Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gvvz8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T19:26:40.310Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Psychological Dangers of Positive Liberty: Reconstructing a Neglected Undercurrent in Isaiah Berlin's “Two Concepts of Liberty”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 April 2014

Abstract

Berlin is often taken to have exaggerated his case against positive liberty, since contrary to what he seems to argue, several versions of it do not logically justify coercion. A more historical interpretation of his warnings may save him from this accusation, yet on the other hand suggests his message is of little relevance for contemporary liberalism. In contrast to both these approaches, this essay considers a third and largely neglected aspect of “Two Concepts of Liberty,” that speaks more directly to the challenges facing liberalism today: Berlin's warning that positive liberty invites the specific kind of coercion that parades as liberation, and that it does so according to a psychologically predictable pattern. After reconstructing this undercurrent in Berlin's critique of positive liberty, this essay also considers the relevance of Berlin's warnings to contemporary European debates on banning the Muslim veil in the name of liberation.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 2014 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Berlin, Isaiah, “Two Concepts of Liberty,” in Liberty, ed. Hardy, Henry (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008)Google Scholar, 211 (hereafter referred to as TCL). Following Berlin, I here use “liberty” and “freedom” synonymously; see TCL, 169.

2 Macpherson, C. B., “Berlin's division of liberty,” in Democratic Theory: Essays in Retrieval, ed. Macpherson, C. B. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), 110–13Google Scholar; Christman, John, “Liberalism and Individual Positive Freedom,” Ethics 101, no. 2 (1991): 359Google Scholar; Simhony, Avital, “On Forcing Individuals to be Free: T. H. Green's Liberal Theory of Positive Freedom,” Political Studies 39, no. 2 (1991): 305CrossRefGoogle Scholar; West, David, “Spinoza on Positive Freedom,” Political Studies 41, no. 2 (1993): 296Google Scholar.

3 Galipeau, Claude J., Isaiah Berlin's Liberalism (Oxford: Clarendon, 1994)Google Scholar, 85; Gray, John, Isaiah Berlin (London: HarperCollins, 1995)Google Scholar, 18; Crowder, George, Isaiah Berlin: Liberty and Pluralism (Cambridge: Polity, 2004), 8485Google Scholar.

4 Franco, Paul, “The Shapes of Liberal Thought: Oakeshott, Berlin, and Liberalism,” Political Theory 31, no. 4 (2003): 490Google Scholar. Also see Galipeau, Isaiah Berlin's Liberalism, 85; and Kenny, Michael, “Isaiah Berlin's Contribution to Modern Political Theory,” Political Studies 48, no. 5 (2000): 1037Google Scholar.

5 Crowder, Isaiah Berlin, 149.

6 Mack, Eric, “Isaiah Berlin and the Quest for Liberal Pluralism,” Public Affairs Quarterly 7, no. 3 (1993): 215–30Google Scholar; Gray, Isaiah Berlin; Tamir, Yael, “A Strange Alliance: Isaiah Berlin and the Liberalism of the Fringes,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1, no. 2 (1998): 279–89Google Scholar; Galston, William A, “Value Pluralism and Liberal Political Theory,” American Political Science Review 93, no. 4 (1999): 769–78Google Scholar; Gutmann, Amy, “Liberty and Pluralism in Pursuit of the Non-ideal,” Social Research 66, no. 4 (1999): 1039–62Google Scholar; Honneth, Axel, “Negative Freedom and Cultural Belonging: An Unhealthy Tension in the Political Philosophy of Isaiah Berlin,” Social Research 66, no. 4 (1999): 1063–77Google Scholar; Riley, Jonathan, “Interpreting Berlin's Liberalism,” American Political Science Review 95, no. 2 (2001): 283–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Franco, “The Shapes of Liberal Thought: Oakeshott, Berlin, and Liberalism”; Gaus, Gerald F., Contemporary Theories of Liberalism (London: Sage, 2003)Google Scholar, chap. 2; Crowder, George, “Two Concepts of Liberal Pluralism,” Political Theory 35, no. 2 (2007): 121–46Google Scholar; Myers, Ella, “From Pluralism to Liberalism: Rereading Isaiah Berlin,” Review of Politics 72, no. 4 (2010): 599625Google Scholar.

