Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T22:06:41.204Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

CONNEXIVE IMPLICATIONS IN SUBSTRUCTURAL LOGICS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 July 2023

DAVIDE FAZIO*
Affiliation:
DIPARTIMENTO DI SCIENZE DELLA COMUNICAZIONE UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DI TERAMO CAMPUS “AURELIO SALICETI,” VIA R. BALZARINI 1, 64100 TERAMO (TE), ITALY
GAVIN ST. JOHN
Affiliation:
DIPARTIMENTO DI MATEMATICA UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DI SALERNO VIA GIOVANNI PAOLO II, 132, 84084 FISCIANO (SA), ITALY E-mail: gavinstjohn@gmail.com
*
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper is devoted to the investigation of term-definable connexive implications in substructural logics with exchange and, on the semantical perspective, in sub-varieties of commutative residuated lattices (FL${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$-algebras). In particular, we inquire into sufficient and necessary conditions under which generalizations of the connexive implication-like operation defined in [6] for Heyting algebras still satisfy connexive theses. It will turn out that, in most cases, connexive principles are equivalent to the equational Glivenko property with respect to Boolean algebras. Furthermore, we provide some philosophical upshots like, e.g., a discussion on the relevance of the above operation in relationship with G. Polya’s logic of plausible inference, and some characterization results on weak and strong connexivity.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

The basic ideas of connexive logic can be traced back to Aristotle’s Prior Analytics and to Boethius’ De hypotheticis syllogismis (see [Reference McCall, Gabbay, Pelletier and Woods19]). Connexive logic developed as an underground stream along the whole history of logic until the sixties of the last century. Since then, it has become a well-established subject of investigation in non-classical logic. Connexive principles reflect a connection, or compatibility, between the antecedent and consequent of sound conditionals. Specifically, they establish that a conditional statement “if A, then B” is sound provided that the negation of B is incompatible with A. Such a connection can be expressed in a language containing a unary (negation) connective $\neg $ and a binary (implication) connective ${\to }$ by means of axioms in Table 1.

Table 1 Basic connexive laws

A connexive logic is nothing but a logic having the above formulas as theorems with respect to a negation $\neg $ and a non-symmetric implication ${\to } $ . The latter requirement, which we call the principle of non-symmetry, is essential, since ${\to }$ must be understood as a genuine implication rather than as an equivalence. Apparently, the above formulas are falsified in classical logic whenever implications with false antecedents are considered. Therefore, classical logic is not connexive with respect to material implication and negation. On the other hand, while material biconditional does satisfy the theses in Table 1, it is obviously symmetric.

Connexive theses have been motivated by different considerations depending on the specific meaning given to implication. One motivation comes from relevance logic and the idea that semantic consequence is a content relationship (see, e.g., [Reference Routley27]). [Reference Cantwell5] argues that connexive systems can formalize indicative natural language conditionals. Some authors (e.g., [Reference Kapsner and Omori15]) suggest that a connexive implication is suitable for modelling counterfactual conditionals (see also [Reference Wansing and Unterhuber33]). Moreover, [Reference McCall, Anderson and Belnap18] proposes an interpretation of connexive conditionals in terms of physical or “causal” implications. Also, the results of empirical research on the interpretation of negated conditionals (see [Reference McCall, Gabbay, Pelletier and Woods19, Reference Pfeifer21, Reference Pfeifer and Tulkki22, Reference Wansing and Zalta29]) suggest that speakers having no previous knowledge of formal logic are inclined to consider connexive conditionals as the sound ones. Recently, A. Kapsner has argued that the intuitive appeal of connexive principles is rooted, at least in the case of indicative conditionals, in the use of implication in concrete argumentation. In particular, it seems to depend on the assumption that a conditional statement of the form “if A, then B” is sound provided that A is “epistemically possible” for the speaker asserting it. Quoting Kapsner [Reference Kapsner14]:

There is a presupposition for indicatives (which I called IP) that says that the antecedent needs to be epistemically possible for the speaker: If I say “If today is Monday, Susy will come home tomorrow”, then this is only correct if I don’t know for sure that today is not Monday.

The interested reader is referred to [Reference Wansing and Zalta29] for an exhaustive survey on these topics.

As stated in [Reference Wansing and Omori32, p. 381], “[…] the central concern of connexive logic consists of developing connexive systems that are naturally motivated conceptually or in terms of applications, that admit of a simple and plausible semantics, and that can be equipped with proof systems possessing nice proof-theoretical properties […].” Indeed, the literature on this subject offers a large amount of connexive logical systems “built from scratch” having interesting proof-theoretical features and, in some cases, transparent and elegant semantics. However, less has been said on the possibility of defining connexive implications within well-established sub-logics of classical logic or some expansion thereof. In [Reference Pizzi23], Pizzi shows that a connexive arrow, called consequential implication, can be defined by means of the modal notions of necessity and possibility within ordinary modal logic systems S1–S5, plus the system T. This approach has the advantage of suggesting a well-studied framework like ordinary modal logic as a conceptual and formal basis for connexive semantics (cf. [Reference McCall, Gabbay, Pelletier and Woods19]). In the same spirit, Gherardi and Orlandelli introduce super-strict implications [Reference Gherardi and Orlandelli11]. Very recently, Fazio, Ledda, and Paoli [Reference Fazio, Ledda and Paoli6] have investigated Connexive Heyting Logic (CHL) which is algebraizable in the sense of Blok and Pigozzi (see, e.g., [Reference Blok and Pigozzi2, Reference Font8]) with respect to a subvariety of H. P. Sankappanavar’s semi-Heyting algebras satisfying an equational rendering of Aristotle’s and Boethius’ theses, i.e., Connexive Heyting algebras (CHAs). It turns out that CHAs are term-equivalent to Heyting algebras, and so CHL is deductively equivalent to Intuitionistic Logic. More precisely, a CHA ${\mathbf A}$ is a semi-Heyting algebra $(A,\land ,\lor ,{\Rightarrow },0,1)$ satisfying, among other identities, the following:

$$ \begin{align*} 1\approx (x{\Rightarrow} y){\Rightarrow}\neg(x{\Rightarrow}\neg y), &&1\approx (x{\Rightarrow} \neg y){\Rightarrow}\neg(x{\Rightarrow} y),\\ 1\approx\neg(x{\Rightarrow}\neg x), &&1\approx\neg(\neg x{\Rightarrow} x), \end{align*} $$

where . Remarkably enough, ${\Rightarrow }$ is, in general, not symmetric. Setting , it follows by general results on semi-Heyting algebras that $\mathbb {H}({\mathbf A})=(A,\land ,\lor ,{\to },0,1)$ is a Heyting algebra. Conversely, given a Heyting algebra ${\mathbf A}$ , upon setting

(1.1)

(where $\neg x$ is defined as expected), one has that $\mathbb {C}({\mathbf A})=(A,\land ,\lor ,{\Rightarrow },0,1)$ is a CHA. Furthermore, $\mathbb {C}$ and $\mathbb {H}$ are mutually inverse mappings.

Due to the above features, CHL, which is the $1$ -assertional logic of CHAs, can be entitled as a full-fledged connexive logic. Moreover, it enjoys properties which are indeed rare within connexive logics literature. For example, CHL is strongly connexive in the sense of [Reference Kapsner13]. Furthermore, it allows one to investigate connexivity with well-known mathematical tools and with the conceptual “arsenal” provided by Intuitionistic Logic (think, e.g., to the BHK semantics).

A somewhat suggestive interpretation of the above results might be the following. For any Heyting algebra ${\mathbf A}$ , the operation $\neg \neg \colon A\to A$ is a nucleus over the $\ell $ -monoid $(A,\land ,\lor ,\cdot ,1)$ , where . Therefore, $\neg \neg $ can be regarded as a modal operator (cf., e.g., [Reference Young34]). If we read $\neg \neg x$ either as “x is not absolutely false,” or as “x is plausible,” then a well-behaving connexive arrow ${\Rightarrow }$ can be obtained from intuitionistic implication $\rightarrow $ by strengthening the latter in such a way that no true (or at least plausible) statement can be implied by an a priori false/implausible one.Footnote 1 Therefore, connexive Heyting implication might be seen as encoding, at a semantic level, a weak version of Kapsner’s presupposition (IP) recalled above. In fact, if a speaker considers the antecedent of “A implies B” epistemically possible, then, a fortiori, she does not consider it absolutely false.

Given this observation, we frame this technique in a broader class of non-classical logics, Substructural Logics [Reference Paoli20], which are understood as the external logics induced by axiomatic extensions of the Full Lambek Calculus $\mathtt {FL}$ , a sequent system introduced to model natural language. In this manuscript we confine ourselves to the commutative setting, namely to $\mathtt {FL}_{\mathtt {e}}$ , which is obtained from $\mathtt {FL}$ by adding the exchange structural rule $(\mathtt {e})$ . Its extensions include many of the most well-studied non-classical logics: intuitionistic logic, relevance logic, linear logic, many-valued logics, with classical logic as a limit case. They find applications to areas as diverse as linguistics, philosophy, and theoretical computer science. Moreover, extensions of $\mathtt {FL}_{\mathtt {e}}$ turn out to be particularly appealing as they are algebraizable, in the sense of Blok and Pigozzi, w.r.t. (pointed) commutative residuated lattices. A thorough treatment of substructural logics and residuated lattices can be found in [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono9].

In this paper, we work from the semantical perspective and investigate the class of pointed commutative residuated lattices (FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras) for which an implication-type connective ${\Rightarrow }$ satisfying equational renderings of Boethius’ and Aristotle’s theses can be term-defined. Specifically, we define connectives similar to ${\Rightarrow }$ in (1.1) by considering the following candidates:

where . This choice is motivated not only by the intrinsic interest for investigating mathematical properties of Heyting algebras underlying connexive principles, but also from more “philosophical” considerations. In fact, we will argue that the above interpretation of ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ can be deepened in the broader framework of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras and put into relationship with G. Polya’s theory of plausible inferences in mathematics developed in [Reference Polya26]. Indeed, we will see that, under a reasonable notion of “being more credible/plausible/likely to be true,” ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ might formalize the kinds of conditionals involving a conjecture and one of its consequences as the antecedent and consequent, respectively. More precisely, ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ is the semantical counterpart of the weakest term-definable (in the external logic of ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ ) implication-like connective $\leadsto $ satisfying axiomatic renderings of modus ponens and Polya’s fundamental inductive pattern: from the truth of “A implies B” and B, one deduces that “A is more credible.”

This work aims at showing that, for an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra ${\mathbf A}$ , a condition ensuring that ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ defined over ${\mathbf A}$ satisfy Aristotle’s and Boethius’ Theses is that ${\mathbf A}$ has the equational Glivenko property w.r.t. Boolean algebras (see below and, e.g., [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono9]). Moreover, this condition becomes necessary when one deals with ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ . As a consequence, we obtain a novel characterization of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras enjoying the equational Glivenko property relative to BA’s by establishing a new link between connexivity and concepts of well-known mathematical depth.

Moreover, we turn our attention to integral FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras. In this case we obtain somewhat surprising and strong results. Indeed, we consider the binary operations ${\Rightarrow }$ in the (pointwise ordered) interval $[{\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{\delta },{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }]$ (where $\delta $ is an increasing map replaying the role of $\neg \neg $ ) over an integral FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra ${\mathbf A}$ , and we show that they satisfy connexive axioms if and only if at least one of them does and $\delta =\neg \neg $ . In this case any of the ${\Rightarrow }$ ’s is symmetric if and only if ${\mathbf A}$ is a Boolean algebra. Note that the latter result still holds, at least for ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ , if integrality is dropped. Therefore, we conclude that, apart from Boolean algebras themselves, FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras with the equational Glivenko property w.r.t. BA’s (and their $1$ -assertional logics, see below) can be regarded as suitable environments in which connexive implications of a certain type can be defined.

Finally, we focus on the concepts of strong and weak (see below and, e.g., [Reference Wansing and Unterhuber33]) connexivity. In fact, on the one hand we will show that, in some cases, weak connexivity and connexivity can be regarded as one and the same thing. On the other, it will turn out that, although strong connexivity has often been associated to contra-classical (cf. [Reference Humberstone12]) theses (see, e.g., the notion of superconnexivity in [Reference Kapsner13]), in the framework of extensions of $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}$ for which ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ are connexive, it is nevertheless equivalent to a rather “classical” inference schema: ex falso quodlibet. Therefore, also in view of characterization theorems outlined above, this work yields an overall picture which is somewhat surprising: although connexive theses (and weak/strong connexivity) make connexive logics incomparable with classical logic, in the context we deal with, they mirror some distinguishing traits of intuitionistic logic.

The results discussed above suggest that a systematic (programmatic) investigation of connexive implication connectives which are term-definable within well-known systems of non-classical logic might have interesting consequences. On the one hand, it would provide (eventually strongly) connexive logics with transparent semantics and implications with intuitive meanings. Therefore, such investigations would perhaps shed some light on the “semantic source” of connexive principles. On the other, this line of research would establish relationships between connexive systems and logics which, like substructural logics, have relevant applications in logico-philosophical investigations as well as in mathematics, computer science, and Artificial Intelligence. This work aims at being a small step in that direction.

Let us summarize the discourse of the paper. In Section 2 we dispatch the basic notions needed for the development of our arguments, and we provide some preliminary results. Section 3 is devoted to alternative characterizations of those FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras in which ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ , ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ , and (in the integral case) any binary operation ${\Rightarrow }$ “in the between” satisfy connexive theses. We prove that, for ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ (and under a slightly stronger assumption ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ ), the largest class of algebras of this sort coincides with the variety of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras with the equational Glivenko property w.r.t. Boolean algebras. In Section 4, building on results obtained in previous sections, we provide some philosophical upshots like, e.g., a discussion on the relevance of ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ , a characterization of substructural logics for which ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ ( ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ ) is strongly connexive, and some remarks on the relationship between weak connexivity and connexivity. We conclude in Section 5.

2 Basic notions and preliminary results

In this section we provide the necessary notions for the contents of this manuscript. We will assume the reader has a working understanding in basic concepts of universal algebra, referring them to [Reference Burris and Sankappanavar3] for further edification.

2.1 Residuated structures

Here we recall the definitions and properties of residuated lattices and FL-algebras, but only define their commutative versions as their full generality is not needed for the purpose of this work. For a thorough treatment of these structures and their connection to substructural logics, we refer the reader to [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono9].

A commutative residuated lattice (CRL) is an algebra $\mathbf {R} = \langle R, \wedge ,\vee , \cdot , \to ,1 \rangle $ such that $\langle R, \wedge ,\vee \rangle $ is a lattice, $\langle R, \cdot ,1\rangle $ is a commutative monoid, and $\mathbf {R}$ satisfies the law of residuation, i.e., for all $x,y,z\in R$ ,

(residuation) $$ \begin{align} x\cdot y \leq z \iff x\leq y\to z, \end{align} $$

where $\leq $ is the induced lattice order; i.e., $x\leq y$ iff $x\wedge y = x$ . The law of residuation can be written equationally, and therefore the class of commutative residuated lattices form a variety denoted by $\mathsf {CRL}$ . We will often abbreviate $\cdot $ by concatenation, i.e., , with the convention that concatenation binds tighter than the remaining connectives in the signature. We also use a bi-implication abbreviation . A residuated lattice is called integral if the monoid unit is the greatest element, i.e., it satisfies the identity ( $\mathsf {i}$ ): $x \wedge 1 \approx x$ . We note that, if there is a greatest element $\top $ (not necessarily $1$ ), then $x\leq y$ implies $x{\to } y \approx \top $ . If there is a least element $\bot $ , then there must be a greatest element, namely $\bot {\to }\bot $ , and $\bot $ is absorbing, i.e., $\bot \cdot x \approx \bot $ .

Below we recall some basic properties of CRLs, which we will mostly utilize without reference throughout this article.

