Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T17:36:21.642Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Thomas Aquinas's Political Science: Philosophy or Theology?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2024

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article examines whether Aquinas's political science is philosophy or theology, a question that arises from his understanding of happiness. If the supernatural vision of God constitutes perfect beatitude or the ultimate end, then how can an account of imperfect happiness—political virtue—be given without reference to it and hence without appeal to revealed theology? I argue that Aquinas provides a strictly philosophical account of imperfect happiness by showing that, among temporal goods, virtue most fully instantiates general attributes of beatitude such as self-sufficiency and continuity, even though it does not perfectly instantiate them. This way of demonstrating the superiority of virtue to other temporal goods requires no appeal to supernatural beatitude, and thus political science, which takes this imperfect happiness as its first principle, is philosophy.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of University of Notre Dame

The question whether Thomas Aquinas understands political science as a philosophical or theological science would prima facie seem to admit of a straightforward answer. In his commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics, Aquinas explicitly includes scientia politica under moral philosophy as the science that considers the actions of human civic society as ordered to civic society's proper end.Footnote 1 In the Politics commentary, he repeats this claim, adding that the study of politics is necessary for the philosopher since “we need to teach everything that reason can know for the perfection of human wisdom called philosophy.”Footnote 2 Study of the political things pertains to reason and is a necessary branch of inquiry for those who seek philosophical wisdom. These remarks are not glosses on Aristotle, who does not make such affirmations. Aquinas inserts his comments in prolegomena which situate the Aristotelian texts under consideration within the broader taxonomy of sciences as he himself understands it.

Notwithstanding Aquinas's seemingly unambiguous affirmation of political science as part of philosophy, Leo Strauss and Denis Bradley have questioned its philosophical character, suggesting that Aquinas's understanding of human beatitude makes impossible a genuinely philosophical moral and, by extension, political science. Strauss argues that since, for Aquinas, no natural good completely perfects human nature and thus constitutes its beatitude, the end of man as man must be supernatural―the vision of God's essence in the afterlife―and hence knowable only through divine revelation. In turn, since the end, good, or beatitude that perfects human nature is the first principle of natural law and ultimately of political science, scientia politica requires revelation for a justification of its first principle and is thus not a species of philosophy but rather of theology.Footnote 3

Among contemporary scholars, Denis Bradley has given the most comprehensive formulation of the problem. As he observes, in Aquinas's understanding, the first principle of both ethics and political science is temporal happiness,Footnote 4 which consists in virtuous living. Ethics is the body of knowledge or science that aims at the attainment of virtuous living by the individual, and politics is the body of knowledge or science that aims at procuring virtuous living for the multitude of citizens.Footnote 5 For these sciences to be philosophical, it must therefore be possible to establish the goodness or choiceworthiness of virtuous living and its superiority to other temporal, natural goods without appealing to divine revelation. Such an account, however, is impossible on Aquinas's view that the ultimate end of human nature―the end which fully satisfies its natural desire for perfection―is the supernatural vision of God's essence. As Bradley explains, in Aquinas's teleological view of human action, the goodness of lower ends or goods is judged in terms of their relationship to the ultimate end that fulfills natural desire.Footnote 6 Only through knowing what the ultimate end is and what conduces to it can we ascertain what other activities count as goods and how these subordinate goods ought to be ordered. Consequently, an account of the goodness or choiceworthiness of virtuous activity in this life and its superiority to other temporal goods requires knowledge of the ultimate end―the beatific vision. Since, however, this end is supernatural, such knowledge depends essentially on divine revelation, and an account of the first principle of ethics and by implication political science is thus irreducibly theological. As Bradley concludes, a “philosophically autonomous Thomistic ethics [and therefore political science] . . . cannot be legitimately derived from Aquinas's theological ethics. Thomistic moral [and political] science is built on knowledge of the actual supernatural end of man, and that knowledge is strictly theological.”Footnote 7

Although Bradley and Strauss are correct that for Aquinas human nature is only completely perfected by a supernatural end, this does not mean that a strictly philosophical account of man's natural, temporal happiness is impossible. The first part of this article examines the two solutions proposed in existing scholarship to the problem raised by Strauss and Bradley, concluding that neither solves the difficulty. In the second part, I provide an original solution to the problem of a philosophical account of temporal happiness in Aquinas's thought and thus of the philosophical character of Thomistic political science. In the third part, I examine an apparent difficulty facing my interpretation that arises from passages in his De regno and show that interpreting these passages in conjunction with other texts in his corpus resolves the difficulty. Finally, I briefly consider the implications of my analysis of Aquinas's account of beatitude and the philosophical character of political science for other aspects of his thought.

1. Supernatural Beatitude and a Philosophical Account of Temporal Happiness: Two Solutions

Two solutions to the problem raised by Strauss and Bradley have been advanced by scholars. The first is to deny that for Aquinas the only good that completely perfects human nature, satisfying its natural desire for beatitude and thus constituting its ultimate end, is the vision of the divine essence. Rather, the perfection of our nature consists in a naturally attainable good, principally the philosophical knowledge and love of God possible in the present life and secondarily acts of moral virtue. The problem of providing an account of temporal happiness―the first principle of ethics and political science―without reference to human nature's supernatural ultimate end thus does not arise precisely because natural or temporal happiness itself is the ultimate end of human nature. In other words, proponents of this solution establish the existence of a natural end that grounds a genuinely philosophical ethics and political science—something Strauss and Bradley deny is possible—by claiming that the ultimate end that perfects human nature is purely natural. The most prominent contemporary proponents of this solution are Lawrence Feingold and Steven Long, and their position was also held by many of the classic Thomistic commentators from the sixteenth through the early twentieth centuries.Footnote 8 The key premise of this argument, a premise formulated by Cajetan (1469–1534)Footnote 9 and shared explicitly or implicitly by all adherents of the first solution, is that for Aquinas natural desire cannot extend to goods that are not naturally attainable. Hence, the human person's natural desire for beatitude must be fulfilled by a purely natural good, and thus the ultimate end that perfects human nature is natural rather than supernatural.

Among contemporary scholars, the view that human nature's proper perfection and beatitude is purely natural and that consequently Aquinas's ethics and political science are philosophical is also held by Jean Porter,Footnote 10 Ernest Fortin,Footnote 11 and Livio Melina,Footnote 12 although without the extensive elaboration found in Feingold, Long, and their Scholastic antecedents. Proponents of the first solution, moreover, do not deny that according to Aquinas God has de facto elevated the human person to the beatific vision as a second final end, but their position entails that in Aquinas's understanding this good is not the fulfillment of our natural desire for beatitude and thus cannot be considered the end and perfection of human nature as such, that is, of man as man.

