Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-w7rtg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-20T05:53:26.675Z Has data issue: true hasContentIssue false

ANSELM’S ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT AND GRADES OF BEING

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 September 2024

Abstract

Anselm described god as “something than which nothing greater can be thought” [1, p. 93], and Descartes viewed him as “a supreme being” [7, p. 122]. I first capture those characterizations formally in a simple language for monadic predicate logic. Next, I construct a model class inspired by Stoic and medieval doctrines of grades of being [8, 20]. Third, I prove the models sufficient for recovering, as internal mathematics, the famous ontological argument of Anselm, and show that argument to be, on this formalization, valid. Fourth, I extend the models to incorporate a modality fit for proving that any item than which necessarily no greater can be thought is also necessarily real. Lastly, with the present approach, I blunt the sharp edges of notable objections to ontological arguments by Gaunilo and by Grant. A trigger warning: every page of this writing flouts the old saw “Existence is not a predicate” and flagrantly.

MSC classification

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Deceased

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Anselm, (1974). Anselm of Canterbury. Volume One. Monologion, Proslogion, Debate with Gaunilo, and a Meditation on Human Redemption . Hopkins, J., & Richardson, H. W., editors (translators). New York: Edwin Mellen Press.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1972). The Ontological Argument . London: The Macmillan Press, Ltd. Google Scholar
Bonaventure, (1882). Quaestio disputata de mysterio Trinitatis . In Berdardini, R. P., editors. Opera Omnia , Vol. 5. Rome: Ad Claras Aquas (Quaracchi). 1.1 ad 6.Google Scholar
Church, A. (1953). Non-normal truth-tables for the propositional calculus. Boletin de la Sociedad Matemática Mexicana, 10(1–2), 4142.Google Scholar
Cohen, P. (1963). The independence of the continuum hypothesis I. Proceedings of the National Academy of the Sciences of the U.S.A., 50, 11431148.Google Scholar
Cohen, P. (1964). The independence of the continuum hypothesis II. Proceedings of the National Academy of the Sciences of the U.S.A., 51, 105110.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1960). Discourse on Method and Meditations . Lafleur, L. J. (translator). Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Educational Publishing, Inc.Google Scholar
Gelinas, L. (2006). The Stoic argument ex gradibus entium. Phronesis , 51(1), 4973.Google Scholar
Grant, C. K. (1957). An ontological disproof of the devil. Analysis , 17(3), 7172.Google Scholar
Hughes, G. E., & Cresswell, M. J. (1968). An Introduction to Modal Logic . London: Methuen and Co Ltd. Google Scholar
Johnson, N. W. (1966). Convex polyhedra with regular faces. Canadian Journal of Mathematics, 18, 169200.Google Scholar
Kretzmann, N. (2004). The Metaphysics of Theism: Aquinas’s Natural Theology in Summa Contra Gentiles I. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kuratowski, C. (1922). Sur l’opération $\overline{\mathrm{A}}$ de l’analysis situs . Fundamenta Mathematicae , 3, 182199.Google Scholar
Oppy, G. (1995). Ontological Arguments and Belief in God . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rasiowa, H., & Sikorski, R. (1963). The Mathematics of Metamathematics. Warsaw: Państwowe Wydawn. Naukowe.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1959). Aristotle: A Complete Exposition of his Works and Thought (second edition). Cleveland: The World Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Scott, D. S. (1977). Foreword . In Bell, J. L., editor. Boolean-Valued Models and Independence Proofs in Set Theory . Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. xixviii.Google Scholar
Scott, D. S. (1979). Identity and existence in intuitionistic logic . In Fourman, M. P. et al., editors. Applications of Sheaves. Proceedings, Durham 1977. Lecture Notes in Mathematics, 753. Berlin: Springer-Verlag, pp. 660696.Google Scholar
Scott, D. S., & Solovay, R. (1967). Boolean-valued models for set theory. Notes for the 1967 American Mathematical Society Symposium on Axiomatic Set Theory.Google Scholar
Spade, P. V. (1999). Degrees of being, degrees of goodness: Aquinas on levels of reality. In MacDonald, S., & Stump, E., editors. Aquinas’s Moral Theory. Essays in Honor of Norman Kretzmann. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 254275.Google Scholar
Vopěnka, P. (1965). The limits of sheaves and applications on constructions of models. Bulletin L’Académie Polonaise des Science, Série des Sciences Mathématiques, Astronomiques et Physiques, 13, 189192.Google Scholar