Proposition 2.1. The following identities hold in $\mathsf {CRL}$ :

  1. 1. $x(y \vee z) \approx xy \vee xz$ .

  2. 2. $x\to (y\wedge z) \approx (x\to y) \wedge (x\to z)$ .

  3. 3. $(x \vee y)\to z \approx (x\to z) \wedge (y\to z)$ .

  4. 4. $1\to x \approx x$ .

  5. 5. $x\to (y\to z) \approx yx\to z$ .

Consequently, $\cdot $ is order-preserving in both coordinates, while ${\to }$ is order-preserving (reversing) in its right (left) coordinate.

An FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra is simply a $0$ -pointed CRL, i.e., a CRL whose signature is expanded by a constant $0$ , and the variety of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras is denoted by ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ . An FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra is $0$ -bounded if $0$ is the least element, i.e., it satisfies ( $\mathsf {o}$ ): $0\wedge x \approx 0$ . By ( $\mathsf {w}$ ) we denote weakening, defined via $(\mathsf {w}) = (\mathsf {i}) + (\mathsf {o})$ . We denote the variety of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras satisfying integrality (weakening) by $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}$ ( $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}$ ).

Given that $0$ is a constant in the signature of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras, we define the unary operation , and use the convention that $\neg $ binds tighter than any connective. An FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra is said to be involutive if it satisfies $x\approx \neg \neg x$ . An FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra is called pseudo-complemented if it satisfies the identity

(pc) $$ \begin{align} x\wedge \neg x\leq 0. \end{align} $$

We say an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra is strongly pseudo-complemented if the following identity holds:

(spc) $$ \begin{align} \neg x \wedge \neg(x{\to} y) \leq 0. \end{align} $$

Clearly (spc) entails (pc) as an instance; however, the converse need not hold as is witnessed by Figure 1.

Figure 1 The Hasse diagram of a pseudo-complemented integral FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra which does not satisfy (spc) since $\neg 0 \wedge \neg (0{\to } \bot ) = \neg 0 \wedge \neg \bot =1 \wedge 1 = 1\neq 0$ .

Remark 2.2. The converse does hold for $0$ -bounded FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras, as being $0$ -bounded entails $\neg x\leq x\to y$ , and hence $\neg x \wedge \neg (x{\to } y)\leq \neg x\wedge \neg \neg x \leq 0$ .

It is easy to see that, for FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras, the operation $\neg $ is order-reversing and satisfies $\neg x\approx \neg \neg \neg x$ . Additionally, the map $x\mapsto \neg \neg x$ is a nucleus; i.e., a map $\gamma \colon G\to G$ on a partially-ordered groupoid that is a closure operator [namely, a map $\gamma $ that is increasing: $x\leq \gamma (x)$ ; monotone: $x\leq y$ implies $\gamma (x)\leq \gamma (y)$ ; and idempotent: $\gamma \circ \gamma = \gamma $ ] which further satisfies the identity $\gamma (x)\cdot \gamma (y)\leq \gamma (xy)$ [or equivalently, $\gamma (\gamma (x)\cdot \gamma (y))\approx \gamma (xy)$ ]. It is well known that, for any FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra ${\mathbf A}$ , if $\gamma \colon A\to A$ is a nucleus then is also an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra, where and [e.g., see Chapter 3.4.11 in [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono9]].

For simplicity, we use the notation henceforth, and summarize the basic properties of ${\diamond }$ , all of which hold for any nucleus, in the proposition below, which we may often utilize without reference.

Proposition 2.3. The following (quasi-) identities hold in ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ :

  1. 1. $x\leq {\diamond } x$ .

  2. 2. $x\leq y \implies {\diamond } x \leq {\diamond } y$ .

  3. 3. ${\diamond }{{\diamond } x} \approx {\diamond }{x}$ .

  4. 4. ${\diamond } x \cdot {\diamond } y \leq {\diamond }(xy)$ .

  5. 5. ${\diamond } x \wedge {\diamond } y \approx {\diamond }({\diamond } x \wedge {\diamond } y)$ .

  6. 6. ${\diamond } x \to {\diamond } y \approx x\to {\diamond } y \approx {\diamond }(x\to {\diamond } y) $ .

Consequently, for any ${\mathbf A}\in {\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ , is an involutive FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra.

The following example will be a useful counter-model throughout this article.

Example 2.4. The set of integers $\mathbb {Z}$ forms a (totally-ordered) commutative residuated lattice where ; , ; $x{\to }_{\mathbb {Z}} y: = y - x$ ; and . For fixed $n\in \mathbb {Z}$ , by $\mathbb {Z}(n)$ we denote the FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra as an expansion of $\mathbb {Z}$ by taking . In $\mathbb {Z}(n)$ , it is clear that for all $x\in \mathbb {Z}$ , $\neg x = n-x$ and $\neg \neg x = x$ , so $\mathbb {Z}(n)$ is involutive, i.e., ${\diamond } \mathbb {Z}(n)=\mathbb {Z}(n)$ .

2.2 Algebraization for substructural logics

A logic $\mathbf {L}$ over an algebraic language $\mathcal {L}$ is a structural consequence relation (i.e., closed under substitutions and is reflexive, transitive, and monotone) ${\vdash }\subseteq \wp (\textit {Fm}_{\mathcal {L}})\times \textit {Fm}_{\mathcal {L}}$ . The interested reader is referred to [Reference Font8] for details.

The name “FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ ” comes from the fact that FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras are the (unique) equivalent algebraic semantics of the external logic $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}$ induced by the Full Lambek Calculus with exchange $\mathtt {FL}_{\mathtt {e}}$ . Precisely, we have that, for any $\Phi \cup \psi \subseteq \textit {Fm}_{\mathcal {L}}$ of formulas over the language $\mathcal {L}=\{\wedge ,\vee ,\cdot ,{\to },0,1 \}$ ,

$$\begin{align*}\Phi\vdash_{\mathbf{FL}_{\mathbf{e}}}\psi\quad\text{iff}\quad\{\operatorname{\mathrm{\blacktriangleright}}\varphi:\varphi\in\Phi\}\vdash_{\mathtt{FL}_{\mathtt{e}}}\operatorname{\mathrm{\blacktriangleright}}\psi.\end{align*}$$

${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ is the equivalent algebraic semantics of $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}$ means that there exists a pair of “mutually inverse” mappings (called transformers) $\tau : \textit {Fm}_{\mathcal {L}}\to \wp (\textit {Fm}_{\mathcal {L}}^{2})$ from formulas to sets of equations, and $\rho : \textit {Fm}_{\mathcal {L}}^{2}\to \wp ( \textit {Fm}_{\mathcal {L}})$ from equations to sets of formulas such that, for any $\Phi \cup \{\psi\} \subseteq \textit {Fm}_{\mathcal {L}}$ :

  • $\Phi \vdash _{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}}\psi $ if and only if $\tau (\Phi )\models _{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}\tau (\psi )$ ,

  • ,

or, equivalently, for any set of equations $\{\epsilon _{i}\approx \delta _{i}:i\in I\}\cup \{\epsilon \approx \delta \}\subseteq Fm^{2}_{\mathcal {L}}$ :

  • $\{\epsilon _{i}\approx \delta _{i}:i\in I\}\models _{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}\epsilon \approx \delta $ iff $\{\rho (\epsilon _{i}\approx \delta _{i}):i\in I\}\vdash _{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}}\rho (\epsilon \approx \delta )$ ,

  • $x\dashv \vdash _{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}}\rho (\tau (x))$ .

It can be seen that, in our framework, a suitable pair of transformers is given by $\tau (\varphi ):=\{1\leq \varphi \}$ , while $\rho (\epsilon \approx \delta ):=\{(x\to y)\land (y\to x)\}$ . Cf. [Reference Galatos and Ono10] for details. For this reason, $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}$ is often referred to as the $1$ -assertional logic of ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ . Now, the lattice of axiomatic extensions of $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}$ , in this paper called substructural logics,Footnote 2 is dually isomorphic to the lattice of subvarieties of ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ . Indeed, for every class $\mathsf {K}$ of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras and for every set $\Phi \subseteq {\textit {Fm}}_{\mathcal {L}}$ of formulas over $\mathcal {L}$ , let $\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {K}):= \{\phi \in {\textit {Fm}}_{\mathcal {L}}: \mathsf {K}\ \models\ 1\leq \phi \}$ and $\mathsf {V}(\Phi )$ the subvariety of ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ axiomatized by $\{ 1\leq \phi :\phi \in \Phi \}$ , we state the well-known algebraization theorem (e.g., Theorem 2.29 in [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono9]):

Theorem 2.5 (The Algebraization Theorem)

The following hold:

  1. 1. For every substructural logic $\mathbf {L}$ , $\mathbf {L}$ is algebraizable with $\mathsf {V}(\mathbf {L})$ as its equivalent algebraic semantics. In particular, for any $\Phi \cup \{ \gamma \}\subseteq {\textit {Fm}}_{\mathcal {L}}$ :

    $$\begin{align*}\Phi \vdash_{\mathbf{L}} \gamma\quad\text{iff}\quad\{1\leq \varphi: \varphi\in \Phi \} \models_{\mathsf{V}(\mathbf{L})} 1\leq \gamma.\end{align*}$$
  2. 2. For any subvariety $\mathsf {V}\subseteq {\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ , $\mathsf {V}$ is the equivalent algebraic semantics of the logic $\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {V})$ . Specifically, for any $E\cup \{s\approx t\}\subseteq \wp ({{\textit {Fm}}_{\mathcal {L}}}^{2})$ , one has

    $$\begin{align*}E\models_{\mathsf{V}} s\approx t\quad\text{iff}\quad\{ u\to v, v\to u : (u\approx v)\in E\} \vdash_{\mathbf{L}(\mathsf{V})} (s{\to} t) \wedge (t{\to} s).\end{align*}$$

2.3 Boolean algebras and their Glivenko varieties

ItFootnote 3 is well known that Boolean algebras are term-equivalent to FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras satisfying $x\cdot y \approx x\wedge y$ and $x {\to } y \approx \neg x \vee y$ (e.g., Lemma 8.32 in [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono9]). By $\mathsf {BA}$ we will denote the variety of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras which are term-equivalent to Boolean algebras. It is well known that Boolean algebras are the equivalent algebraic semantics of classical logic $\mathbf {CPL}$ , i.e., $\mathsf {BA}=\mathsf {V}(\mathbf {CPL})$ and $\mathbf {CPL}=\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {BA})$ . The following proposition is likely folklore, but we provide its proof as it will be useful later.

Proposition 2.6. Let ${\mathbf A}$ be an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra. Then ${\mathbf A}$ is (term-equivalent to) a Boolean algebra iff ${\mathbf A}$ is integral, involutive, and pseudo-complemented.

Proof. The forward direction is obvious. For the reverse direction, let $x,y\in L$ . First, by using the properties of integrality, commutativity, and pseudo-complemented, we compute $\neg (xy)\cdot (x\wedge y) \leq \neg (xy)x \wedge y = (x{\to } \neg y)x \wedge y \leq \neg y \wedge y \leq 0;$ hence $x\wedge y \leq \neg \neg (xy) = xy$ by residuation and involutivity. Since $xy\leq x\wedge y $ by integrality, we obtain $x\cdot y = x\wedge y$ . Hence, using this fact and involutivity, we obtain $x{\to } y = x{\to } \neg \neg y = \neg (x\cdot \neg y) =\neg (x\wedge \neg y) = \neg \neg (\neg x \vee \neg \neg y)=\neg x\vee y. $

It is well known that classical propositional logic $\mathbf {CPL}$ is translatable into intuitionistic propositional logic $\mathbf {IPL}$ ; namely, $\vdash _{\mathbf {CPL}} \varphi $ iff $\vdash _{\mathbf {IPL}} \neg \neg \varphi $ , for any formula $\varphi $ . This concept, known as the Glivenko property, has been studied for substructural logics in general (see [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono9, Reference Galatos and Ono10]), as the property is reflected via their algebraic semantics via the algebraization theorem. Indeed, for substructural logics $\mathbf {L}$ and $\mathbf {K}$ , we say the Glivenko property holds for $\mathbf {K}$ relative to $\mathbf {L}$ if for any formula $\varphi $ , $\vdash _{\mathbf {L}} \varphi $ iff $\vdash _{\mathbf {K}}\neg \neg \varphi $ . Indeed, by Theorem 2.5, this is equivalently stated: for any FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -term t, $\mathsf {V}(\mathbf {L})\models 1\leq t$ iff $\mathsf {V}(\mathbf {K})\models 1\leq \neg \neg t$ .

Proposition 2.7 (See [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono9, Reference Galatos and Ono10])

For subvarieties $\mathsf {V},\mathsf {W}\subseteq {\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ and FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -terms $s,t$ , the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. $\mathsf {V}\ \models\ 1\leq t$ iff $\mathsf {W}\ \models\ 1\leq \neg \neg t$ .

  2. 2. $\mathsf {V}\ \models\ s\leq t$ iff $\mathsf {W}\ \models\ \neg t\leq \neg s$ .

  3. 3. $\mathsf {V}\, {\models}\, s\approx t$ iff $\mathsf{W}\, {\models}\, \neg s \approx \neg t$ .

Thus, for varieties $\mathsf {V}$ and $\mathsf {W}$ of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras, we say the equational Glivenko property holds for $\mathsf {W}$ relative to $\mathsf {V}$ iff

(2.1) $$ \begin{align} \mathsf{V}\ \models\ s\approx t \iff \mathsf{W}\ \models\ \neg s \approx \neg t \end{align} $$

for any equation $s\approx t$ in the language of ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ . In particular, it follows that the equational Glivenko property holds for the variety of Heyting algebras $\mathsf {HA}$ relative to $\mathsf {BA}$ , as it is well known $\mathsf {HA}=\mathsf {V}(\mathbf {IPL})$ . Note that the algebras in $\mathsf {HA}$ are exactly those FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{ew}}$ -algebras in which $\cdot $ coincides with $\wedge $ .

By $\mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}(\mathsf {V})$ we denote the largest subvariety $\mathsf {W}$ for which the equational Glivenko property holds for $\mathsf {W}$ relative to $\mathsf {V}$ . By $\mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {U}}(\mathsf {V})$ we denote $\mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}(\mathsf {V}) \cap \mathsf {U}$ , where $\mathsf {U}$ is a subvariety of ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ , which we call the Glivenko variety of $\mathsf {U}$ relative to $\mathsf {V}$ . Dually, for a substructural logic $\mathbf {L}$ , $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}}(\mathbf {L})$ denotes the least (w.r.t. set inclusion) substructural logic $\mathbf {K}$ for which the Glivenko property holds relative to $\mathbf {L}$ . If $\mathbf {K}$ is a substructural logic, by $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {K}}(\mathbf {L})$ we denote $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}}(\mathbf {L}) \vee \mathbf {K}$ , i.e., the smallest extension of $\mathbf {K}$ having the Glivenko property w.r.t. $\mathbf {L}$ , which we call the Glivenko logic of $\mathbf {K}$ relative to $\mathbf {L}$ .

Theorem 2.8 (See [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono9, Reference Galatos and Ono10])

  1. 1. $\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ is axiomatized relative to ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ by the following identities:

    1. (a) $\neg (x\cdot y)\approx \neg (x\wedge y)$ ,

    2. (b) $1\leq {\diamond }({\diamond } x{\to } x)$ [or, alternatively, $\neg (x{\to } y) \approx \neg (\neg x \vee y)$ ].

  2. 2. $\mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ is axiomatized relative to $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}$ by the following identities:

    1. (a) $x\wedge \neg x \leq 0$ [or, alternatively, $\neg (x\wedge y)\approx \neg (x\cdot y)$ ],

    2. (b) $1\leq {\diamond }({\diamond } x{\to } x)$ .

Remark 2.9. $\mathsf {BA}\subsetneq \mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}}(\mathsf {BA})\subseteq \mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}}(\mathsf {BA})\subseteq \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ as any Heyting algebra is in $\mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ , but there are Heyting algebras which are not Boolean.