The problem with this interpretation is that in the key texts at issue,Footnote 13 Aquinas claims that the vision of the divine essence alone constitutes the complete perfection of the intellectual power. The reason for this is that a power is not perfected until it attains its object, and the object of the intellect is essence or quiddity. Short of knowing the highest essence—God's—the intellect thus does not fully attain its object and hence remains imperfect.Footnote 14 This claim has been overlooked by Feingold, Long, and those who share their interpretation, but is decisive in establishing that the supernatural beatific vision is the only end that completely perfects human nature and satisfies its natural desire for beatitude. For Aquinas, the perfection of a nature consists in the perfection of its highest power, and human nature's highest power is the intellect.Footnote 15 Hence, to assert that the vision of God's essence is the complete perfection of the intellect is to assert that it constitutes the complete perfection of human nature. In turn, since the good that completely perfects human nature is the good that fully satisfies its natural desire and constitutes its beatitude, it follows that only the vision of God satisfies man's natural desire and represents his beatitude.Footnote 16 Aquinas never asserts that the natural desire for beatitude must be satisfied by a purely natural good, as even early critics of Cajetan's view, such as Francisco de Vitoria (1483–1546), realized.Footnote 17 For Aquinas, the end of man as man is therefore supernatural, and this first solution rests on a misinterpretation of Aquinas's understanding of the finis ultimus.Footnote 18

The second solution to the Strauss-Bradley dilemma claims that ethics and political science can depend essentially on supernatural knowledge about our ultimate end and still be philosophy. This position prima facie allows one to admit, with Strauss and Bradley, that there is no purely natural end that completely perfects human nature, while still preserving the philosophical character of ethics and politics. The foremost proponent of this paradoxical solution is Jacques Maritain. In his work on what he calls “moral philosophy adequately considered,”Footnote 19 Maritain holds that moral philosophy―which includes both ethics and political science―is a subalternated science to theology, and that this does not impact its status as philosophy.Footnote 20 On analogy with other subalternated sciences such as optics, which borrows on trust its principles from the higher science of geometry, taking them as hypotheses without demonstrating them, moral philosophy can assume as hypotheses premises about the supernatural end that are the object of theology. However, although ethics and political science presuppose as hypotheses the theological premises that man has a supernatural end and that virtuous activity in this life is a good worth pursuing by individuals and political communities because it is ordered to this end, ethics and political science are still formally philosophy rather than theology because they adopt a “human” or “earthly” instead of a “divine” perspective on human acts. They focus principally on the acquisition and practice of the natural virtues in this life rather than the achievement of the ultimate supernatural end through charity and the infused virtues. For Maritain, the fact that ethics and political science depend for their validity on claims about the supernatural end that can only be known through divine revelation is no obstacle to identifying these sciences as properly philosophical and essentially distinct from theology since, unlike the latter, ethics and politics primarily consider goods attainable in the present life. Among contemporary scholars, William McCormick is sympathetic to Maritain's solution.Footnote 21

Vernon Bourke offers another variant of the second solution.Footnote 22 He claims that for Aquinas only the vision of the divine essence could satisfy our natural desire for beatitude and that the philosopher can recognize that such a vision is beyond the capacity of unaided nature to attain. Moreover, the philosopher cannot prove that man has been given the grace necessary to attain this vision, and hence he or she cannot recognize that it is, in point of fact, the goal of human life. Nevertheless, although philosophy cannot prove that supernatural beatitude is in fact our ultimate end, it would be reasonable for the philosopher to believe that it is the ultimate goal of human life if he or she can show that, as a matter of empirically verifiable fact, the notion of a supernatural end has brought “rational order” into individuals’ lives.Footnote 23 History, Bourke continues, proves that the concept of supernatural beatitude has indeed brought such order into individuals’ lives, specifically in the lives of Christian saints. The philosopher therefore has a plausible reason to suppose that the vision of God is the ultimate end of human life―even though he cannot prove this definitively―and he is therefore justified in determining what constitutes temporal happiness or the first principle of ethics and political science based on what is conducive to supernatural beatitude. For Bourke as for Maritain, the fact that philosophy cannot prove demonstratively that our ultimate end is supernatural is no obstacle to asserting the philosophical character of a science of human action in this life that presupposes this end as its first principle.

This solution is also inadequate. As critics of Maritain such as Bradley and Santiago Ramírez observe,Footnote 24 an argument or science is not formally philosophical unless it is purely rational. If a science depends for its validity on a premise that can only be known through divine revelation, it is not philosophy but theology. It is not enough to claim with Maritain that ethics and politics can presuppose premises about our supernatural end as undemonstrated hypotheses on analogy with other subalternated sciences and still remain essentially distinct from theology simply because they focus primarily on the acquisition and practice of natural virtue in this life. The fact that an account or justification of their first principle cannot ultimately be given without relying on the data of revelation―which is not the case with other subalternated sciences such as optics―means that they are formally theological rather than philosophical sciences. Nor is it sufficient to claim with Bourke that although the ultimate presuppositions of ethics and political science can be known with certainty only through revelation, these sciences are philosophical because the philosopher has probable cause to accept the validity of a supernatural end that would ultimately ground them. For a science to be philosophical, the truth of its premises and presuppositions must be knowable with certainty to unaided natural reason. And because the historical fact that the concept of a supernatural end has brought order into the lives of individuals is not sufficient to prove the truth value of the claim that man's final end is in fact the vision of God―as Bourke himself concedes―it is not sufficient to ground a philosophical ethics and political science. Philosophy cannot rest on premises which, in the final analysis, can be known only through revelation.

These two approaches to the Strauss-Bradley dilemma thus fail to solve the problem. Other prominent scholarly treatments of the theme of a philosophical ethics and political science in Aquinas's thought have not directly answered the question of how moral science can be philosophically grounded given that for Aquinas the ultimate end of human nature is supernatural. Ralph McInerny's treatment of the philosophical character of Thomistic ethics and political science is principally a rebuttal of Gauthier's claim that in identifying God as the ultimate end Aquinas makes an irreducibly theological assertion that compromises the philosophical character of his ethics and by extension his political science.Footnote 25 James Doig's study of the philosophical character of Aquinas's commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics is an argument against Harry Jaffa's claim that doctrines present in the commentary―such as the imperfection of earthly happiness and the existence of divine providence―are strictly revealed doctrines that compromise the work's philosophical character.Footnote 26 It does not offer a solution to the Strauss-Bradley dilemma. Further, although Martin Rhonheimer asserts that Aquinas's ethics and, by implication, political science are philosophical despite the fact that Thomas believes only the vision of the divine essence fully perfects human nature,Footnote 27 he does not offer an account of how Aquinas can both admit that human nature's beatitude and perfection is supernatural and ground an account of temporal happiness without reference to this end and hence without revelation.

Kevin Staley's treatment of the philosophical character of Aquinas's moral science likewise leaves us without a definitive solution. He argues that although for Aquinas the end of human nature is supernatural, Thomistic ethics and political science are philosophical because the temporal goods at which these sciences aim―such as friendship, political community, and philosophical contemplation―are genuine perfections of human nature.Footnote 28 The fact that such goods are perfections of human nature is sufficient to establish that they should be pursued by individuals and political communities and hence to vindicate the philosophical character of Aquinas's ethics and political science. This is not, however, a solution to the Strauss-Bradley dilemma because Staley does not explain how unaided human reason can establish these temporal pursuits as perfections given the supernatural character of human nature's final end—which is the crux of the problem Strauss and Bradley raise. Other notable studies of Aquinas's understanding of imperfect beatitude have likewise left the question unanswered.Footnote 29 The dilemma remains unresolved, and in the following section I offer a new solution which shows how Aquinas reconciles a supernatural end of human nature with a philosophical political and moral science.

