Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T11:58:36.622Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bourdieu and the dead end of reflexivity: On the impossible task of locating the subject

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 June 2015

Abstract

This article examines recent attempts by International Relations (IR) scholars to flesh out a reflexive approach inspired by the work of Pierre Bourdieu. The French sociologist pioneered the idea of turning the tools of sociology onto oneself in order to apply the same grid of social analysis to the object and subject of scholarship. This represents the culmination of a long tradition of seeking to understand from where one speaks and grasp our subjective biases through reflexive means. But as I argue Bourdieu – like most reflexive scholars – largely overestimated his ability to grasp his own subject position. For he assumed he could be objective about the very thing he had the least reasons to be objective about: himself. Instead of bending over backwards in this way and directly take the subject into account, I then propose to rearticulate the problematic of reflexivity by going back to a more classic concern with the question of alienation. Through a detailed critique of Bourdieu’s reflexive approach and the ways in which it was received in IR, I set out a series of principles to reconfigure the agenda of reflexivity and offer a platform for a proper methodological alternative to positivism.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© 2015 British International Studies Association 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

I would like to thank Sahil Dutta, Julian Germann, Xavier Guillaume, Matthew Hughes, Daniel Jacobi, Martijn Konings, Richard Lane, Lara Montesinos-Coleman, Dinah Rajak, Jan Selby, Benno Teschke, Steffan Wyn-Jones, and three anonymous reviewers for their comments and constructive engagement with this article in its formative stages.

References

1 Cox, Robert W., ‘Social forces, states and world orders: Beyond International Relations theory’, Millenium: Journal of International Studies, 10:2 (1981), p. 128CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Neufeld, Mark, The Restructuring of International Relations Theory (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Guzzini, Stefano, ‘Structural power: the limits of neorealist power analysis’, International Organization, 47:3 (1993), pp. 443478CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Guillaume, Xavier, ‘Reflexivity and subjectivity: a dialogical perspective for and on International Relations theory’, Social Research, 3:3 (2002)Google Scholar; Leander, Anna, ‘Do we really need reflexivity in IPE? Bourdieu’s two reasons for answering affirmatively’, Review of International Political Economy, 9:4 (2002), pp. 601609CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hamati-Ataya, Inanna, ‘Reflectivity, reflexivity, reflexivism – IR’s reflexive turn – and beyond’, European Journal of International Relations, 19:4 (2013), pp. 669–694CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 Bourdieu, Pierre, Sketch for a Self-Analysis (Cambridge: Polity, 2007)Google Scholar.

5 Pouliot, Vincent, ‘Sobjectivism – toward a constructivist methodology’, International Studies Quarterly, 51:3 (2007), pp. 359–384CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Eagleton-Pierce, Matthew, ‘Advancing a reflexive International Relations’, Millennium, 39:3 (2011), pp. 805–823CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hamati-Ataya, Inanna, ‘Transcending objectivism, subjectivism, and the knowledge in-between: the subject in/of “strong reflexivity”’, Review of International Studies, 40:1 (2014), pp. 153–175CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Jackson, Patrick Thaddeus, The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations (London: Routledge, 2011)Google Scholar; Salter, Mark and Mutlu, Can (eds), Research Methods in Critical Security Studies: An Introduction (London: Routledge, 2012)Google Scholar.

7 Guzzini, Stefano, ‘A reconstruction of constructivism in International Relations’, European Journal of International Relations, 6:2 (2000), pp. 147–182CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Guzzini, , ‘A reconstruction’, p. 162Google Scholar.

9 Pouliot, Vincent, International Security in Practice: The Politics of NATO-Russia Diplomacy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Bigo, Didier, ‘Pierre Bourdieu and International Relations: Power of practices, practices of power’, International Political Sociology, 5:3 (2011), pp. 225–258CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Mérand, Frédéric and Pouliot, Vincent, ‘Le monde de Pierre Bourdieu: Éléments pour une théorie sociale des Relations internationales’, Canadian Journal of Political Science, 41:3 (2008), pp. 603–625CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 Wacquant, Loïc, ‘The structure and logic of Bourdieu’s sociology’, in Pierre Bourdieu and Loïc Wacquant (ed.), An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology (London: University of Chicago Press, 1992), p 40Google Scholar.