As they will be useful in what follows, we provide further characterizations for the Glivenko varieties of ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ ( $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}$ , and $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}$ ) relative to Boolean algebras.

Lemma 2.10. For an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra ${\mathbf A}$ , the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. ${\mathbf A}\in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ .

  2. 2. ${\mathbf A}$ is pseudo-complemented, satisfies $1\leq {\diamond }({\diamond } x{\to } x)$ , and has ${\diamond } 1$ as its greatest element (i.e., ${\diamond } {\mathbf A}$ is integral).

  3. 3. ${\diamond } {\mathbf A}$ is Boolean and ${\mathbf A}$ satisfies $1\leq {\diamond }({\diamond } x{\to } x)$ .

Proof. (1) implies (2) is obvious. Since ${\diamond } \mathbf{A}$ is involutive by fiat, (2) implies (3) follows by Proposition 2.6. For (3) implies (1), suppose ${\diamond } {\mathbf A}$ is Boolean and ${\mathbf A}$ satisfies $(\star ):1\leq {\diamond }({\diamond } x{\to } x)$ . So ${\diamond } 1$ is the greatest element of ${\mathbf A}$ and the following identities hold in ${\mathbf A}$ :

$$ \begin{align*}{\diamond} (x\cdot y)\approx {\diamond} x\wedge{\diamond} y \quad\mathsf{and}\quad x{\to} {\diamond} y \approx {\diamond}(\neg x \vee y) .\end{align*} $$

By Theorem 2.8, we need only verify that ${\mathbf A}$ satisfies $\neg (x\cdot y)\approx \neg (x\wedge y)$ , or equivalently, ${\diamond }(x\cdot y)\approx {\diamond }(x\wedge y)$ . Towards this, we will first show ${\mathbf A}$ satisfies $(\star \star ):{\diamond }(x{\to } y)\approx x{\to } {\diamond } y$ . Note that we need only verify $x{\to } {\diamond } y \leq {\diamond }(x{\to } y)$ . Let $x,y\in A$ . Since $(x{\to } {\diamond } y)\cdot x \leq {\diamond } y$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*}{\diamond} y {\to} y \leq [(x{\to} {\diamond} y)\cdot x]{\to} y = (x{\to} {\diamond} y) {\to} (x{\to} y), \end{align*} $$

from which it follows that

$$ \begin{align*}\begin{array}{r c l l} {\diamond} 1 &=& {\diamond}[{\diamond} y {\to} y] &\mbox{By } (\star) \\ &\leq & {\diamond}[(x{\to} {\diamond} y) {\to} (x{\to} y)] \\ &\leq & (x{\to} {\diamond} y) {\to} {\diamond}(x{\to} y). \end{array} \end{align*} $$

Hence $x{\to } {\diamond } y \leq {\diamond }(x{\to } y)$ by residuation.

Now, since ${\diamond }(x\wedge y)\leq {\diamond }({\diamond } x \wedge {\diamond } y)={\diamond }(xy)$ , we need only verify ${\diamond }(xy)\leq {\diamond }(x\wedge y)$ , or equivalently, $1\leq {\diamond }(xy)\to {\diamond }(x\wedge y)$ . First, we observe

$$ \begin{align*}\begin{array}{r c l l} {\diamond} 1 {\to} 1 &\leq & (x\vee y){\to} 1 &\mbox{Since } x,y\leq{\diamond} 1\\ &=&[x{\to} 1]\wedge [y{\to} 1]\\ &\leq & [x{\to}(y{\to} y)] \wedge [y{\to} (x{\to} x)]\\ &=& [xy{\to} y]\wedge[xy{\to} x]\\ &=& xy {\to} (x\wedge y). \end{array}\end{align*} $$

Thus we obtain

$$ \begin{align*}\begin{array}[b]{r c l l} 1 &\leq& {\diamond}[{\diamond}1{\to} 1] & \mbox{By } (\star)\\ & \leq &{\diamond}[xy {\to} (x\wedge y)] &\mbox{By the above}\\ & =& xy {\to} {\diamond}(x\wedge y) &\mbox{By } (\star\star)\\ &=& {\diamond}(xy) {\to} {\diamond}(x\wedge y). \end{array}\\[-32pt] \end{align*} $$

Lemma 2.11. For ${\mathbf A}$ an integral FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra, the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. ${\mathbf A} \in \mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ .

  2. 2. ${\mathbf A}$ is strongly pseudo-complemented.

  3. 3. ${\mathbf A} \models \neg (x{\to } y)\approx \neg (\neg x \vee y)$ .

Proof. (1) implies (2) is clear since in $\mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ we have

$$ \begin{align*}\neg x \wedge \neg (x{\to} y) \approx \neg x \wedge \neg(\neg x \vee y)\leq \neg x \wedge \neg\neg x \leq 0.\end{align*} $$

For (2) implies (3), suppose ${\mathbf A}$ is strongly pseudo-complemented and let $x,y\in A$ . Note that $\neg (\neg x \vee y) = {\diamond } x \wedge \neg y$ . On the one hand we have

$$ \begin{align*}\begin{array}{rcll} (x{\to} y)\cdot({\diamond} x \wedge \neg y) &\leq &[(x{\to} y)\cdot{\diamond} x]\wedge \neg y\\ &\leq& [({\diamond} x {\to} {\diamond} y) \cdot {\diamond} x]\wedge \neg y & \mbox{Since } x{\to} y \leq x{\to} {\diamond} y = {\diamond} x{\to} {\diamond} y\\ &\leq & {\diamond} y \wedge \neg y \\ &\leq& 0 &\mbox{By}\ {(\mathrm{spc})}. \end{array} \end{align*} $$

Hence ${\diamond } x \wedge \neg y \leq \neg (x{\to } y)$ by residuation. On the other hand, we have

$$ \begin{align*}\begin{array}{r c l l} (\neg x \vee y)\cdot\neg(x{\to} y) &=& [\neg x \cdot \neg(x{\to} y)] \vee [y \cdot \neg(x{\to} y)]\\ &\leq & [\neg x \wedge \neg(x{\to} y)] \vee [y \cdot \neg y] & \mbox{By integrality}\\ &\leq & [\neg x \wedge \neg(x{\to} y)] \vee 0 \\ &=& 0 &\mbox{By}\ {(\mathrm{spc})}. \end{array} \end{align*} $$

Hence $\neg (x{\to } y)\leq \neg (\neg x \vee y)$ , and we are done.

Lastly, for (3) implies (1), by Theorem 2.8(2), it is enough to show that $\neg (x\wedge y)\approx \neg (x\cdot y)$ holds in ${\mathbf A}$ . Note that the $\leq $ -direction holds by integrality. Let $x,y\in A$ . Note that $x\wedge y \leq {\diamond } x \wedge {\diamond } y = \neg (\neg x \vee \neg y)$ , and $\neg (\neg x \vee \neg y) = \neg (x{\to } \neg y)$ by assumption. Thus,

$$ \begin{align*}(x\wedge y)\cdot \neg(x y) \leq \neg (x{\to} \neg y) \cdot \neg(xy) = \neg (x{\to} \neg y) \cdot (x{\to} \neg y) \leq 0. \end{align*} $$

Hence $\neg (x\cdot y)\leq \neg (x\wedge y)$ by residuation and we are done.

Corollary 2.12. $\mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}}(\mathsf {BA}) = \mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}\ +$ (spc) and $\mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}}(\mathsf {BA}) = \mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}\ + $ (pc).

Proof. The first claim immediately follows from Lemma 2.11, while the second claim follows from the additional observation made in Remark 2.2, namely that ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}} + (\mathsf {o})\models$ (spc) $\mathsf {iff}$ (pc).

3 Connexive FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras

In this section, we lay the groundwork for studying connexivity in substructural logics through the algebraic lens provided by their algebraic semantics, i.e., FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras. We will first begin by considering the case of when the inherent implication ${\to }$ is connexive, and after a short discussion, devote our time to studying the operations ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ (noted in the introduction), and their generalizations. We will show that varieties of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras in which these operations satisfy the (corresponding algebraic notions of) connexive laws are fundamentally linked to Glivenko varieties relative to Boolean algebras—and therefore their corresponding substructural logics having the Glivenko property w.r.t. Classical Logic. In doing so, we generalize a number of results from [Reference Fazio, Ledda and Paoli6], from which much of this investigation was inspired. Furthermore, we provide an entire interval of logics that are bonafide examples of connexive logics, which moreover are equivalently axiomatized by just any one of the connexive theses of Boethius (or even Aristotle in the case of weakening).

3.1 Connexive principles in FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras

In light of the Algebraization Theorem for substructural logics [cf., Theorem 2.5], the algebraic analogue for the connexive laws become evident. Let ${\Rightarrow }$ and ${\sim }$ be some binary and unary connectives, respectively, definable in the language $\{\wedge ,\vee ,\cdot ,{\to },0,1 \}$ . Then a substructural logic $\mathbf {L}$ has a connexive law (i.e., one of Aristotle’s or Boethius’ theses from Table 1) as a theorem, in terms of ${\Rightarrow }$ and ${\sim }$ , if and only if the corresponding identity in Table 2 is modeled by subvariety $\mathsf {V}(\mathbf {L})$ of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras.

Table 2 Order-algebraic connexive laws

Moreover, the connective ${\Rightarrow }$ satisfies the principle of non-symmetry in $\mathbf {L}$ iff $\mathsf {V}(\mathbf {L})$ has a member in which ${\Rightarrow }$ is not a symmetric relation, i.e., there exists ${\mathbf A} \in \mathsf {V}(\mathbf {L})$ such that

(NS) $$ \begin{align} (\exists x,y\in A)[ x {\Rightarrow} y \nleq y {\Rightarrow} x \quad \mathsf{or}\quad y {\Rightarrow} x \nleq x {\Rightarrow} y]. \end{align} $$

Dually, for a variety $\mathsf {V}\subseteq {\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ , $\mathsf {V}$ satisfies an identity from Table 2 if and only if the corresponding connexive law is a theorem of $\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {V})$ . Similarly, if $\mathsf {V}$ has a member in which ${\Rightarrow }$ is not symmetric, then the logic $\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {V})$ satisfies the principle of non-symmetry for ${\Rightarrow }$ .

This leads us to the following definition, whose broader generality will be useful for what follows. Let ${\mathbf A} = \langle A; \leq , {\sim }, 1 \rangle $ be a pointed ordered-algebra with a unary operation, i.e., $\langle A, \leq \rangle $ is a preorder and $\langle A;{\sim },1\rangle $ is an algebra of type $(1,0)$ . For a function ${\Rightarrow }\colon A^2\to A$ , we say $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive if the identities in Table 2 hold in ${\mathbf A}$ , and we say ${\mathbf A}$ is connexive if, furthermore, the condition (NS) holds in ${\mathbf A}$ , i.e., that ${\Rightarrow }$ is not symmetric.

It is worth observing that our notion of proto-connexivity is very general. In fact, it does not mention that ${\Rightarrow }$ and $\sim $ should be understood as a binary and a unary operation satisfying some minimal requirements to be entitled as (the semantical counterpart of) an implication-like and a negation-like connective, respectively. Indeed, our notion is aimed at capturing the behavior of those algebras which may serve in principle as the (possibly equivalent) algebraic semantics of a $1$ -assertional logic satisfying, to some respect, connexive theses.

We are now ready to state the primary definitions for what follows. First, for an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra ${\mathbf A}$ , by ${\mathbf A}'$ we will denote the pointed ordered-algebra ${\langle A;\leq , \neg ,1\rangle }$ , where $\leq $ is the lattice order inherent to ${\mathbf A}$ and $\neg $ is defined as usual, namely $\neg x := x\to 0$ . In this way, we specialize the above concepts to the framework of substructural logics and FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras:

Definition 3.1. Let ${\mathbf A} \in {\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ and ${\Rightarrow }\colon A^2\to A$ a binary function. We say $({\mathbf A}, {\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive if $({\mathbf A}',{\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive, and similarly, $({\mathbf A}, {\Rightarrow })$ is connexive if $({\mathbf A}',{\Rightarrow })$ is connexive. If ${\Rightarrow }$ is term-definable in the language of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras, then for a variety $\mathsf {V}\subseteq {\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ we say $(\mathsf {V},{\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive if for every member of ${\mathbf A}\in \mathsf {V}$ , $({\mathbf A}, {\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive, and we say $(\mathsf {V},{\Rightarrow })$ is connexive if furthermore it contains member ${\mathbf A}$ such that $({\mathbf A}, {\Rightarrow })$ is connexive [i.e., ]. If $\mathbf {L}$ is a substructural logic, we say $(\mathbf {L},{\Rightarrow })$ is (proto-) connexive if $(\mathsf {V}(\mathbf {L}),{\Rightarrow })$ is.

Whenever no danger of confusion will be impending, we will say that a binary operation ${\Rightarrow }$ over $\mathbf {X}$ [taken to be an algebra, variety, or logic], is (proto-) connexive if $(\textbf X,{\Rightarrow })$ is. The next proposition introduces some identities that will be useful for the development of our arguments.

Proposition 3.2. Let ${\mathbf A} $ be an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra and let ${\Rightarrow }\colon A^2\to A$ . If $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ satisfies the identities

(P1) $$ \begin{align} 1 &\leq {x {\Rightarrow} \neg\neg x}, \end{align} $$
(P2) $$ \begin{align} \neg\neg(x {\Rightarrow} y) &\approx \neg(x {\Rightarrow} \neg y ), \end{align} $$

then $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive.

Proof. Note that (P2) is equivalent to $\neg (x {\Rightarrow } y) \approx \neg \neg (x {\Rightarrow } \neg y)$ in the context of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras by Proposition 2.3. Using this observation, by (P1) and Proposition 2.3, we obtain (AT) via $1\leq x{\Rightarrow } \neg \neg x \leq \neg \neg (x{\Rightarrow } \neg \neg x) \approx \neg (x{\Rightarrow } \neg x).$ Similarly, we obtain (AT’) via $1\leq \neg x {\Rightarrow } \neg \neg (\neg x)\leq \neg \neg (\neg x{\Rightarrow } \neg x)\approx \neg (\neg x{\Rightarrow } x)$ . (BT) is derived by a single application of (P1) followed by (P2):

$$ \begin{align*} 1\leq (x{\Rightarrow} y){\Rightarrow} \neg\neg(x{\Rightarrow} y) \approx (x{\Rightarrow} y){\Rightarrow} \neg(x{\Rightarrow} \neg y), \end{align*} $$

and (BT’) is calculated similarly using the equivalent reformation of (P2).

3.2 Connexive implications in ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ -algebras

The most natural question to address first, in the context of substructural logics, is to ask what happens when we assume that the residual operation ${\to }$ satisfies the connexive laws. The ramifications of such an assumption are almost immediate.

Proposition 3.3. The following are equivalent for ${\mathbf A}=\langle A,\wedge ,\vee ,\cdot ,{\to },0,1\rangle \in {\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ :

  1. 1. $({\mathbf A},{\to })$ is proto-connexive.

  2. 2. $({\mathbf A},{\to })\models $ ( AT ).

  3. 3. $0$ is the greatest element in ${\mathbf A}$ .

Proof. (1) implies (2) holds by definition. Suppose (2), then ${\mathbf A}\ \models\ x{\to }\neg x\leq 0$ by residuation. Now, it is easily verified that ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}\ \models\ x\leq (y\land 1){\to } x$ using Proposition 2.1, from which it follows $0\leq (x\land 1){\to } 0$ and $(x\land 1){\to } 0\leq (x\land 1){\to }((x\land 1){\to } 0)\leq 0$ . Hence ${\mathbf A}\ \models\ \neg (x\land 1)\approx 0$ . So for any $x\in A$ , we find $x\leq \neg \neg x \leq \neg (\neg x \wedge 1) \leq 0$ via Proposition 2.3, establishing (3). Lastly, suppose (3) holds, and note that this entails ${\mathbf A}\ \models\ \neg x \approx 0$ , as $0\leq x\to 0$ by residuation of $x\cdot 0\leq 0$ , from which it immediately follows $({\mathbf A},{\to })\ \models$ (P2). Since $1\leq x{\to } \neg \neg x$ is satisfied in any FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra, the desired result follows from Proposition 3.2.