2. Human Nature's Supernatural End and the Philosophical Character of Political Science

Although Strauss, Bradley, and the proponents of the two solutions differ in their conclusions, all agree that a coherent account of the goodness and order of human ends requires explaining this goodness and order precisely in terms of the relationship of these ends to the ultimate end that satisfies natural desire. BradleyFootnote 30 and Strauss reason that because this is the case, and because the ultimate end of human nature is supernatural, no account of the lower end of temporal happiness can be given without reference to revelation about the supernatural final end―for which reason political and moral science are theology rather than philosophy. Proponents of the first solution concede to Strauss and Bradley that an account of human ends can only be given in reference to the ultimate end that satisfies human nature's desire for its perfection,Footnote 31 but since our temporal happiness is this end, there is no question of needing to explain the first principle of ethics and politics in terms of its relationship to a supernatural good. Proponents of the second approach agree that accounting for the goodness and order of lower ends requires reference to the ultimate end of human nature, and further agree with Strauss and Bradley that for Aquinas human nature's finis ultimus is supernatural. However, they hold that this poses no challenge to the philosophical character of ethics and political science since these sciences can depend on revelation for an account of their first principle and nonetheless remain philosophy.

This shared claim that for Aquinas establishing the goodness and order of human ends requires knowledge of their relationship to the ultimate end of human nature is mistaken. It overlooks the structure of his argument for why, even though the ultimate end of human nature is the supernatural vision of God in the afterlife, naturally acquired virtue is superior to all other natural goods and hence constitutes our temporal happiness. Contrary to the assumption of the scholars we have examined, Aquinas's writings do not establish the superiority of the activity of naturally acquired virtue to other natural goods in the present life by adducing its relationship, order, or conduciveness to the supernatural perfect good. Rather, Aquinas shows this superiority by proving that virtuous activity more fully instantiates the attributes generally ascribed to beatitude or happiness, attributes such as self-sufficiency, continuity, and leisureliness, even if virtuous living in this life does not perfectly or completely instantiate these attributes. This way of establishing the superiority of virtuous activity to other temporal goods―in effect, by proving that it is the natural good which comes closest to fulfilling the general definition of beatitude―requires no appeal to the supernatural end even though it is compatible with the assertion that such an end is the only good that fully perfects human nature. The argument does not rest on revelation, and thus a strictly rational or philosophical justification of the first principle of political science can be given.

In several texts Aquinas identifies the general attributes of beatitude and argues that, among temporal activities, the activity of acquired virtue―principally the contemplative activity of the intellectual virtue of wisdom, and secondarily the activity of moral virtueFootnote 32―more fully instantiates these attributes than do other temporal goods even though it does not perfectly instantiate them; indeed, he suggests that only the beatific vision could completely satisfy these criteria. Six attributes of beatitude can be identified, and a consideration of Aquinas's treatment of them reveals the purely philosophical structure of his account of temporal happiness. He elaborates two of these criteria in ST I-II.3.5. First, beatitude is an activity or “operation” of man's highest power in respect of its highest object. The human person's highest power is the speculative intellect, whose highest object is the divine good. Hence, happiness must consist in contemplation of the divine good. Second, beatitude must be an operation common to human beings and higher, immaterial substances―not an operation in which purely material animals share. Only contemplation is the exclusive preserve of immaterial beings; morally virtuous action has something in common with animal action, since it is action bearing on material things.Footnote 33 Hence, beatitude must consist in contemplative activity.

Aquinas admits that these two attributes of beatitude are perfectly fulfilled only in contemplative activity in the next life: “Therefore the last and perfect happiness, which we await in the life to come, consists entirely in contemplation.”Footnote 34 We can readily infer why he thinks this. The highest way of contemplating the intellect's highest object, the divine good (God), is not contemplating God's existence and attributes but rather his essence,Footnote 35 which could only occur in the afterlife.Footnote 36 Moreover, the beatitude of God and the angels consists in contemplation of the divine essence, and only in such contemplation would human beatitude be perfectly common to that of immaterial beings.Footnote 37 But we can also see why these attributes are, among temporal goods, most fulfilled by philosophical contemplation and hence why it is the “most perfect operation of this life.”Footnote 38 Philosophical contemplation of God's existence and attributes is a form of contemplation of the highest object (the divine good) of the human person's highest power (the speculative intellect), even if it is not the highest form of contemplation of that object. Moreover, as a species of contemplative activity, it has nothing in common with animal felicity, but it does have something in common with the beatitude of God and the angels,Footnote 39 who also have perfect knowledge of the divine attributes. Hence it more fully instantiates the attributes of perfect beatitude than do other temporal goods, even if it does not perfectly instantiate them.

Thomas identifies a third attribute of beatitude in ST I-II.3.2, namely, that the operation in which it consists must be one, continuous, and everlasting. This can be achieved only in the beatific vision. In the present life, contemplation cannot be continuous, and hence nor can it be one, since discontinuity implies multiplicity of operation.Footnote 40 Nevertheless, he claims in this text that among earthly goods, philosophical contemplation is the most unitary and continuous, since the active life is busy with a multiplicity of things and as such has, as an operation, less unity and continuity than does contemplative activity.

Further attributes of beatitude which apply, preeminently among temporal goods, to philosophical contemplation are found in Aquinas's Ethics commentary. For example, beatitude or happiness is a “self-sufficient” operation, that is, an operation lacking in nothing.Footnote 41 But contemplation is especially self-sufficient since, once the necessities of life which allow for the maintenance of bodily existence are provided for, contemplative operation requires no further external goods for its performance.Footnote 42 By contrast, the activity of moral virtue requires external things for its exercise, such as persons to whom one can be just. Thus, acts of moral virtue are, qua acts, less self-sufficient than contemplation.Footnote 43 Of course, inasmuch as certain external goods are required for the maintenance of bodily health needed to undertake philosophical contemplation, this contemplation cannot be described as absolutely lacking in nothing and self-sufficient. Only the beatific vision is a self-sufficient operation, since in it one possesses the totality of goodness such that nothing whatsoever is lacking.Footnote 44 Nevertheless, philosophical contemplation is the most self-sufficient activity among humanly attainable operations.

A fifth attribute of beatitude is that it brings leisure―repose in the end attained―and a state of affairs in which one has nothing further to do.Footnote 45 Only contemplative activity, however, brings such leisure and repose. The activity of moral virtues, even in their most noble form of exercise (political life), is not accompanied by leisure, since the practice of politics leaves something left to be done—specifically, contemplation.Footnote 46 By contrast, we do not apply ourselves to contemplative activity for the sake of some other good, and accordingly it brings more leisure and repose than do other goods.Footnote 47 Of course, contemplation of truth in this life does not bring complete repose since it is not possible for any temporal good to do so. As Aquinas writes, “contemplative activity of the intellect clearly provides for man the attributes customarily assigned to the happy person: self-sufficiency, leisureliness, and freedom from labor. And I say this insofar as it is possible for man living a mortal life in which such things cannot exist perfectly.”Footnote 48 Presumably, the reason why complete leisureliness is impossible in this life is because, at some point, the philosopher will have to cease contemplation to provide for his or her bodily needs. At no time, therefore, does he attain perfect rest or leisure; on the contrary, only the beatific vision constitutes the complete good that leaves absolutely nothing left to seek.Footnote 49 But contemplation in this life undoubtedly brings more repose than does the activity of moral virtue, and thus it more closely approximates the perfect leisureliness that characterizes beatitude tout court.