7 Cf. Galston, William A., Liberal Pluralism: The Implications of Value Pluralism for Political Theory and Practice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002)Google Scholar, chap. 2; Mookherje, Monica, “Affective citizenship: feminism, postcolonialism and the politics of recognition,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 8, no. 1 (2005): 33Google Scholar; Tebble, Adam, “Exclusion for Democracy,” Political Theory 34, no. 4 (2006): 474Google Scholar; Joppke, Christian, Veil: Mirror of Identity (Cambridge: Polity, 2010), 2Google Scholar; Adamson, Fiona B., Triadafilopoulos, Triadafilos, and Zolberg, Aristide R., “The Limits of the Liberal State: Migration, Identity and Belonging in Europe,” Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 37, no. 6 (2011): 843–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Zakaras, Alex, “Isaiah Berlin's Cosmopolitan Ethics,” Political Theory 32, no. 4 (2004): 515Google Scholar; Müller, Jan-Werner, “Fear and Freedom: On ‘Cold War Liberalism,’European Journal of Political Theory 7, no. 1 (2008): 5859CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Zakaras, Alex, “A Liberal Pluralism: Isaiah Berlin and John Stuart Mill,” Review of Politics 75, no. 1 (2013): 9192Google Scholar.

9 Crowder, Isaiah Berlin; Ricciardi, Mario, “Berlin on Liberty,” in The One and the Many: Reading Isaiah Berlin, ed. Crowder, George and Hardy, Henry (New York: Prometheus Books, 2007)Google Scholar.

10 Zakaras, “A Liberal Pluralism,” 92. Also see Crowder, George, “Justification and Psychology in Liberal Pluralism: A Reply to Zakaras,” Review of Politics 75, no. 1 (2013): 103–10Google Scholar; Zakaras, Alex, “Reply to Galston and Crowder,” Review of Politics 75, no. 1 (2013): 111–14Google Scholar.

11 See references in footnote 7, above.

12 Cf. McCloskey, H. J., “A Critique of the Ideals of Liberty,” Mind 74, no. 296 (1965): 483508Google Scholar; Ryan, Alan, “Freedom,” Philosophy 40, no. 152 (1965): 93112Google Scholar; Macfarlane, L. J., “On Two Concepts of Liberty,” Political Studies 14, no. 1 (1966): 7781CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Gray, Isaiah Berlin; and Taylor, Charles, “What's Wrong with Negative Liberty?,” in Contemporary Political Philosophy, ed. Goodin, Robert and Pettit, Philip (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997)Google Scholar. For an overview of this vast debate, see Harris, Ian, “Berlin and his Critics,” in Liberty, ed. Hardy, Henry (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008)Google Scholar.

13 Crowder, Isaiah Berlin, 69; Joshua Cherniss, “Berlin's Early Political Thought,” in The One and the Many: Reading Isaiah Berlin, 95; Ricciardi, “Berlin on Liberty,” 126.

14 TCL, 178–79.

15 TCL, 212. This reading is also found in Galipeau, Isaiah Berlin's Liberalism, 8–9; Gray, Isaiah Berlin, 17; Crowder, Isaiah Berlin, 78.

16 Gray, Isaiah Berlin, 15–16.

17 Berlin, Isaiah, “Introduction,” in Liberty, ed. Hardy, Henry (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 179Google Scholar. For an insightful account of these different sides of positive liberty, see Miller, David, editor's introduction to The Liberty Reader (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2006)Google Scholar, 10. Berlin, moreover, clearly refers to “individual liberty, in either the ‘negative’ or in the ‘positive’ senses of the word” (TCL, 204). Thus, although he blames positive liberty for being more easily perverted into an idea of freedom as merging one's individual self into “some super-personal entity,” it seems fair to say that he does not identify positive liberty with any collectivist notion. This reading is argued for in further detail in Crowder, Isaiah Berlin, 68; and Ricciardi, “Berlin on Liberty,” 132.

18 Galipeau, Isaiah Berlin's Liberalism, 36; Crowder, Isaiah Berlin, 188.

19 This reading is also found in Macpherson, “Berlin's division of liberty,” 95; Galipeau, Isaiah Berlin's Liberalism, 104; Gray, Isaiah Berlin, 22; and Crowder, Isaiah Berlin, 68–69.