It is worth noticing that an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra ${\mathbf A}$ having $0$ as its largest element is equivalently stated via ${\mathbf A}\ \models\ \neg x\approx \neg y$ , as the forward direction is shown in the proof above and the reverse direction follows from the valuation $x\mapsto \neg z$ and $y\mapsto 1$ . Therefore, the variety of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras satisfying $x\leq 0$ is equal to the variety $\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {V}_\emptyset )$ , the Glivenko variety of ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ relative to the trivial variety $\mathsf {V}_\emptyset = {\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}} + (x\approx y)$ . In fact:

Proposition 3.4. The variety $(\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {V}_\emptyset ),{\to })$ is connexive.

Proof. From Theorem 3.3 we have that $(\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {V}_\emptyset ),{\to })$ is proto-connexive. Thus it suffices to show that it has a member in which ${\to }$ is not symmetric. Now, it is readily verified that commutative residuated lattices satisfy the quasi-identities $x{\to } y \approx y{\to } x ~\mathsf {iff}~ x\approx y$ . Consequently, ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}+(x{\to } y \approx y{\to } x) = \mathsf {V}_\emptyset $ , so we need only verify that $\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {V}_{\emptyset })$ has a nontrivial member, i.e., $\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {V}_{\emptyset }) \neq \mathsf {V}_{\emptyset }$ . Indeed, by expanding any non-trivial integral commutative residuated lattice by a new constant $0$ such that $0:=1$ we obtain a non-trivial FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra in $\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {V}_{\emptyset })$ .

However, the logic $\mathbf {L}=\mathbf {L}(\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {V}_\emptyset ))$ is far from behaving as a desirable connexive logic. In fact, although $\mathbf {L}$ has, for example, Aristotle’s theses among its theorems, one has also that $\vdash _{\mathbf {L}}\varphi \to \neg \varphi $ , for any formula $\varphi $ , since the identity $1\leq x{\to }\neg x$ holds in $\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {V}_{\emptyset })$ . The latter fact implies that $\varphi \vdash _{\mathbf {L}}\neg \varphi $ , for any formula $\varphi $ . Therefore, $\neg $ does not satisfy the minimal requirement for a connective to be entitled as a negation (see, e.g., [Reference Arieli, Avron and Zamansky1, Reference Marcos17, Reference Wansing, Odintsov, Andreas and Verdée31]).

In the light of the above discussion, it seems reasonable to wonder if there exists other term-definable binary operations on FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras (or expansion thereof) behaving like a connexive implication with much more appealing features. To this aim, for the remainder of this paper, we will study the generalized definition of the connexive implication defined in [Reference Fazio, Ledda and Paoli6] as follows. Given a map $\delta \colon A\to A$ on ${\mathbf A}$ , we define the two following operations:

We will pay special attention to the case where $\delta ={\diamond }$ , as the operations ${\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{{\diamond }}$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{{\wedge }}^{{\diamond }}$ are term-definable in the language of ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ . Moreover, we will omit the superscript when no confusion can arise; i.e., and .

It is worth noticing that, for ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\}$ , the identity $1\leq x{\Rightarrow } x$ holds in all FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras as $1\leq x{\to } x\leq x{\to } {\diamond } x$ . Now, while ${\Rightarrow }$ is neither order-preserving in its right argument nor order-reversing in its left argument, generally speaking, it does satisfy a weakened version of these properties:

Proposition 3.5. The following quasi-identities hold in ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ for ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } \}$ :

$$ \begin{align*} x\leq y ~\mathsf{and}~ {\diamond} x \approx {\diamond} y &\quad\mathsf{implies}\quad z{\Rightarrow} x \leq z{\Rightarrow} y,\\ x\leq y ~\mathsf{and}~ {\diamond} x \approx {\diamond} y &\quad\mathsf{implies}\quad y{\Rightarrow} z \leq x{\Rightarrow} z. \end{align*} $$

Proof. Let ${\mathbf A}\in {\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ and let $x,y,z\in A$ . Suppose $x\leq y$ and ${\diamond } x = {\diamond } y$ . The former implies $y{\to } z\leq x{\to } z$ and $z{\to } x\leq z{\to } y$ , by Proposition 2.1(2,3), while the latter implies $x{\to } {\diamond } z = y{\to } {\diamond } z$ , by Proposition 2.3(6). Since $*\in \{\cdot ,\wedge \}$ is order-preserving in both arguments, we obtain

$$ \begin{align*}\begin{array}[b]{l} z{\Rightarrow} x =(z{\to} x)*(x{\to} {\diamond} z)= (z{\to} x)*(y{\to} {\diamond} z)\leq (z{\to} y)*( y{\to} {\diamond} z) = z{\Rightarrow} y, \\ y{\Rightarrow} z =(y{\to} z)*(z{\to} {\diamond} y)=(y{\to} z)*(z{\to} {\diamond} x) \leq (x{\to} z)*(z{\to} {\diamond} x) =x{\Rightarrow} z. \end{array}\\[-35pt]\end{align*} $$

In terms of their relationship to (equational) connexive principles, we now prove the following observation which will be important throughout this paper.

Lemma 3.6. Let ${\mathbf A}$ be an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra and ${\Rightarrow }\in \{ {\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\}$ . Then $({\mathbf A}, {\Rightarrow })$ satisfies ( P1 ). Consequently, if $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models$ ( P2 ) then $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive.

Proof. The first claim follows from Proposition 3.5, setting $y,z:=x$ and in the first quasi-identity, as $x\leq {\diamond } x$ , ${\diamond } x={\diamond }{\diamond } x$ , and $1\leq x{\Rightarrow } x$ always hold. Hence $({\mathbf A}, {\Rightarrow })\ \models$ (P1). The second claim follows by Proposition 3.2.

In fact, even more can be said for the connective ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ , as we see below.

Lemma 3.7. For any FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra ${\mathbf A}$ , the following hold:

  1. 1. For all $x,y\in A$ , $1\leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } y$ iff $x\leq y$ and ${\diamond } x = {\diamond } y$ .

  2. 2. ${\mathbf A} \ \models\ {\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } {\diamond } y) \approx x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } {\diamond } y \approx {\diamond } x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } {\diamond } y$ .

Proof. For the first claim, towards the forward direction, $1\leq x{\to } y$ and $1\leq y{\to } {\diamond } x$ immediately follow by assumption. Hence $x\leq y\leq {\diamond } x$ , and furthermore this gives ${\diamond } x \leq {\diamond } y \leq {\diamond } {\diamond } x = {\diamond } x$ . The reverse direction follows from Proposition 3.5, setting $z:= x$ in the first quasi-identity, since $1\leq x{\Rightarrow } x$ always holds. The second claim immediately follows by Proposition 2.3(5,6).

Furthermore, we obtain a (stronger) converse of Lemma 3.6 for ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ .

Lemma 3.8. Let ${\mathbf A}$ be an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra. Then the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. $({\mathbf A}, {\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ is proto-connexive.

  2. 2. $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })\ \models$ (BT).

  3. 3. $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })\ \models $ (BT’).

  4. 4. $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })\ \models$ (P2).

  5. 5. $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ models the following identity:

    (P3) $$ \begin{align} \neg(x{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge} y) \approx x{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge} \neg y. \end{align} $$

Proof. For simplicity, set . Clearly (1) implies both (2) and (3), by definition, (4) and (5) are equivalent by Lemma 3.7(2), and (4) implies (1) by Lemma 3.6. It is sufficient then to show that (2) and (3) each imply (4). Indeed, if $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ satisfies (BT) then for any $x,y\in A$ we have $1\leq (x{\Rightarrow } y) {\Rightarrow } \neg (x{\Rightarrow } \neg y) $ . Hence by Lemma 3.7(1), $\neg (x{\Rightarrow } y)\approx {\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow }\neg y)$ . A similar calculation shows (3) implies (4).

Remark 3.9. It is worth noticing that ( P3 ) is a well-known and motivated falsification condition for (connexive) implication (see, e.g., [Reference Wansing, Schmidt, Pratt-Hartmann, Reynolds and Wansing28, Reference Wansing and Zalta29]). For example, [Reference Wansing30] motivates ( P3 ) by the introduction of negated syntactic types in Categorial Grammar (see, e.g., [Reference Buszkowski and Wansing4]) and the consequent need of providing falsity conditions for the functor-type forming directional implications. Wansing’s connexive logic $\mathsf {C}$ is algebraizable w.r.t. a slight modification of the equivalent algebraic semantics of paraconsistent Nelson’s logic $\mathsf {N4}$ satisfying, among other axioms, ( P3 ) (see [Reference Fazio and Odintsov7]).

Example 3.10. The above lemma does not generally hold in ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ for the connective ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ . Indeed, consider $\mathbb {Z}(n)$ from Example 2.4, for some arbitrary $n\in \mathbb {Z}$ . It is easy to verify that $(\mathbb {Z}(n),{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ })$ satisfies (BT) since $x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } y = 0 = 1_{\mathbb {Z}(n)}$ for all $x,y\in \mathbb {Z}$ . However, taking $n\neq 0$ , we see $\neg (x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } \neg y)=n\neq 0 = x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } y = {\diamond } (x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } y).$ Moreover, fixing $n<0$ and $y=x$ above we have $\neg (x {\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }\neg x) = n \not \geq 0=1_{\mathbb {Z}(n)}$ , so $(\mathbb {Z}(n),{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ })$ does not satisfy (AT). We do, however, obtain a restricted converse with ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ relative to FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras satisfying $x\leq {\diamond } 1$ [see Lemma 3.18].

Lastly, we prove the following proposition, whose generality will be useful in the next section.

Proposition 3.11. Suppose ${\mathbf A}$ is an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra in which $0$ is the greatest element. Then for any map $\delta : A^2 \to A$ , the connective ${\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{\delta }$ is proto-connexive on ${\mathbf A}$ . For $\delta = {\diamond }$ , then the connective ${\Rightarrow }_{{\wedge }}^{{\diamond }}$ is proto-connexive in ${\mathbf A}$ .

Proof. The first claim follows from the fact that ${\mathbf A}$ satisfies $\neg x \approx 0$ , hence also $x\cdot 0 \approx 0$ and $x{\to } \neg y \approx 0$ , from which it follows $x{\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{\delta } \neg y \approx 0$ . Consequently, Aristotle’s and Boethius’ theses hold for ${\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{\delta }$ . For the second claim, $x{\Rightarrow }_{{\wedge }}^{{\diamond }} \neg y \approx 0$ holds in ${\mathbf A}$ , so ${\Rightarrow }_{{\wedge }}^{{\diamond }}$ is proto-connexive.

3.3 Characterizing connexivity for ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$

We will now investigate the varieties of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras satisfying the connexive laws for both ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ , and their relationship to the Glivenko variety relative to Boolean Algebras, which is, at least implicitly, hinted at in [Reference Fazio, Ledda and Paoli6]. We provide a characterization for ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ in the general case, and a restricted one for ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ . To that aim, let us start with the following technical lemmas.

Lemma 3.12. Let ${\mathbf A}$ be an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra such that ${\diamond }{\mathbf A}$ is integral. Then:

  1. 1. ${\mathbf A}$ satisfies $x{\to } y \approx x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } ({\diamond } x \wedge y).$

  2. 2. ${\mathbf A}$ satisfies $x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }\neg y \leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } \neg y$ and ${\diamond } x {\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } x \leq {\diamond }({\diamond } x {\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } x)$ .

  3. 3. Let ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\}$ . Then the following hold:

    (a) If $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models$ (AT) then ${\mathbf A}$ is pseudo-complemented.

    (b) If $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models$ (P2) then ${\mathbf A}$ satisfies $1\leq {\diamond }({\diamond } x {\to } x)$ .

Proof. Let $*\in \{\wedge ,\cdot \}$ , and note that ${\mathbf A} \ \models\ {\diamond } x \approx {\diamond } x * {\diamond } 1$ since ${\diamond } 1$ is the greatest element (for the $\wedge $ case), and ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}\ \models\ {\diamond } 1\cdot {\diamond } x \approx {\diamond } x$ (for the $\cdot $ case).Footnote 4 Furthermore, note that ${\diamond } 1$ being the greatest element implies ${\diamond }({\diamond } x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } x) \approx {\diamond }({\diamond } x {\to } x)$ .

For (1), note that ${\diamond } {\mathbf A}$ being integral entails ${\diamond } 1 = x{\to } {\diamond } y$ whenever $x\leq {\diamond } y$ . So for $x,y\in A$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*}\begin{array}{r c l l} x{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge}({\diamond} x\wedge y) &=& [x{\to} ({\diamond} x \wedge y)] \wedge [({\diamond} x \wedge y){\to} {\diamond} x]\\ &=& [x{\to} ({\diamond} x \wedge y)] \wedge {\diamond} 1 \\ &=& (x{\to} {\diamond} x) \wedge(x{\to} y) \\ &=& {\diamond} 1 \wedge(x{\to} y) \\ &=& x{\to} y. \end{array}\end{align*} $$

For (2), first observe that ${\diamond }{\mathbf A}$ being integral entails that $xy\leq {\diamond } x\wedge {\diamond } y$ . Hence, from this observation and Proposition 2.3(6),

$$ \begin{align*}x{\Rightarrow}_{\hspace{-.2em}\circ} \neg y=(x{\to} \neg y)\cdot (\neg y{\to} {\diamond} x)\leq(x{\to} \neg y)\wedge (\neg y{\to} {\diamond} x)=x{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge} \neg y.\end{align*} $$

For the other identity, observe that ${\diamond } x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } x \leq ({\diamond } x {\to } x)\cdot {\diamond } 1\leq {\diamond }({\diamond } x {\to } x)={\diamond }({\diamond } x {\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } x)$ .

For (3), let ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\}$ . Towards (a), set . By order-preservation and residuation, it is easy to see that $c\leq \neg c$ . Since ${\diamond } {\mathbf A}$ is integral, we have, on the one hand, ${\diamond } 1 = c{\to } \neg c $ , and on the other hand ${\diamond } c = {\diamond } 1 {\to } {\diamond } c \leq \neg c {\to } {\diamond } c $ . Now, if $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ satisfies (AT), then we have

For (b), by Proposition 3.2 we have $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models$ (AT’). So for $x\in A$ , we have

$$ \begin{align*}\begin{array}[b]{rcll} 1 &\leq& \neg({\diamond} x{\Rightarrow} \neg x) &\mbox{By (AT')}\\ &=&{\diamond}({\diamond} x{\Rightarrow} x) &\mbox{By (P2)} \\ &\leq& {\diamond}({\diamond} x {\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge} x) & \mbox{By (2)}\\ &=& {\diamond}({\diamond} x {\to} x). \end{array}\\[-33pt] \end{align*} $$

Example 3.13. The converse of Lemma 3.12(1) holds for ${{\Rightarrow }}= {\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ . Indeed, it is easily checked that ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}\ \models\ x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } ({\diamond } x\wedge y)\leq x{\to } {\diamond } x,$ So, if ${\mathbf A}$ satisfies $x{\to } y \approx x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }({\diamond } x \wedge y)$ , by taking $x=1$ we obtain $y = 1{\to } y \leq 1 {\to } {\diamond } 1 = {\diamond } 1.$

Lemma 3.14. Let ${\mathbf A}$ be an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra. If $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })\ \models $ (P2) then ${\mathbf A} \in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ .

