Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T05:33:23.441Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Demos and Its Critics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 July 2019

Abstract

The “demos paradox” is the idea that the composition of a demos could never secure democratic legitimacy because the composition of a demos cannot itself be democratically decided. Those who view this problem as unsolvable argue that this insight allows them to adopt a critical perspective towards common ideas about who has legitimate standing to participate in democratic decision-making. We argue that the opposite is true and that endorsing the demos paradox actually undermines our ability to critically engage with common ideas about legitimate standing. We challenge the conception of legitimacy that lurks behind the demos paradox and argue that the real impossibility is to endorse democracy without also being committed to significant procedure-independent standards for the legitimate composition of the demos. We show that trying to solve the problem of the demos by appeal to some normative conception of democratic legitimacy is a worthwhile project that is not undermined by paradox.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Beckman, Ludvig, Frontiers of Democracy: The Right to Vote and Its Limits (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Lopez-Guerra, Claudio, Democracy and Disenfranchisement: The Morality of Electoral Exclusion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Jennings, Ivor, The Approach to Self-Government (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1956)Google Scholar.

3 Arrhenius, Gustaf, “The Boundary Problem in Democratic Theory,” in Democracy Unbound: Basic Explorations I, ed. Tersman, Folke (Stockholm: Filosofiska Institutionen, Stockholms Universitet, 2005)Google Scholar; Goodin, Robert E., “Enfranchising All Affected Interests, and Its Alternatives,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 35 (2007): 4068CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Miller, David, “Democracy's Domain,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 37 (2009): 201–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Song, Sarah, “The Boundary Problem in Democratic Theory: Why the Demos Should Be Bounded by the State,” International Theory 4 (2012): 3968CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 Agné, Hans, “Why Democracy Must Be Global: Self-Founding and Democratic Intervention,” International Theory 2 (2010): 381409CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Waldron, Jeremy, Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 164–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Benhabib, Seyla, The Rights of Others: Aliens, Residents and Citizens (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Gould, Carol, Globalizing Democracy and Human Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Espejo, Paulina Ochoa, The Time of Popular Sovereignty (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2011)Google Scholar; Olson, Kevin, “Paradoxes of Constitutional Democracy,” American Journal of Political Science 51 (2007): 330–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Ochoa Espejo, Time of Popular Sovereignty, 13, 173.

7 Näsström, Sofia, “The Legitimacy of the People,” Political Theory 35 (2007): 624658CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Honig, Bonnie, “Between Decision and Deliberation: Political Paradox in Democratic Theory,” American Political Science Review 101 (2007): 117CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Yack, Bernard, “Popular Sovereignty and Nationalism,” Political Theory 29 (2001): 529CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Whitt, Matt, “Democracy's Sovereign Enclosures: Territory and the All-Affected Principle,” Constellations 21 (2014): 560–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Näsström, “Legitimacy of the People,” 644. The present debate on the “demos paradox” is often confused by the tendency to speak interchangeably about “the people” and “the demos.” “People” refers either to the inhabitants of territories or the members of some national or ethnic group. “Demos” denotes the individuals legally entitled to participate in democratic decision-making. Given that the debate is ultimately concerned with the status and possibility of democracy, we believe it is more appropriate to focus on the demos. However, as we observe in section 2 of this paper, parts of the debate are more concerned with the normative status of peoples and nationalism than with the normative status of democracy and the demos.

9 Espejo, Paulina Ochoa, “People, Territory, and Legitimacy in Democratic States,” American Journal of Political Science 58 (2014): 466–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Donahue, Thomas J. and Espejo, Paulina Ochoa, “The Analytical-Continental Divide: Styles Dealing with Problems,” European Journal of Political Theory 15 (2016): 144–45, 149–51CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Donahue and Ochoa Espejo, “Analytical-Continental Divide,” 146.

11 Donahue and Ochoa Espejo claim that in addition to “solving” problems, analytical philosophers are also sensitive to the possibility of “dissolving” problems, i.e., showing that there is only a false appearance of a problem (ibid., 150–51). They argue that within the demos debate, dissolving the problem amounts to arguing that there are sources of democratic legitimacy for the composition of demos other than the exercise of democratic procedures. However, the core of the debate between impossibilists and possibilists has from the outset been about whether there could be sources of legitimacy for the demos other than democratic procedure. It is thus unclear why “dissolving” as conceived above should be treated as an alternative mode of analysis in this debate.

12 Whelan, Frederick, “Prologue: Democratic Theory and the Boundary Problem,” in Liberal Democracy, ed. Pennock, Roland J. and Chapman, J. W. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983), 40Google Scholar.

13 Miller, “Democracy's Domain,” 204.

14 Näsström, Sofia, “What Globalization Overshadows,” Political Theory 31 (2003): 819CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ochoa Espejo, Time of Popular Sovereignty, 41.

15 Näsström, “Legitimacy of the People,” 633; Yack, “Popular Sovereignty and Nationalism,.”

16 Bartelson, Jens, “Facing Europe: Is Globalization a Threat to Democracy?,” Distinktion: Scandinavian Journal of Social Theory 5 (2004):55CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Yack, “Popular Sovereignty and Nationalism,” 523.