12 Madsen, Mikael Rask, ‘Reflexivity and the construction of the international object: the case of human rights’, International Political Sociology, 5:1 (2011), pp. 259275CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Bourdieu, Pierre and Wacquant, Loïc, An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology, p. 204Google Scholar.

14 Bourdieu, Pierre, ‘Participant objectivation’, The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, 9:2 (2003), p. 283CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 Mérand, and Pouliot, , ‘Le monde’, p. 607Google Scholar.

16 Bourdieu, Pierre, Homo Academicus (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988)Google Scholar.

17 Leander, , ‘Do we really need reflexivity?’, p. 604Google Scholar.

18 Guillaume, Xavier, ‘Foreign policy and the politics of alterity: a dialogical understanding of International Relations’, Millennium, 31:1 (2002), p. 21CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Leander, , ‘Do we really need reflexivity?’, p. 602Google Scholar.

20 Leander, Anna, ‘The promises, problems, and potentials of a Bourdieu-inspired staging of International Relations’, International Political Sociology, 5:3 (2011), p. 307CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

21 Eagleton-Pierce, , ‘Advancing a reflexive International Relations’, p. 12Google Scholar.

22 Hamati-Ataya, , ‘Reflectivity, reflexivity, reflexivism’, p. 14Google Scholar.

23 Harding, Sandra, ‘After the neutrality ideal: Science, politics, and “Strong Objectivity”’, Social Research, 59:3 (1992), p. 574Google Scholar.

24 Lapid, Yosef, ‘The third debate: On the prospects of international theory in a post-positivist era’, International Studies Quarterly, 33:3 (1989), pp. 235–254CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Gill, Stephen, ‘Epistemology, ontology and the “Italian School”’, in Stephen Gill (ed.), Gramsci, Historical Materialism and International Relations (Cambridge 1993), pp. 21–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ackerly, Brooke A., Stern, Maria, and True, Jacqui, ‘Feminist methodologies for International Relations’, Feminist methodologies for International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), pp. 1–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 Jackson, Thaddeus, The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations: Philosophy of Science and Its Implications for the Study of World Politics (London: Routledge, 2010), p. 182Google Scholar.

26 Leander, Anna, ‘Thinking tools’, in Audie Klotz and Deepa Prakash (eds), Qualitative Methods in International Relations: A Pluralist Guide (London: Palgrave, 2009), p. 26Google Scholar.

27 It might be argued that Bourdieu himself did not fall in this trap since he was sceptical of the idea of objectivity. But the point is moot in that even if we adopt a softer conception of objectivity based on intersubjectivity, as Bourdieu did, the problem remains exactly the same. For the issue here is the promise that knowledge about the self can be produced for an intersubjective realm, such as the one that defines a social scientific community, in order to ground knowledge claims. Bourdieu’s wager is that intersubjective standards can anchor a reflexive engagement with the self which helps control bias. But producing intersubjective knowledge about the self, regardless of the standard to which this production is subjected, will end up confronting the same problems because of the conflicts of interest that are the heart of this strategy. Ultimately, such a project underestimates how these very standards can be easily turned around and be exploited to produce the very opposite of what they intend to do, as I argue below.

28 On this front, it must be noted that the feminist literature is perhaps alone in IR in having offered specific interventions which address more directly the problem of moral ambiguity involved in scholarship. See Dauphinee, Elizabeth, ‘The ethics of autoethnography’, Review of International Studies, 36:3 (2010), pp. 799–818CrossRefGoogle Scholar. But it is important to note that these only succeed precisely when they keep the terrain circumscribed to the personal; a terrain that is fully liable to the problems of self-understanding that I later outline as powerfully demonstrated by Hamati-Ataya. See Hamati-Ataya, ‘Transcending objectivism’.

29 Bourdieu, Sketch.

30 Bourdieu, Pierre, ‘Concluding remarks for a sociogenetic understanding of intellectual works’, in Craig Calhoun, Edward Lipuma, and Moishe Postone (eds), Bourdieu: Critical Perspectives (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993), p. 269Google Scholar.