Proof. Note that $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ satisfies (AT) by Lemma 3.8. In light of Lemmas 2.10(2) and 3.12(3), it suffices to verify that ${\diamond }{\mathbf A}$ is integral. Indeed, for $x\in A$ ,

$$ \begin{align*}\begin{array}{r c l l} x{\to} {\diamond}1&\geq& (x{\to} {\diamond}1) \wedge {\diamond} x \\ &=& (x{\to} {\diamond}1) \wedge ({\diamond} 1 {\to} {\diamond} x) \\ &=& x {\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge} {\diamond} 1 \end{array} \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}\begin{array}{r c l l} &=&\neg (x{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge} 0)& \mbox{By (P3) since } {\diamond} 1 = \neg 0\\ &\geq & \neg (x{\to} 0) & \mbox{By def. of } {\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge}\\ &\geq& x &\mbox{By Prop.~2.3(1)}, \end{array} \end{align*} $$

and so $x\cdot x\leq {\diamond } 1$ by residuation. It easily follows (e.g., by the substitution $x\mapsto y\vee 1$ ) that ${\diamond } 1$ is the greatest element of ${\mathbf A}$ , i.e., ${\diamond } {\mathbf A}$ is integral.

Remark 3.15. The lemma above does not generally hold for the connective ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ . Indeed, consider $\mathbb {Z}(n)$ from Example 2.4 for $n=0$ . Clearly ${\diamond } \mathbb {Z}(0)$ is not integral, but it is easily checked that $(\mathbb {Z}(0),{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ })$ satisfies ( P2 ).

Lemma 3.16. If ${\mathbf A} \in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ then $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ is proto-connexive.

Proof. Boolean algebras are involutive and have ${\wedge } ={\cdot }$ , so it follows that

$$ \begin{align*}\mathbf{G}_{{\mathsf{FL}_{\mathsf{e}}}}(\mathsf{BA})\ \models\ \neg [x{\Rightarrow} y] \approx \neg[(x{\to} y)\wedge (y{\to} x)].\end{align*} $$

Furthermore, it is easily verified that Boolean algebras satisfy the identities:

$$ \begin{align*}(x{\to} \neg y)\wedge (\neg y {\to} \neg\neg x) \approx (x{\to} \neg y)\wedge (\neg y {\to} x) \approx \neg[(x{\to} y)\wedge (y{\to} x)],\end{align*} $$

and hence it follows that $\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ satisfies $\neg (x{\Rightarrow } \neg y) \approx {\diamond } (x{\Rightarrow } y)$ . So $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ satisfies (P2), and therefore is proto-connexive by Lemma 3.8.

We now obtain our promised characterization from Lemmas 3.8, 3.16, and 3.14.

Theorem 3.17. Let $\mathsf {V}$ be a variety of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras. Then $(\mathsf {V},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ is proto-connexive [or satisfies any of the identities (BT), (BT’), or ( P2 )] if and only if $\mathsf {V} \subseteq \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ . Consequently, the largest variety of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras for which ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ is proto-connexive is exactly $\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ .

We now remark upon the connexivity of other connectives in $\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ . We start by proving the following technical lemma, whose generality will be useful in the sequel.

Lemma 3.18. Let ${\mathbf A}$ be an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra such that ${\diamond }{\mathbf A}$ is integral. Let ${\Rightarrow }$ be a binary operation over ${\mathbf A}$ such that $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ satisfies (i) ( P1 ) and the identities (ii) $x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } y \leq {\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow } y)\leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } {\diamond } y$ . Then the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive.

  2. 2. $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ models any one of (BT), (BT’), or ( P2 ).

  3. 3. $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ is proto-connexive [equivalently, ${\mathbf A} \in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ ].

In particular, the above holds for ${\Rightarrow }:= {\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ .

Proof. Let us begin with (1) implies (2). Clearly, (1) implies both (BT) and (BT’) by definition. We show that either of these are sufficient to obtain (P2). Let $x,y\in A$ and define $a:= x{\Rightarrow } y$ and $b:=x{\Rightarrow } \neg y$ . If (BT) holds, then $1\leq a{\Rightarrow }\neg b$ , and we observe

(3.1) $$ \begin{align} \begin{array}{r c l l} 1 &\leq& a{\Rightarrow} \neg b \\ &\leq& {\diamond}[a{\Rightarrow} \neg b] & \mbox{By (ii)} \\ &\leq & {\diamond}[a{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge} \neg b] & \mbox{By assumption on } {\Rightarrow} \\ &=& a {\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge} \neg b & \mbox{By Lem. 3.7(2)}. \end{array} \end{align} $$

Hence, by Lemma 3.7(1), $\neg \neg a = \neg b$ . So $({\mathbf A}, \Rightarrow )\ \models $ (P2). The very same argument (3.1) follows for the (BT’)-case by swapping the roles of a and b. Hence we have concluded (1) implies (2).

For (2) implies (3), we have that, by the arguments above, $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ satisfies (P2) in any case. So (3) follows from that fact that $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive by (i) and Proposition 3.2, i.e., it satisfies (BT), and so by the same argument (3.1) above (by setting $a:= x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } y$ and $b:=x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } \neg y$ ) we conclude $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })\ \models $ (P2), and the result follows from Lemma 3.8.

Now suppose (3) holds. On the one hand, by Lemma 3.8 $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })\ \models\ \mathrm {(P3)}$ , so ${\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } y)=x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } {\diamond } y$ . On the other hand, ${\mathbf A} \in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ by Theorem 3.17, so ${\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } y)= {\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } y)$ by Theorem 2.8(1a). Thus ${\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow } y)={\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } y)$ follows the assumption that ${\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } y)\leq {\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow } y)\leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } {\diamond } y$ . Hence $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models$ (P2) follows from the fact $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ does. Since $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models$ (P1) by assumption, $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive by Proposition 3.2. This completes the equivalences.

Lastly, clearly the above holds for ${\Rightarrow }:={\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ since (i) and (ii) follow from Lemmas 3.6 and 3.12(2).

Corollary 3.19. Let $\mathsf {V}$ be a subvariety of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras. Then $(\mathsf {V},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ is proto-connexive iff $(\mathsf {V},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ })$ is proto-connexive and $\mathsf {V}$ satisfies the identity $x\leq {\diamond } 1$ .

Example 3.20. The converse to the above does not hold if the assumption of $x\leq {\diamond } 1$ is dropped; e.g., $\mathbb {Z}(0)$ has no largest element, $(\mathbb {Z}(0),{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ })$ is proto-connexive, but (BT) (take $x=0$ and $y=1$ ).

Having established the proto-connexitivity of ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ (and other related operations) in the Glivenko variety relative to Boolean algebras, we now investigate the principle of non-symmetry (NS).

Lemma 3.21. Let ${\mathbf A}\in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ and let ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\}$ . Then $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ falsifies ( NS ), i.e., ${\Rightarrow }$ is symmetric on ${\mathbf A}$ , if and only if ${\mathbf A}$ is a Boolean algebra.

Proof. Of course, if ${\mathbf A}$ is a Boolean algebra, then ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } ={\leftrightarrow }={\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ which is indeed symmetric. For the converse direction, first note that ${\diamond } 1$ is the largest element of ${\mathbf A}$ . Let $*\in \{\wedge ,\cdot \}$ and ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\}$

$$ \begin{align*}{\diamond} 1 = (1\to{\diamond} 1)*({\diamond} 1 \to{\diamond} 1)=1{{\kern-1.5pt}\Rightarrow{\kern-1.5pt}}{\diamond} 1 {\kern-1pt}={\kern-1pt}{\diamond} 1{{\kern-1.5pt}\Rightarrow{\kern-1.5pt}} 1{\kern-1pt}={\kern-1pt} ({\diamond} 1{\kern-1pt}\to{\kern-1pt} 1)*(1{\kern-1pt}\to{\kern-1pt}{\diamond} 1)=({\diamond} 1{\kern-1pt}\to{\kern-1pt} 1)*{\diamond} 1.\end{align*} $$

On the one hand, if ${*}={\cdot}$ , then $(\diamond 1\to 1)*\diamond 1\leq 1$ , so $1=\diamond 1$ . On the other hand, for ${*}={\wedge}$ we have $(\diamond 1\to 1)*\diamond 1 = \diamond1 \to 1$ , so one has $\diamond 1\cdot\diamond 1\leq 1$ and we compute $x=x\cdot 1\leq x\cdot {\diamond } 1\leq {\diamond } 1\cdot {\diamond } 1\leq 1$ . So $1={\diamond } 1$ in either case, and consequently $1=x{\to } 1$ .

Now, $x=(1\to x)*(x\to {\diamond } 1)=1{\Rightarrow } x=x{\Rightarrow } 1=(x\to 1)*(1\to {\diamond } x)={\diamond } x.$ The involutivity of $\neg $ , together with ${\mathbf A}\in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ , yield directly that ${\mathbf A}$ is Boolean.

Therefore, by Theorem 3.17, Corollary 3.19, Remark 2.9, and the lemma above:

Corollary 3.22. Let $\mathsf {V}$ be any variety of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras in the interval between $\mathsf {HA}$ and $\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ . Then the connectives ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ are both connexive in $\mathsf {V}$ .

3.4 Generalizations in the integral case

We now consider the special case when dealing with integral (and $0$ -bounded) FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras, and show that the results from Section 3.3 can be strengthened. In fact, Theorem 3.25 shows that, in the setting of $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}$ ( $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}$ ), a binary operation in the pointwise ordered interval $[{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }]$ is proto-connexive if and only if any operation in the interval is. Moreover, ${\diamond }$ is the only increasing mapping for which this holds. Furthermore, we demonstrate that satisfying any one of Aristotle’s theses is sufficient to guarantee proto-connexivity for subvarieties of $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}$ .

Since integral FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras satisfy the identity $x\cdot y \leq x\wedge y$ , given such an algebra ${\mathbf A}$ and map $\delta $ , it follows $x{\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{\delta } y\leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta } y$ for all $x,y\in A$ . We define the (nonempty) interval of functions $[{\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{\delta },{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }]\subseteq A^2\times A$ via

$$ \begin{align*} f\in[{\Rightarrow}_{\circ}^{\delta},{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge}^{\delta}] \iff (\forall x,y\in A)[ x{\Rightarrow}_{\circ}^{\delta} y \leq f(x,y) \leq x{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge}^{\delta} y ].\end{align*} $$

Lemma 3.23. Let ${\mathbf A}$ be an integral FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra, $\delta $ be an increasing map on ${\mathbf A}$ , and ${\Rightarrow }\in [{\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{\delta },{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }]$ .

  1. 1. For all $x\in A$ , $1{\Rightarrow } x = x$ and $x{\Rightarrow } 1={\delta {x}}$ .

  2. 2. If $({\mathbf A}, {\Rightarrow })$ models either (AT) or (AT’), then ${\mathbf A}$ is pseudo-complemented.

  3. 3. If $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models $ ( BT ) then $\neg x\approx x{\Rightarrow } 0$ , ${\delta } = {{\diamond }}$ , and ${\mathbf A} \in \mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ .

Proof. (1) easily follows from the following calculations, by integrality and virtue of the fact that ${\Rightarrow }\in [{\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{\delta },{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }]$ and $\delta $ is increasing: For $x\in A$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} 1{\Rightarrow}_{\hspace{-.2em}\circ} x = (1{\to} x)\cdot (x{\to} \delta{1})=x\cdot 1=x=x\wedge 1=(1{\to} x)\wedge (x{\to} \delta{1}) = 1{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge} x,\\ x{\Rightarrow}_{\hspace{-.2em}\circ} 1 = (x{\to} 1)\cdot( 1{\to} {\delta{x}}) = 1\cdot {\delta{x}} = {\delta{x}}= 1\cdot {\delta{x}}=(x{\to} 1)\wedge( 1{\to} {\delta{x}}) = x{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge} 1. \end{align*} $$

For (2), we follow essentially the same argument as Lemma 3.12(3a). Suppose $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ satisfies (AT), and let $x\in A$ . Set and recall that $c\leq \neg c$ . Since $ {\mathbf A}$ is integral, we have, on the one hand, $ 1 = c{\to } \neg c $ , and on the other hand ${\delta {c}} \leq \neg c {\to } {\delta {c}} $ . Hence

$$ \begin{align*} c\leq {\delta{c}} \leq \neg c \to {\delta{c}} = (c{\to} \neg c)\cdot (\neg c \to {\delta{c}} ) = c{\Rightarrow}_{\circ}^{\delta} \neg c \leq c{\Rightarrow} \neg c\leq 0, \end{align*} $$

where the last line follows from (AT) by residuation. So ${\mathbf A}$ is pseudo-complemented. The same argument follows for (AT’) by considering $\neg \neg c {\Rightarrow } \neg c$ , as $c\leq \neg c$ implies ${\diamond } c\leq \neg c$ , so $c\leq \delta ({\diamond } c)\leq ({\diamond } c {\to } \neg c)\cdot (\neg c {\to } \delta ({\diamond } c)) ={\diamond } c {\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } \neg c \leq {\diamond } c {\Rightarrow } \neg c \leq 0 $ .

For (3), suppose $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models$ (BT). Using (BT) and (1), we have

$$ \begin{align*} 1 = (1{\Rightarrow} x) {\Rightarrow} \neg (1 {\Rightarrow} \neg x) = x {\Rightarrow} \neg\neg x \leq x{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge}^{\delta} {\diamond} x =(x\to {\diamond} x) \wedge ({\diamond} x \to {\delta{x}}) = {\diamond} x {\to} {\delta{x}}, \end{align*} $$

where the last equality follows from integrality. So ${\diamond } x \leq {\delta {x}}$ by residuation. Since ${\mathbf A}$ is integral, $0\cdot \neg x\leq 0$ and thus $0\leq {\diamond } x\leq {\delta {x}}$ , so it follows that $ 0{\to } {\delta {x}} = 1$ . Hence

$$ \begin{align*} \neg x = (x{\to} 0)\cdot (0{\to} {\delta{x}})= x{\Rightarrow}_{\circ}^{\delta} 0 \leq x{\Rightarrow} 0 \leq x{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge}^{\delta} 0 = (x{\to} 0)\wedge (0{\to} {\delta{x}}) = \neg x , \end{align*} $$

completing the first claim. Towards the second claim, it suffices to show ${\delta {x}}\leq {\diamond } x$ , or equivalently $1\leq {\delta {x}}\to {\diamond } x$ . Indeed, we see

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}[b]{ r c l l} 1 &=& (x{\Rightarrow} 1) {\Rightarrow} \neg (x {\Rightarrow} \neg 1) & \mbox{By (BT)}\\ &=& {\delta{x}} {\Rightarrow} \neg (x {\Rightarrow} 0) & \mbox{By (1)}\\ &=& {\delta{x}} {\Rightarrow} {\diamond} x & \mbox{By (b)}\\ &\leq& {\delta{x}} {\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge}^{\delta} {\diamond} x & \mbox{Def. of } {\Rightarrow}\\ &=& {\delta{x}}{\to} {\diamond} x &\mbox{By integrality since } {\diamond} x {\to} {\delta{x}}=1. \end{array} \end{align*} $$

Hence $\delta = {\diamond }$ , and so ${\Rightarrow }\in [{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }]$ . Since $x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } y \leq x {\Rightarrow } y$ , ${\Rightarrow } $ clearly satisfies (P1) by Lemma 3.6. Therefore, ${\Rightarrow }$ satisfies the assumptions of Lemma 3.18, and hence ${\mathbf A} \in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ . Since ${\mathbf A}$ is integral by assumption, the claim follows.

The lemma above allows us to conclude, in contrast to the general case in Section 3.3, the following stronger theorems in the integral setting.

Theorem 3.24. Let ${\mathbf A}$ be an integral FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra, $\delta $ an increasing mapping on ${\mathbf A}$ , and ${\Rightarrow }\in [{\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{\delta },{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }]$ . Then $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive but it does not satisfy $(\mathrm {NS})$ if and only if $\delta = {\diamond }$ and ${\mathbf A}$ is a Boolean algebra.