Finally, all admit that “delight” (delectatio) accompanies beatitude―a sixth criterion. Now, among all virtuous activities, contemplation in accordance with wisdom is most delightful. This is because the delights of wisdom are most pure since contemplation regards immaterial objects, and they are most permanent since the objects of contemplation are most unchangeable.Footnote 50 However, philosophical contemplation in this life cannot be perfectly delightful because, so long as we are in this world, we undergo change, and perfect delight can only come from an activity that is simple and unchanging―such as God's utterly simple and unchanging activity of knowing his own essence.Footnote 51 Likewise, delight follows from an object's goodness,Footnote 52 but in our contemplation in this life we do not possess the perfect good. Only in the vision of God is the complete or perfect good possessed,Footnote 53 and thus only this vision brings perfect delight. Yet because philosophical contemplation in this life, in contrast to other activities (including the moral virtues), does regard immaterial objects that are unchanging in themselves, it brings more delectatio than does any other temporal good.

These arguments from the Summa and Ethics commentaryFootnote 54 all prove the same conclusion: that philosophical contemplation is the most perfect activity attainable by unaided human nature in the present life and thus the activity that bears the greatest likeness to beatitude among all purely temporal activities. Beatitude consists in an operation that is continuous, leisurely, self-sufficient, maximally delightful, shared with the immaterial beings, and related to the highest object of the human person's highest power. Among temporal, naturally attainable goods, philosophical contemplation is the most continuous, most leisurely, most self-sufficient, most delightful, most common to man and the separate substances, and most directly related to the highest object that the intellect can contemplate—even if it does not fully or perfectly instantiate these attributes. That philosophical contemplation more fully corresponds to the general attributes and definition of beatitude than do other temporal goods implies that it is more excellent, desirable, and choiceworthy than these goods. Aquinas states that the intellectual virtues are properly speaking better even than the moral virtuesFootnote 55―to say nothing of lower goods―and that the moral virtues are means to the attainment of intellectual virtue inasmuch as the acts of the former are ordered to the acts of the latter.Footnote 56 The contemplative person, as long as he or she lives in this world, needs the necessities of life, and thus he or she needs moral virtue so as to relate well to these temporal goods. But since these goods are clearly for the sake of enabling contemplation, so are the habits of moral virtue that order us well in respect of them.

This is not to say that for Aquinas one can choose to pursue only the acquired intellectual virtue of wisdom without cultivating the moral virtues and still attain to true temporal happiness. Since such happiness requires the perfection as far as possible of the rational part of the soul,Footnote 57 and since the sense appetites belong to the rational part of the soul by participation inasmuch as they come under the command of reason,Footnote 58 it follows that temporal happiness would require acquisition of the moral virtues that bring the passions fully under the control of reason in addition to the contemplative activity of wisdom that perfects the intellect. Nor does Aquinas's argument preclude him from claiming that participation in supernatural grace in the present life brings an even higher form of happiness than the activity of acquired intellectual and moral virtue. Indeed, he states that those who possess the gifts of the Holy Spirit have, in the present life, an inchoate participation in the happiness of the next, since they possess a knowledge of divine mysteries that surpasses the grasp of natural reason.Footnote 59 The clear implication is that the incomplete supernatural beatitude of the present life is, because supernatural, an even higher form of beatitude than philosophical contemplation.

What Aquinas's argument does do, however, is establish a clear hierarchy among natural goods, with virtuous activity—principally contemplative, but secondarily moral—at its summit. In establishing the greater choiceworthiness and thus superordination of philosophical contemplation with respect to other natural goods no argumentative appeal has been made to its conduciveness to the ultimate end. The relationship of the good of philosophical contemplation to the supernatural final end has not been adduced to establish its primacy over other temporal goods. On the contrary, this supremacy has been shown solely by analyzing the general attributes of beatitude―attributes knowable to unaided reason―and assessing the degrees to which various temporal goods instantiate these attributes. This argumentative structure allows Aquinas to prove by unaided reason that the happiness or beatitude found in philosophical contemplation is superior to other temporal goods even though, in itself, it is an imperfect good that is not ultimate. Since it is thus possible for reason to give an account of temporal happiness, the first principle of politicsFootnote 60 and ethics, these sciences are genuinely philosophical even though the ultimate end which alone satisfies natural desire is the supernatural vision of God.

3. Political Philosophy and the Subordination of Temporal to Spiritual Authority

We have seen that, for Aquinas, a rational account of temporal happiness can be given of the sort necessary for a philosophical political science that takes this happiness as its first principle, the good at which it aims. Nevertheless, De regno, a gift for the king of Cyprus exhorting him to govern justly and avoid tyranny,Footnote 61 seems to challenge the possibility of a strictly rational account of political happiness. Discussing “the origin of kingly government and the things which pertain to the office of the king,”Footnote 62 Aquinas states that the end of political life is virtuous living or the common good, and that the attainment of this end is the prerogative of the king in virtue of his office.Footnote 63 However, this is not the human person's ultimate end; indeed, virtuous living exists for the sake of a higher end, namely, supernatural beatitude with God in the afterlife. As he writes, “through virtuous living man is further ordained to a higher end, which consists in the enjoyment of God. . . . Consequently, since society must have the same end as the individual man, it is not the ultimate end of an assembled multitude to live virtuously, but through virtuous living to attain to the possession of God.”Footnote 64

If political society is ordained to the higher end of eternal beatitude, the question arises whether the promotion of eternal beatitude is an intrinsic element of the properly political good, such that promoting the supernatural end enters into the formal specification of the bonum civile that the king qua king is charged with procuring. If the answer is affirmative, then supernatural revelation is necessary for politics to carry out its proper task―promotion of the civic good―and a philosophical political science is impossible. Later in De regno, Aquinas appears to conclude that because virtuous living in the political community is ultimately ordered to a supernatural end, and because one who has charge over something that is ordained to a further end must ensure that the thing made is suitable to that end, the king is bound to govern in a way that makes citizens fit for the kingdom of God, taking explicit account of Christian beatitude in his political decision making:

Now anyone on whom it devolves to do something which is ordained to another thing as to its end is bound to see that his work is suitable to that end. . . . Therefore, since the beatitude of heaven is the end of that virtuous life which we live at present, it pertains to the king's office to promote the good life of the multitude in such a way as to make it suitable for the attainment of heavenly happiness; that is to say, the king should command those things which lead to the happiness of heaven and, as far as possible, forbid the contrary.