31 Jenkins, Richard, Pierre Bourdieu (London: Routledge, 1992), p. 16CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32 Bourdieu, Pierre, Homo Academicus (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988), p. 62Google Scholar.

33 This was a point raised by Bourdieu himself when criticising the idea that the subject is a bearer of transhistorical qualities. He argued that a trajectory cannot be understood without taking into account how individuals find themselves in different social settings which necessarily inflect this trajectory in unpredictable ways, at least from the individual’s perspective. See Bourdieu, Pierre, Raisons pratique: Sur la théorie de l’action (Paris: Seuil, 1994), pp. 81–89Google Scholar. But he misunderstood the significance of this point. For the issue here stems from the narrative reconstruction, not the actual bifurcations produced by history. For the latter change little to the point I make here: even if Bourdieu sought to reconstruct his trajectory differently as a series of surprising turning points and emphasised in the process social settings rather than individual commitments, he still fell in the trap of what he calls the biographical illusion. Saying that the subject is shaped by (changing) contexts does not alter the fact that meaning and purpose are established through narrating one’s life.

34 Wacquant, Bordieu and, An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology, p. 208Google Scholar.

35 Mérand and Pouliot, ‘Le monde’.

36 Knafo, Samuel, ‘Critical approaches and the legacy of the agent/structure debate in International Relations’, Cambridge Review of International Affairs, 23:3 (2010), pp. 493516CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37 Winch, Peter, The Idea of Social Science (London: Routledge & Keegan Paul, 1958)Google Scholar.

38 Bourdieu, Raisons pratiques.

39 Dreyfuss, Hubert and Rabinow, Paul, ‘Can there be a science of existential structure and social meaning’, in Craig Calhoun, Edward Lipuma, and Moishe Postone (ed.), Bourdieu: Critical Perspectives (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993), pp. 35–44Google Scholar.

40 Calhoun, Craig, Lipuma, Edward, and Postone, Moishe, ‘Introduction: Bourdieu and social theory’, in Craig Calhoun, Edward Lipuma, and Moishe Postone (eds), Bourdieu: Critical Perspectives (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993), p. 2Google Scholar.

41 Elsewhere I have made the argument that this phenomenological problem compels us to place agency at the centre of our methodology in order to move away from the idea of structural determination. Knafo, ‘Critical approaches’.

42 Bourdieu, , Sketch, p. 2Google Scholar.

43 Epstein, Charlotte, ‘Who speaks? Discourse, the subject and the study of identity international politics’, European Journal of International Relations, 17:2 (2011), p. 335CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

44 This move essentially leads Bourdieu to take phenomenology out of the equation by assuming that there is nothing specific about the question of how an object presents itself to a subject. The outcome is then a superficial solution for the gaze of the author is not captured through this process of bending over backwards. It is simply transferred to another level as it now looks upon the object of research and an objectified self. For this reason, the subject object relationship cannot be solved by treating the subject as an object, for you still need a subject to look upon the new assemblage. In this respect, Hamati-Ataya fails to recognise that a similar critique as the one she so effectively addresses to autobiography to this effect also applies to her own Bourdieusian project of objectifying the objectification. Hamati-Ataya, Inanna, ‘Transcending objectivism, subjectivism, and the knowledge in-between: the subject in/of “strong reflexivity”’, Review of International Studies, 40:1 (2014), pp. 153175CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

45 Maton, Kevin, ‘Reflexivity, relationism, and research: Pierre Bourdieu and the epistemic conditions of social scientific knowledge’, Space and Culture, 6:1 (2003), pp. 52–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

46 Hacking, Ian, The Social Construction of What? (London: Harvard University Press, 1999)Google Scholar.

47 Madsen, ‘Reflexivity and the construction of the international object’.

48 This is not to deny that reflexivity can be a means to conduct empirical research as international sociologists wish to do, but rather to emphasise that when it comes to empirical research, they have little left to specify what is reflexive about their work, by comparison to any other empirical work.