Proof. Suppose that $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive but it does not satisfy $(\mathrm {NS})$ . So $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ satisfies (BT), and hence $\delta ={\diamond }$ and ${\mathbf A}\in \mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ by Lemma 3.23(3), in particular $\delta {\mathbf A} = {\diamond }{\mathbf A} \in \mathsf {BA}$ . Since $(\mathrm {NS})$ is not satisfied and hence, for any $x\in A$ , $x{\Rightarrow } 1 = 1{\Rightarrow } x$ . Thus $x = {\delta {x}}={\diamond } x$ by Lemma 3.23(1), and we conclude ${\diamond } = \mathrm {id}_{\mathbf {A}}$ . So ${\mathbf A}={\diamond }{\mathbf A}$ is a Boolean algebra.

The converse direction easily follows upon noticing that, if ${\mathbf A}$ is a Boolean algebra and ${\diamond }=\delta $ , then ${{\Rightarrow }} = {\leftrightarrow }$ follows from involutivity and fact that $\cdot $ and $\wedge $ coincide in Boolean algebras. Of course, material equivalence in Boolean algebras is proto-connexive but fails $(\mathrm {NS})$ by straightforward calculations.

Theorem 3.25. For ${\mathbf A}$ an integral FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra, the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. ${\mathbf A} \in \mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ (i.e., ${\mathbf A}$ is strongly pseudo-complemented).

  2. 2. For all ${\Rightarrow }\in [{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }]$ , $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive.

  3. 3. There exists an increasing $\delta $ and ${\Rightarrow }\in [{\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{\delta },{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }]$ such that $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models $ (BT).

Proof. For (1) implies (2), note that ${\Rightarrow }\in [{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }]$ implies $x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } y \leq {\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow } y)\leq {\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } y)$ and ${\diamond }(x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } y) = x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } {\diamond } y$ by the fact that ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ satisfies (P3) by (1). Since $ {\diamond } {\mathbf A}$ is integral, by fiat, (2) follows from Lemma 3.18. (2) implies (3) is obvious, and (3) implies (1) by Lemma 3.23(3).

In light of Corollary 2.12 and Lemma 3.23(2), the theorem above implies:

Corollary 3.26. Let ${\mathbf A} \in \mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}$ . Then the following are equivalent.

  1. 1. ${\mathbf A} \in \mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ (i.e., ${\mathbf A}$ is pseudo-complemented).

  2. 2. For all ${\Rightarrow }\in [{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }]$ , $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })$ is proto-connexive.

  3. 3. There exists an increasing $\delta $ and ${\Rightarrow }\in [{\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{\delta },{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }]$ such that $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models $ (AT).

Example 3.27. Note that the direction (3) to (1) in Corollary 3.26 does not generally hold if $0$ -boundedness is dropped. Indeed, Figure 1 is an integral FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra satisfying Aristotle’s thesis but not Boethius’ thesis (take $x = 0$ and $y = \bot $ ) for ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ .

3.5 Returning to the logics: the main results

In what follows, we put in good use Theorem 2.5 to set substructural logics mimicking a connexive implication expressed in terms of ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ “on the map.” First, as a consequence of Theorem 3.17, Lemma 3.18, and Corollary 3.22, we obtain the following theorem.

Theorem 3.28. Let $\mathbf {L}$ be any substructural logic in the interval between $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}$ and $\mathbf {IPL}$ . Then the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. $(\mathbf {L},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ is a connexive logic.

  2. 2. $(\mathbf {L},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ is a proto-connexive logic.

  3. 3. Any one of Boethius’ theses for ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ are theorems of $\mathbf {L}$ .

  4. 4. $\mathbf {L}$ is an axiomatic extension of $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}}(\mathbf {CPL})$ .

The same holds for the connective ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ if it is further assumed that $\varphi {\to } \neg \neg 1$ are theorems of $\mathbf {L}$ .

Furthermore, in the presence of weakening, by Corollary 3.26 the above theorem specializes:

Theorem 3.29. Let $\mathbf {L}$ be any logic in the interval between $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ew}}$ and $\mathbf {IPL}$ . Then the following are equivalent for ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } \}$ :

  1. 1. $(\mathbf {L},{\Rightarrow })$ is a connexive logic.

  2. 2. Any one of Aristotle’s theses for ${\Rightarrow }$ are theorems of $\mathbf {L}$ .

  3. 3. $\mathbf {L}$ is an axiomatic extension of $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ew}}}(\mathbf {CPL})$ .

Interestingly enough, in the framework of $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ew}}$ , the above result “does justice” to the idea that “Aristotles Thesis is the cornerstone of the logics belonging to the family of so-called connexive logics” (cf. [Reference Pizzi24]).

Since the variety $\mathsf {HA}$ of Heyting algebras is pseudo-complemented, we recover the following result from [Reference Fazio, Ledda and Paoli6] as a particular instance of Theorem 3.29.

Corollary 3.30. $(\mathsf {HA},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ is connexive, and therefore $(\mathbf {IPL},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ is connexive.

As the connectives $\cdot $ and $\wedge $ coincide in Heyting algebras, so too do the operations ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ . We therefore conclude with the following corollary.

Corollary 3.31. The connectives ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ are connexive for every logic in the interval between $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}}(\mathbf {CPL})$ and $\mathbf {IPL}$ .

4 Some philosophical considerations

As we have seen through the above sections, the implication ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ plays a prominent role in our investigation. Indeed, its intrinsic interest (see page 3) depends not only on that it behaves as a connexive implication with a desirable formal behavior, but also on its particularly smooth interpretation. Section 4.1 is devoted to deepening such a reading, highlighting interesting links between ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and the theory of plausible reasoning. Subsequently, we will put into good use the machinery developed so far in order to highlight some interesting features of ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ . The last part of this section provides an investigation of two variants of connexivity, namely weak and strong connexivity. Interestingly enough, we will show that, when dealing with $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}$ , these concepts can be regarded as one and the same thing. Furthermore, we will point out that, for any substructural logic, the strong connexivity of ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ is formally embodied by a well-known inference schema of intuitionistic logic: ex falso quodlibet.

4.1 A focus on ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$

In the second volume of his famous Mathematics and plausible reasoning [Reference Polya26], Polya aims at formulating several patterns of plausible reasoning explicitly. Among them, he investigates an inference schema “which is of so general use that we could extract it from almost any example” [Reference Polya26, vol. 2, p. 3]. Let A be some clearly formulated conjecture which is, at present, neither proved, nor refuted. Also, let B be some consequence of A which we have neither proved, nor refuted, as well. For example, if we set A to be Goldbach’s conjecture

every even natural number greater than 2 is the sum of two prime numbers,

B might be that $198388=p_1 + p_2$ for suitable primes $p_1$ and $p_2$ . Indeed, although we do not know whether A or B is true, it is unquestionable that A implies B. We verify B. If B turns out to be false, then performing modus tollens we can conclude that A is false as well. Otherwise, if we recognize that B is true (and this is the case), then, although we do not have a proof of A, we can nevertheless conclude that A is more credible (implicitly understood as more credible than before). In other words, we have applied the following fundamental inductive pattern (in brief “inductive pattern” [Reference Polya26, vol. 2, p. 4]) or heuristic syllogism:

$$ \begin{align*} \frac{A\ \textrm{implies}\ B \quad B}{A\ \textrm{is}\ \textrm{more}\ \textrm{credible}}. \end{align*} $$

As stated in [Reference Polya25, p. 34], a reasonable logic of plausible inference should (a) be general enough to include the use of inductive (in a broad sense) reasoning in mathematics; (b) include the heuristic syllogism among its inference rules; and (c) be fully qualitative, in the sense that “[…] it is not possible to give a numerical value to the degree of credence attached to any statement considered.” If one takes into account the possibility of developing this proposal in a monotonic setting, then it is reasonable to interpret “x is more credible” (or “x is more likely to be true than before”) as a modal operator. Therefore, it becomes worthy of attention considering expansions of $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}$ in which assertions on “plausibility,” as well as the inductive pattern, are amenable of a formal treatment.

To this aim, and to motivate a formal account of the notion of plausibility, one might rely on the following assumptions:Footnote 5

  • $\blacklozenge $ 1 If $\neg A$ is more credible, then A is not.

  • $\blacklozenge $ 2 If $\neg A$ is false, then A is more credible.

  • $\blacklozenge $ 3 If A is equivalent to B, then A is more credible if and only if B is.

Note that $\blacklozenge $ 1 encodes a weak version of Polya’s principle that “non-A more credible” is equivalent to “A less credible” (see [Reference Polya26, vol. 2, p. 23]).

Let us consider then the language $\mathcal {L}=\{\land ,\lor ,\cdot ,\rightarrow ,\blacklozenge ,0,1\}$ , where $\blacklozenge $ is a unary (modal) operator. We denote the absolutely free algebra over $\mathcal {L}$ generated by a denumerable set of variables by $\textit {Fm}_{\mathcal {L}}$ . The formula $\blacklozenge \varphi $ will be read as “ $\varphi $ is more credible/plausible/likely to be true than before.” In order to include $\blacklozenge $ 1- $\blacklozenge $ 3 in our formal system, we consider the expansion $\vdash _{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}^{\blacklozenge } }\subseteq \wp ({\textit {Fm}}_{\mathcal {L}})\times {\textit {Fm}}_{\mathcal {L}}$ of $\vdash _{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}}$ by the following axioms and inference schemas:

  • $\blacklozenge $ 1: $\vdash _{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}^{\blacklozenge } } \blacklozenge \neg \varphi \to \neg \blacklozenge \varphi $ ;

  • $\blacklozenge $ 2: $\vdash _{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}^{\blacklozenge } } \neg \neg \varphi \to \blacklozenge \varphi $ ;

  • $\blacklozenge $ 3: $\varphi \leftrightarrow \psi \vdash _{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}^{\blacklozenge } } \blacklozenge \varphi \leftrightarrow \blacklozenge \psi $ .

Due to $\blacklozenge $ 3, it follows from general facts concerning algebraizable logics (see, e.g., [Reference Font8, proposition 3.31]) that $\vdash _{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}^{\blacklozenge }}$ is algebraizable. Its equivalent algebraic semantics is the variety $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}^{\blacklozenge }$ of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}^\blacklozenge $ -algebras whose members are structures of the form $(A,\land ,\lor ,\cdot ,\to , \blacklozenge ,0,1)$ where $(A,\land ,\lor ,\cdot ,\to ,0,1)$ is an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra, and the following identities hold:

  1. A1: $\blacklozenge \neg x\leq \neg \blacklozenge x$ ;

  2. A2: $\neg \neg x\leq \blacklozenge x.$

As a consequence, we have the following.

Proposition 4.1. Any FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}^\blacklozenge $ -algebra satisfies $\neg \neg x \approx \blacklozenge x$ .

Proof. One has that $\neg x\geq \neg \blacklozenge x\geq \blacklozenge \neg x\geq \neg \neg \neg x= \neg x$ . We conclude that $\neg x=\neg \blacklozenge x$ . Consequently, we have $\neg \neg x=\neg \neg \blacklozenge x\geq \blacklozenge x$ and $\neg \neg x=\blacklozenge x$ .

Note that, in particular, any FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}^\blacklozenge $ -algebra satisfies the identity $\blacklozenge \blacklozenge x\approx \blacklozenge x.$ It is arguable that this last fact seems to have a rather intuitive flavor, since it just establishes that the statement “The proposition ‘A is more credible than before’ is more credible than before” is equivalent to “A is more credible than before.”

Now, we observe that, in general, the following does not hold:

(4.1) $$ \begin{align} \varphi\to\psi,\psi\vdash_{\mathbf{FL}_{\mathbf{e}}^{\blacklozenge} }\blacklozenge\varphi, \end{align} $$

i.e., $\to $ does not satisfy the inductive pattern. However, it is easy to see that ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ is the weakest term-definable implication-like connective $\leadsto $ satisfying, for any formulas $\varphi ,\psi \in {\textit {Fm}}_{\mathcal {L}}$ , the following (stronger) axiomatic renderings of modus ponens, and the heuristic syllogism

  1. S1: $\vdash _{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}^{\blacklozenge } }(\varphi \leadsto \psi )\to (\varphi \to \psi )$ ,

  2. S2: $\vdash _{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}^{\blacklozenge } } (\varphi \leadsto \psi )\to (\psi \to \blacklozenge \varphi )$ ,

where “weakest” here means that, for any term-definable binary connective $\leadsto $ satisfying S1-S2, we have that, for any $\varphi ,\psi \in {\textit {Fm}}_{\mathcal {L}}$ :

$$ \begin{align*} \vdash_{\mathbf{FL}_{\mathbf{e}}^{\blacklozenge} }(\varphi\leadsto\psi)\to(\varphi{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge}\psi). \end{align*} $$

In light of the above discussion, it can be argued that, under Polya’s desiderata [Reference Polya25], ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ might be considered as a reasonable candidate for formalizing the kind of conditionals which express a connection between a conjecture and one of its consequences in a monotonic framework. In fact, given that in any FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra ${\mathbf A}$ it holds that

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{r c l } x{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge} y&=& (x\to y)\land (y\to{\diamond} x)\\ &=& (x\to y)\land ({\diamond} y\to{\diamond} x)\\ &=& (x\to y)\land ({\diamond} x\to{\diamond} y)\land ({\diamond} y\to{\diamond} x)\\ &=& (x\to y)\land ({\diamond} x\leftrightarrow{\diamond} y), \end{array} \end{align*} $$

$x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } y$ can be read as “x implies y and x is plausible/more credible/likely to be true if and only if y is,” whenever “it is plausible/more credible/likely to be true that x” is meant to satisfy $\blacklozenge 1-\blacklozenge 3$ , and so it can be formalized by ${\diamond }$ . Note that, under such interpretation, the identity

(4.2) $$ \begin{align} x\leq{\diamond} 1 \end{align} $$

seems to be a reasonable assumption once $1$ is meant as an absolutely true statement and so ${\diamond } 1$ can be read as “an absolutely true statement is plausible.” Therefore, if we confine ourselves to consider FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras satisfying (4.2), then Corollary 3.19 states a full equivalence between the connexivity of ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ (cf. page 18).

4.2 On the strength of ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$

Besides having particularly fair motivations, ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ plays a special role for our discussion since it enjoys interesting properties which are not shared by its product-variant ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ . Indeed, the connexivity of ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ can be formulated in a stronger form.

Proposition 4.2. Let ${\mathbf A}$ be an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra. Then $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ satisfies (BT) if and only if it satisfies

(BT*) $$\begin{align} 1\leq(x{\Rightarrow} y){\Rightarrow}[(y{\Rightarrow} z){\Rightarrow}\neg(x{\Rightarrow}\neg z)]. \end{align}$$

Proof. Set . Concerning the left-to-right direction, observe that (BT* ) has the form $1\leq r{\Rightarrow }(s{\Rightarrow } t)$ , for suitable terms $r,s,t$ , which holds iff (i) $r\leq s{\Rightarrow } t$ and (ii) $s{\Rightarrow } t \leq {\diamond } r$ by the definition of ${\Rightarrow }$ . Clearly (i) holds iff $rs\leq t$ and $rt\leq {\diamond } s$ hold, which are verified by simply using Proposition 2.1, the fact that ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}\ \models\ a\to {\diamond } b \approx \neg b\to \neg a $ , and an application of (P3), by Lemma 3.8, via $x{\Rightarrow } z \leq \neg (x{\Rightarrow } \neg z)$ . Moreover, since $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models $ (BT), we have ${\mathbf A}\in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ by Theorem 3.17. The reader can easily verify that $\mathsf {BA}\ \models\ x\leftrightarrow y \approx (x\leftrightarrow z) \wedge (z\leftrightarrow y)$ . Therefore, using the Glivenko property, Lemma 3.16, and the fact that ${\diamond }$ is a nucleus, it follows that property (ii) holds as well. Conversely, setting in (BT* ), we derive $x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } x\leq (x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } z){\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\neg (x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\neg z)$ . Thus (BT) holds since $1\leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } x$ .