20 Isaiah Berlin, “Introduction,” 32.

21 Ibid. 39 (emphasis added).

22 TCL, 169.

23 TCL, 180–81.

24 TCL, 215.

25 TCL, 180.

26 Zakaras, “Isaiah Berlin's Cosmopolitan Ethics,” 504–7. Cf. Berlin, Isaiah, “The Pursuit of the Ideal,” in The Crooked Timber of Humanity: Chapters in the History of Ideas, ed. Hardy, Henry (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990), 11Google Scholar; Berlin, Isaiah, Three Critics of the Enlightenment: Vico, Hamann, Herder, ed. Hardy, Henry (Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000), 49Google Scholar.

27 TCL, 216–17.

28 Christman, “Liberalism and Individual Positive Freedom,” 359; Simhony, “On Forcing Individual to be Free: T. H. Green's Liberal Theory of Positive Freedom,” 305; West, “Spinoza on Positive Freedom,” 296; Crowder, Isaiah Berlin, 86.

29 TCL, 179, 181. Berlin, “Introduction, 37.

30 Cf. Macpherson, “Berlin's division of liberty,” 110–11.

31 Crowder, Isaiah Berlin, 69–70. The notion of the “inversion thesis” is also used in Ricciardi, “Berlin on Liberty,” 121.

32 Crowder, Isaiah Berlin, 84.

33 Ibid., 69.

34 TCL, 167.

35 TCL, 179.

36 Berlin, Isaiah, “Kant as an Unfamiliar Source of Nationalism,” in The Sense of Reality: Studies in Ideas and their History, ed. Hardy, Henry (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1997), 237Google Scholar.

37 TCL, 198 (emphasis added).

38 TCL, 207–8 (emphasis added).

39 Berlin, “Introduction,” 31–32.

40 Zakaras, “Isaiah Berlin's Cosmopolitan Ethics,” 515; Müller, “Fear and Freedom,” 59; Zakaras, “A Liberal Pluralism.”

41 Cf. Cherniss, Joshua L., “Isaiah Berlin's Political Ideas: From the Twentieth Century to the Romantic Age,” in Political Ideas in the Romantic Age, ed. Hardy, Henry (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006)Google Scholar; Graeme Garrard, “Strange Reversals: Berlin on the Enlightenment and the Counter-Enlightenment,” in The One and the Many: Reading Isaiah Berlin; Ricciardi, “Berlin on Liberty.”

42 Gray, Isaiah Berlin; Galston, “Value Pluralism and Liberal Political Theory”; Riley, “Interpreting Berlin's Liberalism”; Franco, “The Shapes of Liberal Thought: Oakeshott, Berlin, and Liberalism.”

43 Macfarlane, “On Two Concepts of Liberty,” 79–80; Christman, “Liberalism and Individual Positive Freedom,” 359; West, “Spinoza on Positive Freedom,” 288; Galipeau, Isaiah Berlin's Liberalism, 101–2.

44 His more general concern that, as Galston puts it, “the totalitarian temptation is an enduring feature of the human mind” has often been recognized, however. See Galston, William A., “Moral Pluralism and Liberal Democracy: Isaiah Berlin's Heterodox Liberalism,” Review of Politics 71, no. 1 (2009): 99Google Scholar; and Zakaras, “A Liberal Pluralism,” 86.

45 TCL, 208.

46 TCL, 214.

47 TCL, 216.

48 TCL, 217.

49 As an anonymous reviewer brought to my attention, a monist could of course merely assume that there is one rational ordering of human values, but doubt that there can be any positive access to this knowledge. By repeatedly lumping together monism, certainty, and self-righteousness, Berlin thus neglects this much less comforting version of monism. Cf. Berlin, “The Pursuit of the Ideal,” 13–14.

50 Note that this differs from the more common interpretation of Berlin as seeing monism as a consequence of positive liberty, which has recently been discussed by Kis, Janos, “Berlin's two concepts of positive liberty,” European Journal of Political Theory 12, no. 1 (2013): 3839CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

51 TCL, 181.

52 TCL,179–80.

53 TCL, 192.

54 Berlin seems to have thought of himself as a pluralistic supporter of positive liberty: Berlin, “Introduction,” 50; Cherniss, “Berlin's Early Political Thought.”