49 Pouliot, International Security.

50 Dezalay, Yves, and Garth, Bryant, The Internationalization of Palace Wars: Lawyers, Economists, and the Contest to Transform Latin American States (London: University of Chicago Press, 2002), p. 9CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

51 When Bourdieu seeks to address more technical matters, such as the issue of interviewing, it is striking how much of what he writes places the onus on disposition rather than concrete methodological techniques once more reflecting the optimism of a scholars confident in his own judgement rather than challenging it. See Bourdieu, Pierre, The Weight of the World: Social Suffering in Contemporary Society (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002)Google Scholar.

52 Bourdieu, Pierre, Chamboredon, Jean-Claude, and Passeron, Jean-Claude, The Craft of Sociology: Epistemological Preliminaries (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1968)Google Scholar.

53 Boltanski, Luc and Thévenot, Laurent, ‘The sociology of critical capacity’, European Journal of Social Theory, 2:3 (1999), pp. 359–377CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Latour, Bruno, Re-assembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005)Google Scholar.

54 Leander, Anna, ‘Pierre Bourdieu on economics: les structures sociales de l’économie’, Review of International Political Economy, 8:2 (2001), p. 351Google Scholar.

55 Bourdieu, Pierre, The Social Structures of the Economy (Cambridge: Polity, 2005)Google Scholar.

56 For another example of a highly structural account of neoliberalism produced by a reflexive sociologist see Wacquant, Loïc, Punishing the Poor: The Neoliberal Government of Social Insecurity (London: Duke University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

57 Grenfell, Michael, Pierre Bourdieu: Agent Provocateur (London: Continuum, 2004), p. 129Google Scholar.

58 Bigo, ‘Pierre Bourdieu and International Relations’.

59 See also Leander, , ‘The promises’, p. 351Google Scholar.

60 Knafo, Samuel, ‘Political Marxism and value theory: Bridging the gap between theory and history’, Historical Materialism, 15:2 (2007) pp. 75–104CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

61 This is a point that Skinner makes, for example, with the notion of virtù in Machiavelli. See Skinner, Quentin, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought. Volume One: The Renaissance (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1978)Google Scholar.

62 Skinner, Quentin, ‘Meaning and understanding in the history of ideas’, in James Tully (ed.), Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and his Critics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988), pp. 29–67Google Scholar.

63 Pels, Dick, ‘Knowledge politics and anti-politics: Toward a critical appraisal of Bourdieu’s concept of intellectual autonomy’, Theory and Society, 24:1 (1995), pp. 79104CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Lynch, Michael, ‘Against reflexivity as an academic virtue and source of privileged knowledge’, Theory, Culture & Society, 17:3 (2000), pp. 26–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

64 Bourdieu, , Homo Academicus, p. 35Google Scholar.

65 Lacan, Jacques, ‘The function and field of speech and language in psychoanalysis’, Ecrits (New York 2002), pp. 197268Google Scholar.

66 Verdes-Leroux, Jeannine, Deconstructing Pierre Bourdieu’s Sociological Terrorism: Against the Sociological Terrorism from the Left (New York: Algora Publishers, 2000)Google Scholar.

67 Lynch, ‘Against reflexivity’.

68 Bourdieu, Pierre, Science of Science and Reflexivity (Cambridge: Polity, 2004), p. 72Google Scholar.

69 Bourdieu et al., Craft of Sociology.

70 See, by the author of this article, ‘The fetishizing subject of Marx’s capital’, Capital and Class, 76 (2002), pp. 183–213.

71 Although Skinner offers a brilliant strategy to think of textual contextualisation, he decided, for some reason, not to apply across the board the same principles of contextualisation based on differentiation and authorship. As a result, Skinner’s social and political contextualisations are very superficial and mostly concerned with establishing the reasons motivating someone to write, rather than a broader attempt to use social contextualisation to place their work in perspective and understand its historical significance. This is, in a way, the problem I seek to tackle with the idea of agency.

72 Checkel, Jeffrey T., ‘The constructivist turn in International Relations theory’, World Politics, 50:1 (1998), pp. 324348CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

73 Knafo, ‘Critical approaches’.