We show the above proposition does not hold for ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ with the following example.

Example 4.3. Consider $A=\{\bot ,0,a,b,c,1 \}$ with the lattice order via $\bot <0<b,c<a<1$ . Let $\cdot $ be the commutative operation with unit $1$ described via: For all $x\in A$ , $\bot $ is absorbing; $x\cdot x=x$ for $x\neq 0$ ; $0\cdot x = \bot $ for $x\neq 1$ ; $a\cdot x = x$ for $x=b,c$ ; and $b\cdot c = \bot $ . It is not difficult to show that $\cdot $ is associative and distributes over joins and therefore, by general results (since the lattice is complete), has a residual operation ${\to }$ . Hence ${\mathbf A} = \langle A, \wedge ,\vee ,\cdot ,{\to },0,1 \rangle $ is an integral FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra, which is furthermore verified to be a member of $\mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ . Therefore, by Corollary 3.19 one has that ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ is proto-connexive. However, noting that $\neg c=c{\to } b=b$ , $\neg b=b{\to } c = c$ , and $0{\to } \bot = a$ , the failure of (BT* ) is computed: $(0{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } 1){\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }((1{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } b){\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }\neg (0{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } c))=0{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }(b {\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } \neg \neg c)=0{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }(b{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } c)=0{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } \bot =a\ngeq 1.$

Furthermore, we see that ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ has a privileged status among arrows of the form ${\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }$ which can be defined over an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra by means of an increasing map $\delta $ . In fact, we show below that it is the only operation of this form capable of satisfying connexive theses in the Glivenko variety relative to Boolean algebras.

Proposition 4.4. Let ${\mathbf A} \in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ and $\delta $ be an increasing map on ${\mathbf A}$ . If $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta })\ \models$ (BT) then $\delta = {\diamond }$ .

Proof. By (BT) we have $1\leq (1{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta } x){\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }\neg (1{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }\neg x)$ , and from the definition of ${\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }$ , it follows that $1\leq \neg (1{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }\neg x){\to }\delta (1{\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta } x)$ . Expanding this, we obtain

(*) $$ \begin{align} 1&\leq \neg[(1{\to}\neg x)\land(\neg x{\to}{\delta{1}})]{\to}\delta[(1{\to} x)\land(x{\to}{\delta{1}})]\notag\\ &=\neg[\neg x\land(\neg x{\to}{\delta{1}})]{\to}\delta[x\land(x{\to}{\delta{1}})]. \end{align} $$

Setting , (*) yields $1\leq \neg [\neg 1\land (\neg 1{\to }{\delta {1}})]{\to }\delta [1\land (1{\to }{\delta {1}})]=(0{\to }0){\to }{\delta {1}}$ , hence $0\to 0\leq {\delta {1}}$ . Since ${\mathbf A} \in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ and $0{\to } 0$ is its greatest element, it follows that $0{\to } 0={\delta {1}}$ . So ${\delta {1}}$ is the greatest element of ${\mathbf A}$ , and thus the identity $y\leq y{\to }{\delta {1}}$ , in particular, holds in ${\mathbf A}$ . Using this fact, (*) simplifies to $1\leq \neg \neg x{\to }{\delta {x}}$ , i.e., ${\diamond } x\leq {\delta {x}}$ . Moreover, using the fact that $\delta $ is increasing and ${\delta {1}}$ is the greatest element, it is easily deduced that ${\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }$ also satisfies (AT) as a consequence instantiating of in (BT). As ${\mathbf A} \in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ , from (AT) we conclude

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}[b]{r c l} 1&\leq& \neg(x{\Rightarrow}_{\scriptscriptstyle\wedge}^{\delta}\neg x)\\ &=& \neg((x{\to}\neg x)\land(\neg x{\to}{\delta{x}}))\\ &=&\neg(\neg x\land{\delta{x}})\\ &=&\neg(\neg x\cdot{\delta{x}})\\ &=&{\delta{x}}{\to}{\diamond} x. \end{array}\\[-34pt] \end{align*} $$

As a consequence of the above proposition, we have the following.

Corollary 4.5. Let ${\mathbf A}$ be an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra. Then $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ is proto-connexive if and only if it is the unique binary operation of the form ${\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }$ to be so.

The example below shows neither Proposition 4.4 nor the corollary above hold for ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ .

Example 4.6. Consider the lattice $A = \{\bot < 1 < a < 0 \}$ , where $\cdot $ is commutative and idempotent with unit $1$ , described via $\bot $ being absorbing and $0 \cdot x = 0$ for any $x\neq \bot $ . It is easily checked that $\cdot $ has a residual $\to $ and hence ${\mathbf A} = \langle A,\wedge ,\vee , \cdot ,\to , 0 ,1 \rangle $ is an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra. By Proposition 3.11, ${\Rightarrow }_{\circ }^{\delta }$ is proto-connexive in ${\mathbf A}$ for any map $\delta $ , in particular for ${\diamond }$ . Moreover, specifying $\delta $ to be the map defined via ${\delta {x}}$ is $a$ if $x=a$ , and $0$ otherwise, we see that $\delta $ is increasing (and idempotent) which differs from ${\diamond }$ .

A somewhat suggestive interpretation of the above result comes next. If one wants to expand FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras with a modal operator $\delta $ standing for “being plausible/more credible/likely to be true,” then a reasonable, minimal condition that $\delta $ should satisfy is being increasing, since any true statement should be a fortiori plausible/more credible/likely to be true. Now, if one interprets ${\Rightarrow }_{\wedge }^{\delta }$ as the kind of implication which might appear in Polya’s heuristic syllogism, then it seems reasonable to assume that it satisfies connexive theses. In fact, one might notice that any conjecture A whose truth or falsity is unknown should not have, among its consequences, both a statement B and its negation $\neg B$ on pain of being a priori false, a contradiction. Moreover, it is arguable that conditionals involved in heuristic syllogisms have “epistemically possible” antecedents (cf. page and [Reference Kapsner14]). But then, in the light of Proposition 4.4, $\delta ={\diamond }$ , namely “being plausible/more credible/likely to be true” must be perforce expressed by double negation. Since inquiring into the consequences of the above considerations is beyond the scope of the present work, we postpone them to future investigations.

4.3 On weak connexitivity

In [Reference Wansing and Unterhuber33], a weaker notion of connexivity is formulated. A logic endowed with a binary and a unary connective ${\Rightarrow }$ and ${\sim }$ , respectively, is called weakly connexive if it satisfies Aristotle’s theses and the following two weak versions of Boethius theses:

$$ \begin{align*} A{\Rightarrow} B &\vdash {\sim}(A{\Rightarrow} {\sim} B),\\ A{\Rightarrow} {\sim} B &\vdash {\sim}(A{\Rightarrow} B). \end{align*} $$

Clearly, in the light of Theorem 2.5, the above inference schemas hold in a substructural logic w.r.t. (term defined) connectives ${\Rightarrow }$ and ${\sim }$ if and only if the following quasi-identities, which we call equational weak Boethius theses, hold:

(BTw) $$ \begin{align} \ \ 1\leq x{\Rightarrow} y &\quad\ \ \,\mathsf{implies}\quad 1\leq \neg (x{\Rightarrow} \neg y), \end{align} $$
(BTw') $$ \begin{align} 1\leq x{\Rightarrow} \neg y &\quad\mathsf{implies}\quad1\leq \neg (x{\Rightarrow} y). \end{align} $$

We will use the same naming convention for weak connexivity as in (and in the same spirit of) Definition 3.1 for logics and (classes of) algebras.

Lemma 4.7. For an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra ${\mathbf A}$ and ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } \}$ , the following hold:

  1. 1. $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }) \ \models$ (BTw) iff $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models$ (BTw').

  2. 2. If $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }) \ \models $ (BT) [or (BT’)] then $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })\ \models$ (BTw) and (BTw').

  3. 3. If ${\diamond } {\mathbf A}$ is integral, then $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }) \ \models $ (BT) [or (BT’)] implies $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ })\ \models$ (BTw) and (BTw').

  4. 4. If $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }) \ \models$ (BTw) then $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow })\ \models$ (AT) and (AT’).

Consequently, ${\Rightarrow }$ is weakly connexive for a class $\mathsf {K}$ of ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ -algebras if and only if at least one of the weak Boethius theses holds for ${\Rightarrow }$ in $\mathsf {K}$ .

Proof. Fix ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } \}$ and let $*\in \{\cdot ,\wedge \}$ . First, note that, as a consequence of the first quasi-identity in Proposition 3.5, FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras satisfy the following identity:

(4.3) $$ \begin{align} x{\Rightarrow} y \leq x{\Rightarrow} \neg\neg y. \end{align} $$

Now, for (1), suppose (BTw) holds and let $1\leq x{\Rightarrow } \neg y$ . Then by (BTw), $1\leq \neg (x{\Rightarrow } \neg \neg y)$ . But $\neg (x{\Rightarrow } \neg \neg y) \leq \neg (x{\Rightarrow } y)$ by Equation (4.3), so (BTw') holds. Conversely, suppose (BTw') holds. If $1\leq x{\Rightarrow } y$ , then again by Equation (4.3), so too $1\leq x{\Rightarrow } \neg \neg y$ . Hence by (BTw'), $1\leq \neg (x{\Rightarrow } \neg y)$ .

For (2) and (3), it is sufficient to verify that $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }) \ \models $ (BT) implies $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })\ \models$ (BTw), in light of (1), Lemma 3.8 [for the case of (2)], and Lemma 3.18 [for the case of (3)]. Indeed, suppose $1\leq a:=x{\Rightarrow } y$ . Let $b:=\neg (x{\Rightarrow } \neg y)$ . Then by (BT), using antitonicity of the left argument for ${\to }$ and Prop. 2.3, we find

$$ \begin{align*} 1\leq a{\Rightarrow} b = (a{\to} b)*(b{\to} {\diamond} a)\leq b*(b{\to} {\diamond} a)={\diamond} b * {\diamond}(b{\to} {\diamond} a)\leq {\diamond} b \wedge (b{\to} {\diamond} a)\leq {\diamond} b=b, \end{align*} $$

so (BTw) holds. This completes (2) and (3).

Lastly, (4) is immediate by (1) and the fact $1\leq x{\Rightarrow } x$ and $1\leq \neg x{\Rightarrow } \neg x$ .

The question of whether a converse of Lemma 4.7(2) can be proven naturally rises, namely if weak connexivity is equivalent to connexivity. Unfortunately, the next example shows that, even under the assumption of integrality, the former concept is properly weaker than the latter.

Example 4.8. Consider an arbitrary Heyting algebra ${\mathbf A}=(A,\land ,\lor ,\to ,0,1)$ containing an element $a$ such that $b=\neg a\to a\neq a$ , e.g., a three-element chain with operations defined in the expected way. Let ${\mathbf A}^{*}$ be the algebra obtained from ${\mathbf A}$ by setting $0:=a$ . It is easily seen that ${\mathbf A}^{*}$ is still a pointed commutative residuated lattice with a bottom element $\bot $ satisfying $\land =\cdot $ . Moreover, one has that $1\leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } y$ implies $x\leq y$ and $\neg x=\neg y$ . So $\neg (x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\neg y)=\neg ((x{\to }\neg y)\land (\neg y{\to }{\diamond } x))=\neg (\neg x\land {\diamond } x)=\neg 0 = 1.$ Therefore, ${\mathbf A}^{*}$ satisfies ( BTw ) and, by Lemma 4.7, also ( BTw' ), i.e., ${\mathbf A}^{*}$ is weakly connexive. However, one has also, e.g., $\neg (0{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\bot ) = \neg ((0{\to }\bot )\land (\bot {\to }{\diamond } 0))=b\neq a=((0{\to } 1)\land 1{\Rightarrow }{\diamond } 0)=0{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } 1=0{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\neg \bot $ . Therefore, since ( P3 ) fails, by Lemma 3.8 we have that $({\mathbf A}^{*},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ is not proto-connexive.

However, with the assumption of weakening, Lemma 4.7 and Corollary 3.26 yield the equivalence below. First, for a variety $\mathsf {V}$ of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras and term-definable connective ${\Rightarrow }$ , let us denote by $Q_w(\mathsf {V})$ the quasi-variety axiomatized relative to $\mathsf {V}$ by the equational Aristotle’s and weak Boethius’ theses.

Theorem 4.9. If $\mathsf {K}$ is a class of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{ew}}$ -algebras and ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } \}$ , then ${\Rightarrow }$ is weakly connexive for $\mathsf {K}$ if and only if ${\Rightarrow }$ is proto-connexive for $\mathsf {K}$ . Moreover, for any subvariety $\mathsf {V}\subseteq \mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}$ , $Q_w(\mathsf {V})$ is a variety, namely the variety $\mathsf {V}\ + $ (AT).

Let ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } \}$ and $\mathbf {C}_{\Rightarrow }^{wk}$ be the extension of $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ew}}$ by the weak Boethius’ theses for ${\Rightarrow }$ . By algebraization and the theorem above, this logic is deductively equivalent to the extension of $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ew}}$ by any weak Boethius’ thesis for ${\Rightarrow }$ . Note that $\mathbf {IPL}$ satisfies the weak Boethius theses for ${\Rightarrow }$ since $(\mathsf {HA},{\Rightarrow })\ \models$ (AT). By well-known facts on algebraization, Theorem 4.9 yields the following.

Corollary 4.10. Let ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } \}$ . Then, for any substructural logic $\mathbf {L}$ in the interval between $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ew}}$ and $\mathbf {IPL}$ , $(\mathbf {L},{\Rightarrow })$ is weakly connexive if and only if $(\mathbf {L},{\Rightarrow })$ is connexive. Moreover, every logic between $\mathbf {C}_{\Rightarrow }^{wk}$ and $\mathbf {IPL}$ is connexive for ${\Rightarrow }$ .

Consequently, $\mathbf {C}_{\Rightarrow }^{wk}$ is deductively equivalent to $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ew}}}(\mathbf {CPL})$ .

4.4 On strong connexivity

Lastly, we put our results in the context of what is often referred to in the literature as strong connexivity [Reference Kapsner13, Reference Wansing and Omori32]. A logic is called strongly connexive if it satisfies Aristotle’s and Boethius’ theses w.r.t. a non-symmetric implication and, moreover, satisfies the requirements:

  1. (K1) In no (nontrivial) model, $A{\Rightarrow } \neg A$ is satisfiable (for any A), and in no model, $\neg A{\Rightarrow } A$ is satisfiable (for any A).

  2. (K2) In no (nontrivial) model, $A{\Rightarrow } B$ and $A{\Rightarrow } \neg B$ are simultaneously satisfiable (for any A and B).

Accordingly, let us define a logic to be strongly connexive if it is connexive and satisfies the principles (K1) and (K2). In this way, we also refer to a connective ${\Rightarrow }$ being strongly connexive for some logic.

Now, if ${\mathbf A}$ is an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra in which $0$ is the largest element, both ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ are proto-connexive for ${\mathbf A}$ (see Proposition 3.11). Furthermore, if ${\mathbf A}$ is nontrivial, then (K1) and (K2) are refuted. By the remarks above, we obtain the following.

Proposition 4.11. For the logics $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}}(\mathbf {CPL})$ and $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ei}}}(\mathbf {CPL})$ , both ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ are connexive but not strongly connexive.

It is easily shown that if either (K1) or (K2) is refuted in an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra ${\mathbf A}$ , for either ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ or ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ , then ${\mathbf A}\ \models\ 1\leq 0$ .

Proposition 4.12. Let ${\mathbf A}$ be an FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra.

  1. 1. If $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ is proto-connexive, then it refutes (K1) or (K2) iff ${\mathbf A}\ \models\ x\leq 0$ .

