bailer-Jones, D (2002) Models, metaphors and analogies. In Machamer, P and Silberstein, M (eds), Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science. Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 108127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baldwin, D (2016) Understanding the link between joint attention and language. In Moore, C and Dunham, PJ (eds), Joint Attention: Its Origins and Role in Development. New York: Psychology Press, pp. 131158.Google Scholar
Bartha, P (2022) Analogy and analogical reasoning. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Zalta, Edward (ed.). Available at https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2022/entries/reasoning-analogy/.Google Scholar
Bratman, M (1999) Faces of Intention: Selected Essays on Intention and Agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratman, M (2014) Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnet, G (2000) Boyle Lectures (1692–1732): A Defence of Natural and Revealed Religion, Being an Abridgement of the Sermons Preached at the Lectures Founded by Robert Boyle. Bristol: Thoemmes.Google Scholar
Craig, WL and Moreland, JP (eds) (2012) The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Davies, TR (1988) Determination, uniformity, and relevance: normative criteria generalization and reasoning by analogy. In Helman, DH (ed.), Analogical Reasoning: Perspectives of Artificial Intelligence, Cognitive Science, and Philosophy. Kluwer: Dordrecht, pp. 227259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, S (2006) Christian Philosophical Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fara, P (2009) A microscopic reality tale. Nature 459, 642644.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fuller, D (1966) The resurrection of Jesus and the historical method. Journal of Bible and Religion 34, 1824.Google Scholar
Gentner, D and Smith, L (2012) Analogical reasoning. In Ramachandran, VS (ed.), Encyclopedia of Human Behavior, 2nd edn. London: Elsevier, pp. 130136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gergely, G and Csibra, G (2005) A few reasons why we don't share Tomasello et al's intuitions about sharing. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28, 701702.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, M (1992) On Social Facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Habermas, G and Licona, M (2004) The Case for the Resurrection of Jesus. Grand Rapids, MI: Kregal Publications.Google Scholar
Holder, R (2021) Ramified Natural Theology in Science and Religion: Moving Forward from Natural Theology. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ivani, S (2019) What we (should) talk about when we talk about fruitfulness. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 9, 118.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Juthe, A (2005) Argument by analogy. Argumentation 19, 127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klix, F (2001) Problem solving: deduction, induction, and analogical reasoning. In Baltes, P and Smelser, N (eds), The International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences. Amsterdam: Elsevier, pp. 1212312130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T (1977) Objectivity, value judgement, and theory choice. In The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, pp. 320339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leslie, A (1987) Pretence and representation: the origins of ‘theory of mind’. Psychological Review 94, 412426.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mastoridis, P (2020) Making great-making properties great again. Dialogue: Journal of Phi Sigma Tau 62, 144151.Google Scholar
McFague, S (1982) Metaphorical Theology. Philadelphia, PA: Fortress Press.Google Scholar
McGrew, T and McGrew, L (2012) The argument from miracles: a cumulative case for the resurrection of Jesus of Nazareth. In Craig, WL and Moreland, JP (eds), The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 593662.Google Scholar
Melis, A, Hare, B and Tomasello, M (2006) Chimpanzees recruit the best collaborators. Science 311, 12971300.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Moreland, JP and Craig, WL (2003) Philosophical Foundations for a Christian Worldview. Downers Grove, IL: Inter-Varsity Press, pp. 594595.Google Scholar
Morin, A and Racy, F (2021) Dynamic self-processes. In Rauthmann, J (ed.), The Handbook of Personality Dynamics and Processes. London: Academic Press, pp. 375376.Google Scholar
Murphy, M (2017) God's Own Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 2244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murray, M and Rea, M (2008) An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, J and Leidenhag, J (2021) What is science-engaged theology? Modern Theology 37, 245253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, J and Leidenhag, J (2023) Science-Engaged Theology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polkinghorne, J (2003) Physics and metaphysics in a Trinitarian perspective. Theology and Science 1, 3349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polkinghorne, J (2008) Theology in the Context of Science. London: SPCK.Google Scholar
Priestley, J (1966) The History and Present State of Electricity. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rea, M (2018) The Hiddenness of God. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J (1996) The Construction of Social Reality. New York, NY: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R (2004a) The Existence of God, 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, R (2004b) Natural theology, its ‘dwindling probabilities’ and ‘lack of rapport’. Faith and Philosophy 21, 533546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomasello, M (1995) Joint attention as social cognition. In Moore, C and Dunham, PJ (eds), Joint Attention: Its Origins and Role in Development. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc., pp. 103130.Google Scholar
Tomasello, M and Carpenter, M (2007) Shared intentionality. Developmental Sciences 10, 121125.Google ScholarPubMed
Tomasello, M, Kruger, AC, and Ratner, HH (1993) Cultural learning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16, 495552.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomasello, M, Carpenter, M, Call, J, Behne, T, and Moll, H (2005) Understanding and sharing intentions: the origins of cultural cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28, 691735.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tuomela, R (1995) The Importance of Us: Philosophical Study of Basic Social Notions. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Weizenfeld, JS (1984) Valid reasoning by analogy. Philosophy of Science 51, 137149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wierenga, E (2003) The Nature of God: An Inquiry into Divine Attributes. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, GF (1956) The use of analogy in Christian theology. The Journal of Theological Studies 7, 226238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Counterparts.

Figure 1

Figure 2. Human and divine social-psychological structures.