No CrossRef data available.
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 19 April 2018
One of the many contributions of Postmodern Platos is that it raises an old question in the postmodern age: what is the value of philosophy? This essay finds and assesses three distinct arguments for the philosophical life in Zuckert's book, which she associates with Aristotle, Nietzsche, and Strauss. Philosophy, according to all three arguments, represents the highest life for human beings because it realizes our highest capacity, and it secures for our otherwise finite existence a measure of permanence. The arguments diverge on the question of the order and goodness of nature. The case for philosophy has relevance in our postmodern age, as we are driven to ask the question of the best life yet are unequipped to answer it.
1 Zuckert, Catherine H., Postmodern Platos (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996)Google Scholar. Parenthetical references in text are to this work unless otherwise indicated.
2 Hadot, Pierre, Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to Foucault, ed. Davidson, Arnold I. (Oxford: Wiley, 1995)Google Scholar.
3 An exception in the case of Nietzsche has been the work of Lampert, Laurence (Nietzsche's Teaching: An Interpretation of “Thus Spoke Zarathustra” [New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1986]Google Scholar and Leo Strauss and Nietzsche [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996]Google Scholar). On Heidegger and Strauss, see Velkley, Richard L., Heidegger, Strauss, and the Premises of Philosophy: On Original Forgetting (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011)Google Scholar.
4 For further discussion of Aristotle's view of the value of the philosophical life, see Inglis, Kristen, “Philosophical Virtue: In Defense of the Grand End” in The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's “Nicomachean Ethics,” ed. Polansky, Ronald (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014), 263–87Google Scholar; Griswold, Charles L., “Happiness, Tranquillity, and Philosophy,” Critical Review 10, no. 1 (1996): 1–32, doi:10.1080/08913819608443407CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Burger, Ronna, Aristotle's Dialogue with Socrates: On the “Nicomachean Ethics” (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2009), chap. 7Google Scholar; and Collins and Bartlett's commentary on Book X in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Bartlett, Robert C. and Collins, Susan D. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2012)Google Scholar.
5 Cf. Zuckert, Catherine H., “Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Political Life,” Interpretation 11, no. 2 (1983): 185–206Google Scholar, for a discussion of Aristotle on the limits of the practical life.
6 Nietzsche, Friedrich, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans. Kaufmann, Walter (New York: Penguin Books, 1978), 17–18Google Scholar; Heidegger, Martin, The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, trans. Lovitt, William (New York: HarperCollins, 1982), 17Google Scholar.
7 Nietzsche, Friedrich, Untimely Meditations, ed. Breazeale, Daniel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 112Google Scholar.
8 Nietzsche, Friedrich, The Birth of Tragedy and Other Writings, ed. Geuss, Raymond and Speirs, Ronald (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 50Google Scholar.
9 Ibid., 87.
10 Ibid., 109–10; Untimely Meditations, 62–63.
11 Nietzsche, Birth of Tragedy, 74.
12 Nietzsche, Friedrich, The Gay Science, with a Prelude in German Rhymes and an Appendix of Songs, ed. Williams, Bernard (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 120Google Scholar.
13 Nietzsche, Friedrich, The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, Twilight of the Idols, and Other Writings, ed. Ridley, Aaron and Norman, Judith (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 171Google Scholar.
14 Nietzsche, Friedrich, Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks, trans. Cowan, Marianne (Washington, DC: Regnery, 2012), 43Google Scholar; Nietzsche, , Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future, trans. Norman, Judith (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 106Google Scholar.
15 See Church, Jeffrey, Nietzsche's Culture of Humanity: Beyond Aristocracy and Democracy in the Early Period (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015)CrossRefGoogle Scholar for a fuller defense of this interpretation. Nietzsche scholarship has recently recognized the importance of freedom in Nietzsche. See, for example, Gemes, Ken and May, Simon, Nietzsche on Freedom and Autonomy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
16 Nietzsche, Gay Science, 189.
17 Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, 9.
18 Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, 68–69.
19 Zuckert, Michael P. and Zuckert, Catherine H., Leo Strauss and the Problem of Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2014)Google Scholar; Melzer, Arthur M., “Esotericism and the Critique of Historicism,” American Political Science Review 100, no. 2 (2006): 279–95, doi:10.1017/S0003055406062162Google Scholar.
20 Strauss, Leo, Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 24Google Scholar.
21 Strauss, Leo, An Introduction to Political Philosophy: Ten Essays, ed. Gildin, Hilail (Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 1989), 4–5Google Scholar.
22 Strauss, Leo, The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism, ed. Pangle, Thomas L. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989), 142Google Scholar.
23 Untimely Meditations, 159.
24 Locke, John, An Essay concerning Human Understanding, ed. Nidditch, Peter H. (Oxford: Clarendon, 1975), 268–69Google Scholar.
25 Hobbes, Leviathan, chap. 8.
26 Machiavelli, The Prince, chap. 6; Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract, II.6.
27 Kant, Immanuel, Kant: Political Writings, ed. Reiss, H. S. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 41–42Google Scholar.
28 See, e.g., Zuckert, Catherine H. and Zuckert, Michael P., The Truth about Leo Strauss: Political Philosophy and American Democracy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2008)Google Scholar, chap. 2.