55 TCL, 193.

56 TCL, 213.

57 TCL, 180.

58 Ross, Lee and Ward, Andrew, “Naive Realism in Everyday Life: Implications for Social Conflict and Misunderstanding,” in Values and Knowledge, ed. Reed, Edward, Turiel, Elliot, and Brown, Terrance (Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1996), 110–11Google Scholar. Also see Griffin, Dale W. and Ross, Lee, “Subjective Construal, Social Inference, and Human Misunderstanding,” in Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, vol. 4 (New York: Academic Press, 1991), 319–59Google Scholar.

59 Taber, Charles S. and Lodge, Milton, “Motivated Skepticism in the Evaluation of Political Beliefs,” American Journal of Political Science 50, no. 3 (2006): 767Google Scholar. Also see Kunda, Ziva, “The Case for Motivated Reasoning,” Psychological Bulletin 108, no. 3 (1990): 480–98Google Scholar.

60 Nickerson, Raymond S., “How we know—and sometimes misjudge—what others know: Imputing one's own knowledge to others,” Psychological Bulletin 125, no. 6 (1999): 739–59Google Scholar; Royzman, Edward B., Cassidy, Kimberly Wright, and Baron, Jonathan, “‘I Know, You Know’: Epistemic Egocentrism in Children and Adults,” Review of General Psychology 7, no. 1 (2003): 3865Google Scholar; Epley, Nicholas, Keysar, Boaz, Van Boven, Leaf, and Gilovich, Thomas, “Perspective taking as egocentric anchoring and adjustment,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 87, no. 3 (2004): 327–39Google Scholar.

61 Arblaster, Anthony, “Vision and Revision: A Note on the Text of Isaiah Berlin's Four Essays on Liberty,” Political Studies 19, no. 1 (1971): 86CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

62 TCL, 169.

63 Berlin, “Introduction,” 32.

64 Berlin, Isaiah, “Two Concepts of Freedom: Romantic and Liberal,” in Political Ideas in the Romantic Age, ed. Hardy, Henry (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008), 205Google Scholar.

65 MacCallum, Gerald, “Negative and Positive Freedom,” The Philosophical Review 73, no. 3 (1967): 312–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

66 Crowder, Isaiah Berlin, 78; Christman, John, “Saving Positive Freedom,” Political Theory 33, no. 1 (2005): 81Google Scholar.

67 TCL, 179–80.

68 TCL, 185, 204, 195, 169.

69 TCL, 180–81.

70 Christman, “Liberalism and Individual Positive Freedom,” 354–55; Galipeau, Isaiah Berlin's Liberalism, 101; Gray, Isaiah Berlin, 21.

71 Berlin, “Two Concepts of Freedom: Romantic and Liberal,” 185, 89 (emphasis added). The term “romantic” is of course notoriously difficult to define. I here simply follow Berlin in using it to refer to ideas he associates with early German Romanticism. See Berlin, Isaiah, The Roots of Romanticism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001)Google Scholar.

72 Berlin, Roots of Romanticism, 50–51.

73 Isaiah Berlin, “The Apotheosis of the Romantic Will,” in The Crooked Timber of Humanity, 229.

74 Berlin, “Two Concepts of Freedom: Romantic and Liberal,” 201.

75 Ibid., 197.

76 Berlin, “The Apotheosis of the Romantic Will,” 231.

77 Berlin, “Two Concepts of Freedom: Romantic and Liberal,” 201–2.

78 TCL, 169, 70, 79, 75.

79 TCL, 175, 78, 81–82.

80 TCL, 184.

81 TCL, 185.

82 TCL, 198–99.

83 TCL, 199.

84 Kant, Immanuel, An Answer to the Question: What Is Enlightenment?, in What Is Enlightenment? Eighteenth-Century Answers and Twentieth-Century Questions, ed. Schmidt, James (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1996), 63Google Scholar.

85 Ibid, 59.

86 Ibid., 63.

87 TCL, 197.

88 Berlin, “Two Concepts of Freedom: Romantic and Liberal,” 202.

89 Zakaras has suggested this in passing, yet no one has yet to my knowledge actually tried to bring together the two (Zakaras, “A Liberal Pluralism,” 94).