  2. 2. If $({\mathbf A},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ })$ is proto-connexive and it refutes (K1) or (K2), then ${\mathbf A}\ \models\ 1\leq 0$ .

Proof. (1). Concerning the right-to-left direction, note that ${\mathbf A}\ \models\ x\leq 0$ implies that, for any $y\in A$ , one has $1\leq y{\to }\neg y$ and $1\leq \neg y{\to }{\diamond } y$ . So we conclude that $1\leq y{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\neg y$ and so ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ is not strongly connexive over A. Conversely, let us distinguish the following cases:

  1. (i) There exists $x\in A$ such that $1\leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\neg x$ . This means by Lemma 3.7(1), $\neg x=\neg \neg x$ . Since ${\mathbf A}\in \mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ , we have that ${\diamond }{\mathbf A}$ is trivial and so we conclude $x\leq 0$ .

  2. (ii) If there exist $x,y\in A$ such that $1\leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge } y$ and $1\leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\neg y$ , then one has, again by Lemma 3.7(1), $\neg x =\neg y$ and $\neg x =\neg \neg y$ , i.e., $\neg y=\neg \neg y$ . Reasoning as in (i), the desired conclusion follows.

As regards (2), let us distinguish the following cases:

  1. (i) There exists $x\in A$ such that $1\leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }\neg x$ . Then, of course, one has $1\leq x{\Rightarrow }\neg x\leq 0$ .

  2. (ii) If there exist $x,y\in A$ such that $1\leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ } y$ and $1\leq x{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }\neg y$ , then we have

    $$ \begin{align*} 1\leq& (x{\Rightarrow}_{\hspace{-.2em}\circ} y)(x{\Rightarrow}_{\hspace{-.2em}\circ}\neg y)\\ =&(x{\to} y)(y{\to}{\diamond} x)(x{\to}\neg y)(\neg y{\to}{\diamond} x)\\ \leq& (x{\to}\neg x)(\neg x{\to}{\diamond} x) = (x{\Rightarrow}_{\hspace{-.2em}\circ}\neg x). \end{align*} $$
    By the previous case, our claim follows.

Even more, the above results show that, for ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ , the failure of strong connexivity is witnessed exactly by those FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras having the equational Glivenko property with respect to the trivial variety (cf. Section 3.2). As there is no non-trivial algebra in $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}$ in which $0=1$ , Proposition 4.12 yields the following result

Theorem 4.13. Let ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\}$ . Then, for any substructural logic $\mathbf {L}$ in the interval between $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ew}}$ and $\mathbf {IPL}$ , $(\mathbf {L},{\Rightarrow })$ is strongly connexive if and only if $(\mathbf {L},{\Rightarrow })$ is connexive. Moreover, every logic between $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ew}}}(\mathbf {CPL})$ and $\mathbf {IPL}$ is strongly connexive for ${\Rightarrow }$ .

In light of Theorem 4.15 and Theorem 4.13, we are confronted with the surprising fact:

Theorem 4.14. For any logic between $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ew}}$ and $\mathbf {IPL}$ , the conditions of being strongly connexive, connexive, and weakly connexive are equivalently satisfied for both ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ .

As already argued in [Reference Kapsner13, p. 4], a reasonable task to pursue is expressing strong connexivity in the object language itself. To this aim, Kapsner introduces the notion of superconnexivity as the formal alter-ego of strong connexivity, since it reflects the idea that violations of Aristotle’s and Boethius’ theses should be regarded as genuine contradictions whose satisfaction results into triviality. The latter fact can be codified by the following axiom schemas:

  1. SA: $(\varphi \to \neg \varphi ){\to }\psi $ .

  2. SB: $(\varphi \to \psi )\to ((\varphi \to \neg \psi )\to \chi )$ .

Unfortunately, SA and SB lead to triviality under a very narrow set of assumptions (among the others, being closed under substitution). Therefore, one might wonder whether, at least in some cases, strong connexivity is conveyed by less demanding inference rules. And the answer is positive. In fact, in what follows we show that, at least in our framework, strong connexivity can be expressed by means of a simple (indeed very classical!) schema: ex falso quodlibet.

Let us denote by $\mathsf {PC}^{\circ }$ and $\mathsf {PC}^{\land } [=\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})]$ the varieties of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras in which ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ are proto-connexive, respectively. In view of Proposition 4.12, the largest sub-quasivariety $\mathsf {M}^{\circ }$ ( $\mathsf {M}^{\land }$ ) of $\mathsf {PC}^{\circ }$ ( $\mathsf {PC}^{\land }$ ) in whose $1$ -assertional logic ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ ( ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ ) is strongly connexive is axiomatized by the quasi-identity

$$\begin{align*}1\leq 0\quad\mathsf{implies}\quad 1\leq x\end{align*}$$

(or, equivalently, $1\leq 0\quad \mathsf {implies}\quad x=y$ ). Therefore, we have that $\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {M}^{\circ })$ ( $\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {M}^{\land })$ ) can be obtained from $\vdash _{\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {PC}^{\circ })}$ ( $\vdash _{\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {PC}^{\land })}$ ) by adding the explosion schema

(EFQ) $$ \begin{align} 0\vdash\varphi. \end{align} $$

Of course, $\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {M}^{\circ })$ ( $\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {M}^{\land })$ ) is the least $1$ -assertional sub-logic of ${\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {PC}^{\circ })}$ ( ${\mathbf {L}(\mathsf {PC}^{\land })}$ ) for which ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ ( ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ ) is strongly connexive. The above considerations boil down to the following.

Theorem 4.15. Let ${\Rightarrow }\in \{{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }\}$ and $\mathbf {L}$ be a substructural logic such $(\mathbf {L},{\Rightarrow })$ is connexive. Then $(\mathbf {L},{\Rightarrow })$ is strongly connexive iff ( EFQ ) holds in $\mathbf {L}$ .

5 Conclusion and future research

This work has been devoted to a preliminary investigation of term-definable connexive implications in Substructural Logics and their semantic features.

We have shown that the Glivenko variety of ${\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ ( $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}$ , and $\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}$ ) relative to Boolean algebras, provides a suitable semantical environment in which the connectives ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ serve as bonafide connexive implications, and vice versa. Consequently, any axiomatic extension of $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}}(\mathbf {CPL})$ provides a full-fledged connexive logic once the $\{\land ,\lor ,\cdot ,{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge },0,1\}$ -fragment (and, assuming the axiom $\vdash \varphi \to \neg \neg 1$ , the same holds replacing ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ by ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ ) is considered.

We have also argued that these logics provide a suitable framework (resp. semantics) for the logic of plausible inference à la Polya. As it has been remarked in Section 3.3, focusing on ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ does not result in a valuable loss of generality, since in most cases the connexivity of ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ is equivalent to the connexivity of ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ or, at least in the integral case, to the connexivity of any binary operation in the interval $[{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ },{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }]$ . See also Section 4.2.

Finally, we have shown that, in our framework, strong connexivity is codified by (EFQ). Therefore, in some cases, it can be expressed in the object language of a connexive logic by means of an anything but contra-classical inference rule. We see this contribution as a stepping-stone for further investigations of both the connective ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ , in particular, and other (term-defined) implications in residuated lattices and substructural logics in general. For instance, it seems reasonable that the characterization results presented in the work may generalize to the non-commutative case; while other lines to be considered may be the following:

  • Obviously, for any sub-variety $\mathsf {V}$ of the variety $\mathsf {In}{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}$ of involutive (i.e., satisfying $\neg \neg x \approx x$ ) FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras, neither $(\mathsf {V},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge })$ nor $(\mathsf {V},{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ })$ are connexive. Therefore, an interesting task would be investigating term-definable connexive implications in involutive pointed commutative residuated lattices.

  • Due to results obtained so far, ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ and ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\circ }$ fall short of behaving, in general, as suitable connexive implications once an arbitrary FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebra is considered. However, extending the line of research [Reference Gherardi and Orlandelli11, Reference Pizzi23], it is reasonable to wonder if there are modal expansions of FL ${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$ -algebras for which full-fledged connexive implications can be term-defined.

  • Along the stream of research inaugurated by [Reference Wansing30], expansions of residuated lattices with connexive implications and/or unary operations $\sim $ which satisfy connexive theses together with $/$ and $\backslash $ are worthy of investigation.

  • As it has been pointed out in Section 4.3, in some cases (e.g., for extensions of $\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ew}}$ ), weak connexivity is equivalent to (strong!) proto-connexivity. However, as witnessed by Example 4.8, the former concept is properly weaker in the general framework, even for the well-performing connective ${\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge }$ . Therefore, it naturally raises the question if a characterization of algebras admitting weakly connexive implications like the ones investigated in this paper can be provided.

And lastly there is, of course, the naturally risen question of if there is a cut-free sequent calculus for at least the $\{\land ,\lor ,\cdot ,{\Rightarrow }_{\hspace {-.2em}\wedge },0,1\}$ -fragment of $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {e}}}(\mathbf {CPL})$ [ $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ei}}}(\mathbf {CPL})$ or $\mathbf {G}_{\mathbf {FL}_{\mathbf {ew}}}(\mathbf {CPL})$ ]. The problem is obviously strictly connected to finding a cut-free sequent calculus whose equivalent algebraic semantics are $\mathbf {G}_{{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {e}}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ , $\mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ei}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ , and $\mathbf {G}_{\mathsf {FL}_{\mathsf {ew}}}(\mathsf {BA})$ which, to the best of our knowledge, is still missing.

Acknowledgements

The authors gratefully acknowledge the anonymous reviewers for their helpful feedback, as well as Antonio Ledda, Hitoshi Omori, Francesco Paoli, Adam Přenosil, and Sara Ugolini for the insightful discussions on the subjects of the present work.

Footnotes

1 Here we mean that, for any Heyting algebra ${\mathbf A}$ , $x\Rightarrow y\leq x\to y$ , i.e., $\Rightarrow $ strengthens $\to $ . Moreover, by routine calculations: $x\Rightarrow y=(x\to y) \land \neg (\neg \neg y\land \neg x)=(x\to y) \land \neg ((y\lor \neg \neg y)\land \neg x)$ .

2 Typically, “substructural logic” refers to any axiomatic extension of the logic $\mathbf {FL}$ , i.e., the external consequence relation induced by the Full Lambek Calculus $\mathtt {FL}$ without the axiom of exchange (commutativity in the corresponding algebras), where the same algebraization results hold. See [Reference Galatos, Jipsen, Kowalski and Ono9].

3 Cf. [Reference Font8, definition 3.9].

4 ${\diamond } x = {\diamond } x \cdot 1 \leq {\diamond } x\cdot {\diamond } 1 \leq {\diamond }({\diamond } x \cdot {\diamond } 1)={\diamond }(x\cdot 1)={\diamond } x$ .

5 Here, we are implicitly assuming a negation-consistent perspective. However, negation-inconsistent logics with valuable applications to epistemology appear, e.g., in [Reference Mangraviti and Tedder16, Reference Wansing, Schmidt, Pratt-Hartmann, Reynolds and Wansing28]. Such an approach is beyond the scope of this paper, and we leave this study to future work.

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Arieli, O., Avron, A., & Zamansky, A. (2011). Ideal paraconsistent logics. Studia Logica, 99, 3160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blok, W. J., & Pigozzi, D. (1989). Algebraizable Logics. Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, Providence, Rhode Island.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burris, S., & Sankappanavar, H. P. (1981). A Course in Universal Algebra, Graduate Texts in Mathematics. Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buszkowski, W. (1996). Categorial grammars with negative information. In Wansing, H., editor. Negation. A Notion in Focus. Berlin: de Gruyter, pp. 107126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cantwell, J. (2008). The logic of conditional negation. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 49, 245260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fazio, D., Ledda, A., & Paoli, F. (2023). Intuitionistic logic is a connexive logic. Studia Logica.Google Scholar
Fazio, D., & Odintsov, S. P. (2023). An algebraic investigation of the connexive logic $\textsf{C}$ . Studia Logica.Google Scholar
Font, J. (2016). Abstract Algebraic Logic: An Introductory Textbook. London: College Publications.Google Scholar
Galatos, N., Jipsen, P., Kowalski, T., & Ono, H. (2007). Residuated Lattices: An Algebraic Glimpse at Substructural Logics. Studies in Logic and the Foundation of Mathematics, Vol. 151. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Galatos, N., & Ono, H. (2006). Algebraization, parametrized local deduction theorem and interpolation for substructural logics over FL. Studia Logica, 83, 279308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gherardi, G., & Orlandelli, E. (2021). Super-strict implications. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 50(1), 134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Humberstone, L. (2000). Contra-classical logics. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78(4), 438474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kapsner, A. (2012). Strong Connexivity. Thought, 1, 141145.Google Scholar
Kapsner, A. (2022). Connexivity and the pragmatics of conditionals. Erkenntnis, 87, 27452778.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kapsner, A., & Omori, H. (2017). Counterfactuals in Nelson logic. In Proceedings of LORI 2017. Berlin: Springer, pp. 497511.Google Scholar
Mangraviti, F., & Tedder, A. (2023). Consistent theories in inconsistent logics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 52, 11331148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marcos, J. (2005). On negation: Pure local rules. Journal of Applied Logic, 3, 185219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCall, S. (1975). Connexive implication. §29.8. In Anderson, A. R., & Belnap, N. D., editors. Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, Vol. 1. Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 434446.Google Scholar
McCall, S. (2012). A history of connexivity. In Gabbay, D. M., Pelletier, F. J., & Woods, J., editors. Handbook of the History of Logic, Vol. 11. Oxford: North-Holland, pp. 415449.Google Scholar
Paoli, F. (2011). Substructural Logics: A Primer. Heidelberg: Springer.Google Scholar
Pfeifer, N. (2012). Experiments on Aristotle’s thesis: Towards an experimental philosophy of conditionals. The Monist, 95, 223240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pfeifer, N., & Tulkki, L. (2017). Conditionals, counterfactuals, and rational reasoning. An experimental study on basic principles. Minds and Machines, 27, 119165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pizzi, C. (1991). Decision procedures for logics of consequential implication. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 32, 618636.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pizzi, C. (2005). Aristotle’s thesis between paraconsistency and modalization. Journal of Applied Logic, 3(1), 119131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polya, G. (1949). Preliminary remarks on a logic of plausible inference. Dialectica, 3, 2835.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polya, G. (1990). Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning, 2 Vols. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Routley, R. (1978). Semantics for connexive logics. I. Studia Logica, 37, 393412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wansing, H. (2005). Connexive modal logic. In Schmidt, R., Pratt-Hartmann, I, Reynolds, M, and Wansing, H, editors. Advances in Modal Logic, Vol. 5. London: King’s College Publications, pp. 367383.Google Scholar
Wansing, H. (2006). Connexive logic. In Zalta, E. N., editor. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2021 Edition). Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Available from: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/logic-connexive/.Google Scholar
Wansing, H. (2007). A note on negation in categorial grammar. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 13(3), 271286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wansing, H., & Odintsov, S. (2016). On the methodology of paraconsistent logic. In Andreas, H., & Verdée, P., editors. Logical Studies of Paraconsistent Reasoning in Science and Mathematics. Trends in Logic, Vol. 45. Cham: Springer, pp. 175204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wansing, H., & Omori, H. (2019). Connexive logics. An overview and current trends. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 28, 371387.Google Scholar
Wansing, H., & Unterhuber, M. (2019). Connexive conditional logic. Part I. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 28, 567610.Google Scholar
Young, W. (2015). From interior algebras to unital $\ell$ -groups: A unifying treatment of modal residuated lattices. Studia Logica, 103, 265286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1 Basic connexive laws

Figure 1

Figure 1 The Hasse diagram of a pseudo-complemented integral FL${}_{\scriptsize\mbox{e}}$-algebra which does not satisfy (spc) since $\neg 0 \wedge \neg (0{\to } \bot ) = \neg 0 \wedge \neg \bot =1 \wedge 1 = 1\neq 0$.

Figure 2

Table 2 Order-algebraic connexive laws