18 Habermas, Jürgen, “The European Nation-State: On the Past and Future of Sovereignty and Citizenship,” Public Culture 10 (1998): 397416CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Similarly, see Bartelson, “Facing Europe,” 51.

20 Abizadeh, Arash, “Democratic Theory and Border Coercion: No Right to Unilaterally Control Your Own Borders,” Political Theory 36 (2008): 47CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

21 Ochoa Espejo, Time of Popular Sovereignty, 41.

22 Olson, “Paradoxes of Constitutional Democracy,” 330.

23 Näsström, “Legitimacy of the People,” 630.

24 Näsström, “What Globalization Overshadows,” 824.

25 Whelan, “Prologue,” 16.

26 Näsström, Sofia, “The Challenge of the All-Affected Principle,” Political Studies 59 (2011): 116–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ochoa Espejo, “People, Territory, and Legitimacy”; Whitt, “Democracy's Sovereign Enclosures.”

27 Näsström, “Legitimacy of the People,” 641.

28 Olson, “Paradoxes of Constitutional Democracy,” 331.

29 Honig, “Between Decision and Deliberation”; Mouffe, Chantal, The Democratic Paradox (London: Verso, 2004)Google Scholar; Näsström, “Legitimacy of the People.”

30 Waldron, Law and Disagreement, 164–87.

31 Ibid., 111–16, 282–312.

32 Ibid., 232–54.

33 Ibid., 298–300.

34 Ibid., 299–300, emphasis added.

35 Ibid., 300.

36 Ibid., 283.

37 Ibid., 88–118.

38 Ibid., 282.

39 Agné, “Why Democracy Must Be Global.”

40 Näsström, “Challenge of the All-Affected Principle,” 129.

41 Dahl, Robert, Democracy and Its Critics (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1989)Google Scholar.

42 Lopez-Guerra, Democracy and Disenfranchisement, 68–69.

43 See Raz, Joseph, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon, 1986), 90Google Scholar; Hampton, Jean, Political Philosophy (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1997), 5961Google Scholar; Freeman, Samuel, “Illiberal Libertarians: Why Libertarianism Is Not a Liberal View,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 30 (2001): 110–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Maltais, Aaron, Global Warming and Our Natural Duties of Justice (Uppsala: Acta Universitatis Upsalaiensis, 2008), 158–63Google Scholar; Maltais, Aaron, “Political Obligations in a Sea of Tyranny and Crushing Poverty,” Legal Theory 20 (2014): 188–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

44 See Hume, David, “Of the Original Contract,” in Hume's Ethical Writings, ed. MacIntyre, Alasdair (New York: Collier Books, 1965), 263Google Scholar; Simmons, John A., Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981), 99100Google Scholar; Wellman, Christopher Heath, “Toward a Liberal Theory of Political Obligation,” Ethics 111 (2001): 735–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Maltais, “Political Obligations,” 190–93.

45 Goodin, Robert E., “Enfranchising All Affected Interests, and Its Alternatives,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 35 (2007): 4068CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Miller, “Democracy's Domain”; Hurley, Susanne L., “Rationality, Democracy and Leaky Boundaries: Vertical vs. Horizontal Modularity,” Journal of Political Philosophy 7 (1999): 126–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Saunders, Ben, “Defining the Demos,” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 11 (2012): 280301CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Song, “Boundary Problem in Democratic Theory.”

46 Honig, “Between Decision and Deliberation,” 13.

47 Näsström, “Legitimacy of the People,” 644.

48 Ibid., 626, 642.

49 Donahue and Ochoa Espejo, “Analytical-Continental Divide,” 151. Mouffe's approach (to which Donahue and Ochoa Espejo also refer) to the problem of the demos is in a sense an “impossibilist” position because she does not think a legitimate demarcation of the demos is achievable. However, it is important to see that Mouffe does not base this claim on the idea that any demarcation of the demos necessarily leads to the paradox of the demos as we described it in the introduction. Instead, she argues that the question of the demos's composition can never be legitimately closed because there is a tension between the individualistic universalism of liberalism and the excluding particularism inherent to democratic practice. She argues that this tension is intractable for liberal democratic theory. Mouffe clearly does not adopt the strongly procedural theory of democratic legitimacy that some impossibilists endorse. Rather she recognizes that procedural justice and democratic procedures “presupposes acceptance of certain values” (Mouffe, Democratic Paradox, 68–69). Given her normative commitments, what is surprising in Mouffe's case is how little theoretical progress she thinks can be made on the problem of the legitimate composition of the demos.

50 Ochoa Espejo, Time of Popular Sovereignty, 174.

51 Ibid., 177.

52 Ibid., 178.

53 A similar critique of paradox in democratic theory and a call for a problem-based approach to democratic problems, based on a normative understanding of democracy, is defended in Warren, Mark E., “A Problem-Based Approach to Democratic Theory,” American Political Science Review 111 (2017): 3953CrossRefGoogle Scholar.