90 André Gerin and Eric Raoult, Document no. 2262: Rapport d'information au nom de la mission d'information sur la pratique du port du voile intégral sur le territoire national, Assemblée Nationale, 29 January 2010, 87; retrieved from http://www.assemblee-nationale.fr/13/rap-info/i2262.asp, last accessed on 18 November 2013. All quotes from this document were translated by the author.

91 Ibid., 93.

92 Ibid., 287–88, 291. He also raised other concerns, for example that the unveiled majority needed protection from the “symbolic violence” inherent in the full veil (ibid., 286).

93 Ibid., 291.

94 Ibid., 286.

95 Ibid., 291.

96 Ibid.

97 Ibid.

98 Ibid., 287. Also see his insistence on the face as the expressive mirror of the soul (ibid., 286).

99 Ibid., 98, 118. Also see the reasoning of the Sufi poet and intellectual Abdelwahab Meddeb, cited at116–17.

100 For a lucid account of Schlegel's sometimes opaque critique of Kant on this matter, see Gorodeisky, Keren, “(Re)encountering Individuality: Schlegel's Romantic Imperative as a Response to Nihilism,” Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 54, no. 6 (2011): 576–79Google Scholar.

101 Cf. Fekete, Liz, “Enlightened fundamentalism? Immigration, feminism and the Right,” Race & Class 48, no. 2 (2006): 122Google Scholar; Wallach-Scott, Joan, The Politics of the Veil (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2007), 16, 121, 135Google Scholar; Winter, Bronwyn, Hijab and the Republic: Uncovering the French Headscarf Debate (Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 2008)Google Scholar, chap. 6; Al-Saji, Alia, “The Racialization of Muslim veils: A philosophical analysis,” Philosophy and Social Criticism 36, no. 8 (2010): 875902Google Scholar. A notable exception is Laborde, Cécile, Critical Republicanism: The Hijab Controversy and Political Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008)Google Scholar. Yet Laborde only considers the ban on headscarves on minors in public schools, not the more recent and substantially different issue of banning full veils on adult women in the public sphere. Nor does Laborde mention Berlin or his warnings against the positive liberty of self-mastery; her concern is instead with republican freedom as nondomination, which is considerably different (cf. Miller, introduction to Liberty Reader, 10).

102 Baehr, Peter and Gordon, Daniel, “From the headscarf to the burqa: The role of social theorists in shaping laws against the veil,” Economy and Society 42, no. 2 (2013): 253, 255Google Scholar.

103 Ali, Ayaan Hirsi, The Caged Virgin: A Muslim Woman's Cry for Reason (London: Simon and Schuster, 2007), 32Google Scholar; Bruckner, Pascal, “Unveiled: A Case for France's Burqa Ban,” World Affairs 173, no. 4 (2010): 6165Google Scholar.

104 Gustavsson, Gina, “Romantic Liberalism: An Alternative Perspective on the Muhammad Cartoons Controversy,” Political Studies 62, no. 1 (2014): 6667Google Scholar.

105 Also see Gustavsson, Gina, “Freedom in mass values: egocentric, humanistic, or both? Using Isaiah Berlin to understand a contemporary debate,” European Political Science Review 4, no. 2 (2012): 241–62Google Scholar.

106 Adamson, Triadafilopoulos, and Zolberg, “The Limits of the Liberal State.”

107 Galston, William A., “Two Concepts of Liberalism,” Ethics 105, no. 3 (1995): 516–34Google Scholar; King, Desmond, In the Name of Liberalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999)Google Scholar; Gray, John, Two Faces of Liberalism (New York: New Press, 2000)Google Scholar; Kukathas, Chandran, The Liberal Archipelago: A Theory of Diversity and Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007)Google Scholar. Also see the references in note 7, above.

108 Flanagan, Scott C. and Lee, Aie-Rie, “The New Politics, Culture Wars, and the Authoritarian-Libertarian Value Change in Advanced Industrial Democracies,” Comparative Political Studies 36, no. 3 (2003): 238Google Scholar; Bellah, Robert N., Madsen, Richard, Sullivan, William M., Swidler, Ann, and Tipton, Steven M., Habits of the Heart, Individualism and Commitment in American Life (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2008), 130–33Google Scholar, 333–34; Stoltzenberg, Nomi Maya, “Liberalism in a Romantic State,” Law, Culture and the Humanities 5 (2009): 194215Google Scholar.