What conduces to true beatitude and what hinders it are learned from the law of God, the teaching of which belongs to the office of the priest. . . . Thus the king, taught the law of God [by the priest], should have for his principal concern the means by which the multitude subject to him may live well.Footnote 65

This passage seems to imply that, for Aquinas, the political good by its very nature includes the active ordering of man to his ultimate end, such that, if a ruler does not expressly govern the citizens with a view towards preparing them for eternal life, he has failed in his duties qua ruler and has failed to uphold the specifically political good. Several scholars have interpreted De regno in this way. Citing its subordination of virtuous living to supernatural beatitude, Charles McCoy draws the conclusion that, on account of this subordination, the common good is “specified integrally by being properly ordinated to the last end.”Footnote 66 For McCoy, the direction of citizens to eternal beatitude is thus formally included within the bonum civile, and it is therefore only insofar as politics serves as a means to the supernatural end that it realizes its proper good as politics. Benjamin Smith argues that, given De regno's subordination of moral or political virtue to the end of eternal beatitude, “theology (insofar as it is related to the ultimate end) reshapes the discourse of politics by introducing the conclusions of theology as principles in practical political deliberation.”Footnote 67 Politics takes as its first principle the theological conclusion that man is ordered to a supernatural ultimate end and makes practical decisions about how to order the affairs of the city based on what best promotes citizens’ attainment of this end. The task of politics qua politics is therefore to serve as a means to our supernatural end. On such an interpretation of De regno, the political good by its very nature includes the express promotion of eternal beatitude, and revealed knowledge concerning the supernatural end is by implication necessary for a complete account of the bonum civile.

Nevertheless, if we read De regno in conjunction with other Thomistic texts, it becomes clear that this is not Aquinas's view.Footnote 68 First, in a range of texts spanning the length of his career―including De regno Footnote 69―Aquinas frequently affirms that the ruler is the “supreme authority” in political matters.Footnote 70 To maintain, however, that the king is the supreme political authority seems incompatible with claiming that the political good includes as a constitutive element the promotion of eternal beatitude. If promotion of this end were an intrinsic element of the specifically political good, then, contrary to Aquinas's stated position, the Catholic church rather than the king would have final or supreme say in all political affairs, since all political affairs would be reducible to mere means to the supernatural beatitude over which the church has ultimate custody. These texts suggest a formal distinction between the political and supernatural goods, between kingly and ecclesiastical office, that does not subordinate the former to the latter in all affairs, as would be the case if promoting eternal beatitude were an essential part of the political good. Further, Aquinas clearly distinguishes the “earthly city” which aims at the happiness brought about by naturally acquired virtue from the “heavenly society of Jerusalem”—eternal beatitude—of which man is made a citizen not by acquired virtue but only by supernaturally infused virtue.Footnote 71 The implication is that the two cities and the authorities which govern them have formally distinct goods and that promoting the beatitude of the heavenly city does not enter into the task of the earthly city qua earthly city, since progress towards eternal beatitude requires supernatural virtues that politics—which belongs to the natural order—could never produce.

The text in which the formal distinction between spiritual and temporal authority is most fully articulated, and from which emerges most clearly the specification of the political good as an independent good that does not include express promotion of the finis ultimus, is found in the commentary on Sentences II. Discussing the relationship between spiritual and temporal power, Aquinas explains that there are two ways in which a higher and a lower power are related. In one way, the lower power is derived completely from the higher, as the authority of a lower government official is derived completely from that of the emperor.Footnote 72 The higher power is to be obeyed before the lower in all things. In the second way, however, there is only a qualified subjection of the lower power to the higher:

[A] higher and lower power can be such that each arises from some supreme power which arranges them in relation to each other as it wishes. In this case, the one will not be subject to the other save in respect of those things in which it has been subjected to the other by the supreme power; and only in such things are we to obey the higher power before the lower. . . . Spiritual and secular power are both derived from the divine power, and so secular power is subject to spiritual power insofar as this is ordered by God: that is, in those things which pertain to the salvation of the soul. In such matters, then, the spiritual power is to be obeyed before the secular. But in those things which pertain to the civil good, the secular power should be obeyed before the spiritual.Footnote 73

Aquinas holds that the kingly office is specified by the civic good, whereas the priestly office is specified by “the salvation of souls”―eternal beatitude. By a divine ordinance, the king is subject to the priest in matters bearing directly on the attainment of this supernatural end,Footnote 74 while in matters bearing solely on the civic good, the priest is subject to the king. The implication is that whenever the king takes measures directly aimed at promoting the supernatural end, as distinguished from those which only bear on the political end, he is acting to promote an end that formally belongs not to him but rather to the priest. In matters bearing on eternal beatitude, the king acts only as the subject of the priest, on the priest's authority and thus as his instrument in the attainment of a good that pertains to the priestly office alone—a good that does not come under the charge of the king qua king or the bonum civile the king is tasked with promoting.

Further, according to the text, the obligation of the ruler to promote eternal beatitude as the subject and instrument of the priest arises not from the nature of political office itself but rather from a special divine ordinance establishing the relation and order between spiritual and temporal power―an ordinance which, as we will see, Aquinas identifies elsewhere with the New Law. This ordinance is entirely extrinsic and accidental to the obligations that pertain to the king qua a ruler tasked with procuring the common good. Of course, the king in virtue of his duty to promote the bonum politicum is bound to prescribe acts of natural virtue and prohibit acts of vice, and insofar as this incidentally aids in the attainment of supernatural beatitude by removing obstacles to it, the king can be said to promote the supernatural end indirectly. But he exercises independent authority in these matters only insofar as they are directed towards the realization of the civic good. Any benefit that accrues to citizens in respect of the supernatural good is strictly incidental to the promotion of the political good that is the king's proper task, and if an act does not bear on the attainment of the bonum civile, then the king has no right to make legislation about it. Even when an action does bear on the bonum civile, if it also bears on the supernatural end—as in the case of Christian marriage—the king can regulate it only insofar as the spiritual authority allows him to do so, and only in view of the temporal good.Footnote 75

Some examples of political promotion of the supernatural end that Aquinas adduces illustrate the strictly instrumental role that political authority plays in promoting eternal beatitude. He states that it belongs to the church to determine whether the religious rites of non-Christians are to be tolerated or forcibly repressed for the sake of advancing the supernatural end.Footnote 76 He makes the same observation concerning the suppression of heresy, arguing that the church decides whether to condemn heretics and hand them over to the temporal authority for capital punishment: “If [the heretic] is yet stubborn, the Church, no longer hoping for his conversion, looks to the salvation of others, by excommunicating him and separating him from the Church, and furthermore delivers him to the secular tribunal to be exterminated thereby from the world by death.”Footnote 77 Similarly, in order to force schismatics to return to the church for the sake of their salvation, the church “employs the compulsion of the secular arm [i.e., the state]” for this purpose.Footnote 78

In these Summa texts, Aquinas envisages the temporal power undertaking the actions described not on its own authority but only at the behest of the church, which uses or instrumentalizes state power for specific actions directly intended to promote the attainment of supernatural beatitude.Footnote 79 His assertion in each passage that the church decides whether and how the state is to punish sins against the faith that undermine the attainment of our supernatural end suggests that it is the prerogative of the church, not the state, to make such decisions, and the logical explanation for the church's exclusive right to take such actions is that they bear on an end that the spiritual authority alone is tasked with promoting.

Key passages in De regno articulate the same understanding of the relationship of temporal to spiritual authority found in other works, namely, that the authority of the ruler qua ruler extends solely to actions bearing on the human person's temporal end; that the king is bound to promote supernatural beatitude only as directed by the ecclesiastical power and hence as its instrument; and that this obligation arises not from the political good itself but rather from an extrinsic divine ordinance or law. In the same text in which Aquinas writes that the king, having custody over a lower end, should make laws that render men apt for the higher end of eternal beatitude, he adds that these laws are learned from the teaching of the priests and hence that it is only as taught or instructed by the priest that the king should promote the citizens’ eternal beatitude.Footnote 80 This qualification―which has been overlooked in scholarship on the passage―suggests that it is only under the direction of priests that kings make ordinances that are expressly intended to promote heavenly beatitude, and, by implication, that kings make such ordinances not in service of their own proper end but strictly as appendages of the ecclesiastical power in the attainment of its own, formally distinct end.

Moreover, in De regno 2.3, Aquinas writes that “all the kings of the Christian people are to be subject [to the pope] as to our Lord Jesus Christ Himself” inasmuch as they are bound to obey papal commands in matters pertaining to the supernatural end.Footnote 81 Of note is Aquinas's qualification that only the rulers of Christian peoples are bound to be subject to priests (principally the pope) in promoting eternal beatitude, not the rulers of all peoples. This suggests that the obligation to promote the supernatural end arises not from the nature of political office itself―since otherwise all political rulers would be obliged to obey the pope―but only from the fact that the ruler is Christian. Aquinas confirms in the subsequent paragraph that the obligation to promote the supernatural end arises from an ordinance extrinsic to the political good and hence is not part of the bonum civile as such. Contrasting the obligations of kings in relation to priests before and after the coming of Christ, he writes:

Because the priesthood of the gentiles and the whole worship of their gods existed merely for the acquisition of temporal goods (which were all ordained to the common good of the multitude, whose care devolved upon the king), the priests of the gentiles were fittingly [convenienter] subject to the kings. Similarly, since in the Old Law earthly goods were promised to the religious people (not indeed by demons but by the true God), the priests of the Old Law, we read, were also subject to the kings. But in the New Law there is a higher priesthood by which men are guided to heavenly goods. Consequently, in the law of Christ, kings must be subject to priests.Footnote 82

The text affirms that the obligation of kings to be subject to priests arises only under the “law of Christ” or the New Law, a law which is not binding for all times or on all persons but only on Christians.Footnote 83 The king qua king is not obliged to order the body politic under the direction of the priests with the explicit aim of making it “suitable for the attainment of heavenly happiness”―except insofar as his promotion of the civic good of virtuous living incidentally promotes this beatitude by removing obstacles to it―but the king qua Christian is under such an obligation because of his acceptance of the New Law and the additional obligations arising from it.Footnote 84 Specifically, he is under an obligation to do what the ecclesiastical power orders him to do in those matters which bear directly on the attainment of the ultimate end over which the church has sole charge. Thus, when Aquinas urges the Cypriot monarch in De regno to “command those things which lead to the happiness of heaven and, as far as possible, forbid the contrary,” and to make the multitude “suitable for heavenly happiness”―a text which, as we have seen, suggests prima facie that promoting supernatural beatitude is a constitutive element of the political good―Aquinas's meaning is that his addressee should carry out his specifically Christian duties as a Christian king to follow ecclesiastical directives in matters bearing on the eternal salvation of the citizens. His meaning is not that qua king the Cypriot prince's role is to promote the human person's supernatural end, but only that as a Christian ruler he is obliged to carry out through legislation the church's directives in matters directly pertaining to the ultimate end, an end over which the church has exclusive custody.

In a work that is a hortatory letter rather than a scientific treatise, it is not surprising that, in lines exhorting the prince to govern well precisely as a Christian king, Aquinas would not parse the exhortation into those obligations his addressee is bound to carry out qua king as distinguished from those which he is bound to carry out qua a Christian under the New Law―even though, as we have seen, the distinction is implied in the passages urging the king to legislate with an eye towards heavenly beatitude as instructed by the priest. Indeed, as Marc Guerra has observed, citing the example of the foundations of justice, De regno often presupposes a range of concepts that are developed fully only in Aquinas's theoretical works.Footnote 85 The doctrine that a state's political promotion of supernatural beatitude is strictly an instrument used by the church in the service of the church's own end, an end entirely separate from the state's, is thus the same in De regno as in the other Thomistic texts we have considered, as is its teaching that the ruler's obligation to advance the cause of heavenly beatitude arises not from the nature of the political good itself but rather from a special divine ordinance, namely, the New Law or “law of Christ.” Explicit ordering of political life to the finis ultimus is thus not a constitutive element of the bonum civile, and when Aquinas affirms that the political good of virtuous living is ordained to eternal beatitude as to a further end, he means only that it is ordained to such an end by an extrinsic divine law―not by its very nature. The bonum politicum remains a purely natural good. This analysis does not entail, of course, that the political good is strictly secular. On the contrary, for Aquinas religion understood as rendering thanksgiving to God qua creator and providential governor of the universe is a natural virtue that is a part of justice and thus the common good, for which reason even non-Christian kings are bound to public acts of monotheistic worship.Footnote 86 But the analysis does mean that the bonum civile is naturally attainable and knowable by human reason without the aid of divine revelation.

4. Conclusion

The problem that Strauss and Bradley raise concerning the possibility of a philosophical ethics and political science, a problem that has long been an object of scholarly debate, admits of a definitive solution on the basis of Aquinas's texts. Ultimately, the key to realizing how Aquinas can maintain both that the ultimate end of man as man is supernatural and that political science is genuinely philosophical is recognizing the fact that, in his view, unaided reason can give an account of political happiness that establishes its superordination over other temporal goods without appealing to its relation to human nature's final end. The primacy of virtuous activity over other temporal goods derives from the fact that it more fully instantiates the general attributes of beatitude and thus is more worthy of pursuit than they are. It does not rest on claims about the relation, order, or conduciveness of earthly happiness to the perfect good of supernatural beatitude, contrary to the assumption of Strauss, Bradley, and most other scholars. The sciences concerning the attainment of temporal happiness by the individual and the political community are thus philosophical, since the desirability of the end that constitutes their first principle and the superiority of this end to other temporal ends can be established without revelation. Of course, temporal happiness is still for Aquinas an imperfect form of beatitude. It does not fully measure up to the definition of beatitude as the perfect and self-sufficient good that fulfills all human desire,Footnote 87 and the philosopher, knowing that natural desire cannot be satisfied by any naturally attainable good, can know the imperfection of the beatitude of the present life. But even in the knowledge of the imperfection of all temporal goods, the philosopher still knows by the unaided light of natural reason that some goods are more perfect than others and ought to be pursued as such.

The significance for Thomistic political philosophy of finding a solution to the Strauss-Bradley problem can hardly be overstated, and the interpretation of Aquinas advanced here has important consequences for other aspects of his political thought. As Henry Veatch has observed, a Thomistic account of rights that is genuinely philosophical requires a rational account of the common good or happiness that constitutes the first principle of politics, since in Aquinas's understanding rights are derived from what is conducive to this good.Footnote 88 Likewise, as Mortimer Adler and Walter Farrell suggest, a rational account of the political good, the temporal happiness of the body politic, is necessary for a philosophical account of good and bad regimes, since good regimes promote natural flourishing or the common good of the citizens while bad regimes undermine it.Footnote 89 Ultimately, what is at stake is the ability of unaided reason to make claims about what is good and evil, just and unjust, in the spheres of both morals and politics, and thus the possibility of dialogue on the basis of Thomistic philosophy between Christian believers and those outside the Christian faith about moral and political questions. By establishing the philosophical character of Aquinas's science of politics and the naturalness of the political good, the interpretation I have elaborated suggests that such a dialogue is indeed possible, and it highlights the foundational principles or goods on the basis of which such a dialogue can take place.

References

1 Aquinas, Thomas, Commentary on Aristotle's “Nicomachean Ethics” (Sententia libri Ethicorum), trans. C. J. Litzinger, OP (Chicago: Regnery, 1964; repr. Notre Dame, IN: Dumb Ox Books, 1993), 1.1.3–6Google Scholar (hereafter SLE). Translations of Aquinas are from the editions cited, with minor modifications based on the Leonine Latin text. See Thomas Aquinas, Opera omnia (Rome: Leonine Commission, 1882–).

2 Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle's “Politics” (Sententia libri Politicorum), trans. Richard Regan (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2007), prol., 2.

3 Strauss, Leo, Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 163–64Google Scholar.

4 Bradley, Denis, Aquinas on the Twofold Human Good: Reason and Human Happiness in Aquinas's Moral Science (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1997), 375Google Scholar.

5 SLE 1.2.30–31; SLE 1.19.225; Aquinas, On Kingship, to the King of Cypress (De regno), trans. Gerald Phelan (Toronto: Pontifical Institute for Medieval Studies, 1949), 2.3.106 (hereafter DR).

6 Bradley, Aquinas, 492. See also SLE 1.12.139.

7 Bradley, Aquinas, 528.

8 Feingold, Lawrence, The Natural Desire to See God According to St. Thomas Aquinas and His Interpreters, 2nd ed. (Naples, FL: Sapientia, 2010), 1–46, 397428Google Scholar; Long, Steven A., “On the Possibility of a Purely Natural End for Man,” The Thomist 64 (2000): 211–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Long, Steven A., Natura Pura: On the Recovery of Nature in the Doctrine of Grace (New York: Fordham University Press, 2010), 1051Google Scholar. For a review of the history of this position and critiques of it, see Feingold, Natural Desire, xxv–xxxvii.

9 Cajetan, commentary on Summa theologiae I.12.1, X (Leonine ed., 4:116). See Lubac, Henri de, Augustinisme et théologie moderne (Paris: Cerf, 2008), 183223Google Scholar, for a history of Cajetan's claim.

10 Porter, Jean, Nature as Reason: A Thomistic Theory of Natural Law (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2005), 158Google Scholar.

11 Ernest Fortin, “St. Thomas Aquinas,” in History of Political Philosophy, 3rd ed., ed. Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 252.

12 Livio Melina, La conoscenza morale: Linee di riflessione sul Commento di san Tommaso all'Etica Nicomachea (Rome: Città Nuova Editrice, 1987), 135–37.

13 Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (New York: Benziger Brothers, 1947–1948), I.12.1, I-II.3.8 (hereafter ST); Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, trans. Vernon J. Bourke (Garden City, NY: Hanover House, 1956; repr., Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1975), 3.51.1 (hereafter SCG).

14 ST I-II.3.7–8.

15 ST I-II.3.5.

16 ST I.26.2.

17 Francisco de Vitoria, De beatitudine, I-II.5.5, 3–4, ed. Augusto Sarmiento (Navarre: Eunsa, 2012), 167–70. Although Vitoria held that for Aquinas only the vision of God can satisfy the natural desire for beatitude, he does not explain how Thomas can give an account of natural happiness without reference to this ultimate end.

18 For a comprehensive critique of the first solution―which exceeds the scope of this article given the lengthy history of the debate over it―see Bradley, Aquinas, 424–534.

19 Jacques Maritain, Science and Wisdom, trans. Bernard Wall (New York: Scribner's, 1954), 110.

20 Ibid., 102–27, 174–209; Jacques Maritain, An Essay on Christian Philosophy, trans. Edward H. Flannery (New York: Philosophical Library, 1955), 38–43, 61–100.

21 William McCormick, SJ, “Jacques Maritain on Political Theology,” European Journal of Political Theory 12 (2013): 176–90.

22 Vernon Bourke, Ethics: A Textbook in Moral Philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 1951), 41–43.

23 Ibid., 41.

24 Bradley, Aquinas, 495–506; Santiago Ramírez, OP, review of Distinguer pour unir, ou Les degrés du savoir, by Jacques Maritain, Bulletin thomiste 4 (1934–1936): 423–32, cited in Bradley, Aquinas, 502.

25 Ralph McInerny, The Question of Christian Ethics (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1993), 21–38.

26 James Doig, Aquinas's Philosophical Commentary on the “Ethics”: A Historical Perspective (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2001), 109–93, especially 122–35.

27 Martin Rhonheimer, The Perspective of Morality: Philosophical Foundations of Thomistic Virtue Ethics, trans. Gerald Malsbary (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2011), 78–81.

28 Kevin Staley, “Happiness: The Natural End of Man?,” The Thomist 53 (1989): 229–31.

29 Anthony Celano, “The Concept of Worldly Beatitude in the Writings of Thomas Aquinas,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 25 (1987): 215–26; Jörn Müller, “Duplex beatitudo: Aristotle's Legacy and Aquinas's Conception of Human Happiness,” in Aquinas and the “Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Tobias Hoffmann, Jörn Müller, and Matthias Perkams (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 52–71.

30 “[For Aquinas] ‘penultimate’ ends can only be rightly understood in subordination to the ultimate end.” Bradley, Aquinas, 492.

31 For Aquinas “all ends [i.e., goods] derive their ‘end-likeness’ or very appetibility [and hence their goodness] from being further ordered to the last end.” Long, “Possibility,” 219.

32 ST I-II.3.5. Contemplation in accordance with wisdom is the speculative knowledge of the first cause and its causality in relation to created being, in other words, of God's existence, causality, and naturally knowable attributes. For Aquinas this specific form of contemplation constitutes temporal happiness.

33 ST I-II.3.5. See also SCG 3.34.6; SCG 3.35.5.

34 ST I-II.3.5.

35 ST I-II.3.8.

36 SCG 3.47; SCG 3.48.1.

37 ST I-II.3.2, ad 4.

38 ST I-II.3.3, ad 2.

39 SCG 3.37.4.

40 ST I-II.3.2, ad 4. See also SCG 3.48.7.

41 SLE 1.9.112, 114; SLE 10.10.2093.

42 SLE 10.10.2095. Friends, though a help to contemplation, are not necessary for it, since contemplative operations are internal to the agent. See SLE 10.10.2096.

43 SLE 10.10.2093–94. See also SCG 3.37.6.

44 ST I-II.5.4; ST I-II.4.7.

45 SLE 10.11.2098–99.

46 “The whole of political life seems directed [to contemplative happiness]; as long as the arrangement of political life establishes and preserves peace giving men the opportunity of contemplating truth” (SLE 10.11.2101).

47 SLE 10.11.2098–103.

48 SLE 10.11.2103.

49 ST I-II.4.1–2.

50 SLE 10.10.2090.

51 SLE 7.14.1535.

52 ST I-II.4.2.

53 ST I-II.5.4.

54 The Ethics commentary also repeats the Summa arguments which show that happiness consists in contemplation because of the continuity of contemplatio and because this activity is the act of the highest human power in respect of its highest object. See SLE 10.10.2088–89; SLE 10.10.2087.

55 ST I-II.66.3. He adds that because moral virtues direct the acts of all other powers, they correspond more to the nature of virtue since virtue is an act. Strictly speaking, however, intellectual virtues are better and more desirable.

56 SLE 10.12.2120; SLE 10.11.2101; SCG 3.37.7; and ST I-II.66.5.

57 SLE 1.10.127–28.

58 ST I-II.24.1, ad 2.

59 ST I-II.69.2. For further discussion of the principally contemplative character of this inchoate supernatural beatitude, see ST I-II.68.7; II-II.45.1–2; II-II.45.3, ad 1, 3; II-II.45.6.

60 As Charles De Koninck suggests, the philosophical contemplation that constitutes temporal happiness is the first principle of political science not in that the civic good is merely an instrument to the individual philosopher's contemplation, but rather in that the common good of the community requires for its realization that some devote themselves to contemplating the truth. All aspects of political life, as Aquinas maintains (see note 46), should be arranged so as to make this contemplation―the crowning element of the common good―possible. Charles De Koninck, The Primacy of the Common Good against the Personalists, trans. Ralph McInerny, in The Writings of Charles De Koninck, vol. 2 (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2009), 100; Charles De Koninck, In Defence of St. Thomas, trans. Ralph McInerny, in Writings of Charles De Koninck, 2:299–316. For further discussion of the noninstrumental character of the common good, see Lawrence Dewan, OP, “St. Thomas, John Finnis, and the Political Good,” The Thomist 64 (2000): 337–74; Michael Pakaluk, “Is the Common Good of Political Society Limited and Instrumental?,” Review of Metaphysics 55 (2001): 57–94; Gregory Froelich, “Ultimate End and Common Good,” The Thomist 57 (1993): 609–19.

61 On the text's hortatory character, see William McCormick, SJ, The Christian Structure of Politics: On the “De Regno” of Thomas Aquinas (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2022), 18–19; Mark Jordan, “De Regno and the Place of Political Thinking in Thomas Aquinas,” Medioevo 18 (1992): 151–68; Holly Hamilton Bleakley, “The Art of Ruling in Aquinas's De Regimine Principum,” History of Political Thought 20 (1999): 575–602.

62 DR, prol., 1.

63 DR 2.3.106.

64 DR 2.3.107.

65 DR 2.4.115–16.

66 Charles McCoy, “St. Thomas and Political Science,” in On the Intelligibility of Political Philosophy: Essays of Charles N. R. McCoy (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1989), 36.

67 Benjamin Smith, “Political Theology and Thomas Aquinas: A Reading of the De Regno,” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 84 (2010): 103–4.

68 Some scholars claim that De regno is in tension with Aquinas's other works on the relation of the political good to the supernatural end. I. T. Eschmann, “St. Thomas Aquinas on the Two Powers,” Mediaeval Studies 20 (1958): 177–205; Paul Sigmund, “Law and Politics,” in The Cambridge Companion to Aquinas, ed. Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 219. But as we will see, this is not the case. For critiques of Eschmann, see McCormick, William SJ, “‘A Unity of Order’: Aquinas on the End of Politics,” Nova et Vetera 21 (2023): 1019–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Leonard Boyle, OP, “The De Regno and the Two Powers,” in Facing History: A Different Thomas Aquinas (Louvain-la-Neuve: Collège Cardinal Mercier, 2000), 1–12; Fitzgerald, Laurence OP, “St. Thomas Aquinas and the Two Powers,” Angelicum 56 (1979): 515–56Google Scholar.

69 DR 2.3.108.

70 Aquinas, Scriptum super libros Sententiarum IV, d. 20, q. 1, a. 4, qca. 3, sol. 3, ad 2 (hereafter Sent.); Aquinas, Super Epistolam B. Pauli ad Hebraeos lectura, c. V, l. 1; ST I-II.104.1, ad 1. Cited in Fitzgerald, “Aquinas and the Two Powers,” 545–46.

71 Aquinas, On the Virtues in General, in Disputed Questions on Virtue, trans. Jeffrey Hause and Claudia Murphy (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2010), art. 9, resp., 141–56.

72 Sent. II, d. 44, q. 3, a. 4, in Aquinas: Political Writings, trans. R. W. Dyson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 277–78.

73 Sent. II, d. 44, q. 3, a. 4, in Aquinas: Political Writings, 278. Emphasis added.

74 See also ST II-II.60.6, ad 3.

75 ST III supp. 57.2, ad 4. Aquinas holds, however, that since only sacramental marriage involving Christians is ordered to eternal beatitude, the church lacks authority to regulate marriages between non-Christians. These marriages bear solely on the temporal good and thus fall entirely under the state's jurisdiction. ST III supp. 59.2.

76 ST II-II.10.11.

77 ST II-II.11.3.

78 ST II-II.39.4, ad 3.

79 See also Sent. IV, d. 37, q. 2, a. 2, exp. text. For further discussion of Aquinas's view of the church's coercive authority, see Reichberg, Gregory, “Scholastic Arguments for and against Religious Freedom,” The Thomist 84 (2020): 150CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Mary Keys, Aquinas, Aristotle, and the Promise of the Common Good (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 226–34; Charles McCoy, The Structure of Political Thought: A Study in the History of Political Ideas (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1963), 120.

80 DR 2.4.115–16.

81 DR 2.3.110.

82 DR 2.3.111.

83 ST I-II.106.3.

84 Once a person accepts Christianity, it becomes a dictate of right reason and of natural law to abide by it inasmuch as it would be unreasonable to reject divinely revealed truth. This obligation, however, does not belong to the natural law absolutely considered, since only those to whom Christianity has been revealed are bound by it. See ST II-II.81.2, ad 3; ST II-II.85.4; ST II-II.85.1, ad 1.

85 Guerra, Marc, “Beyond Natural Law Talk: Politics and Prudence in St. Thomas Aquinas's On Kingship,” Perspectives on Political Science 31 (2002): 13CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

86 ST II-II.81.1–3, 5; ST II-II.85.1, 4; ST II-II.94.1. On the political implications of natural religion for Aquinas, see McCormick, Christian Structure, 180; Douglas Kries, “The Virtue of Religion in the Political Thought of Thomas Aquinas,” Proceedings of the Patristic, Medieval, and Renaissance Conference 15 (1990): 103–15; Kries, Douglas, “Thomas Aquinas and the Politics of Moses,” Review of Politics 52 (1990): 98102CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

87 SLE 1.9.107–17.

88 Henry Veatch, “Natural Law: Dead or Alive?,” in Swimming against the Current in Contemporary Philosophy (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press), 265.

89 Farrell, Walter and Adler, Mortimer, “The Theory of Democracy, Part III: The End of the State―Happiness,” The Thomist 4 (1942): 127–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar, cited in Staley, “Happiness,” 223.