Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T15:44:10.036Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A TWO-DIMENSIONAL LOGIC FOR TWO PARADOXES OF DEONTIC MODALITY

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 August 2020

MELISSA FUSCO
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY NEW YORK, NY, USA E-mail: mf3095@columbia.edu
ALEXANDER W. KOCUREK
Affiliation:
SAGE SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY CORNELL UNIVERSITY ITHACA, NY, USA E-mail: awk78@cornell.edu

Abstract

In this paper, we axiomatize the deontic logic in Fusco (2015), which uses a Stalnaker-inspired account of diagonal acceptance and a two-dimensional account of disjunction to treat Ross’s Paradox and the Puzzle of Free Choice Permission. On this account, disjunction-involving validities are a priori rather than necessary. We show how to axiomatize two-dimensional disjunction so that the introduction/elimination rules for boolean disjunction can be viewed as one-dimensional projections of more general two-dimensional rules. These completeness results help make explicit the restrictions Fusco’s account must place on free-choice inferences. They are also of independent interest, as they raise difficult questions about how to “lift” a Kripke frame for a one-dimensional modal logic into two dimensions.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Anderson, A. R. (1958). A reduction of deontic logic to alethic modal logic. Mind, 67, 100103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Åqvist, L. (1973). Modal logic with subjunctive conditionals and dispositional predicates. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2(1), 176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, C. (2010). Free choice permission as resource-sensitive reasoning. Semantics and Pragmatics, 3, 138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, P., de Rijke, M., & Venema, Y. (2002). Modal Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bledin, J. (2015). Modus ponens defended. Journal of Philosophy, 112(2), 5783.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess, J. (1999). Which modal logic is the right one? Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 40, 8193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carr, J. (2014). The If $P$ , Ought $\;P\;$ problem. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 95(4), 555583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. (2004). Epistemic two-dimensional semantics. Philosophical Studies, 118, 153226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. (2012). Constructing the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Crossley, J., & Humberstone, L. (1977). The logic of ‘actually’. Reports on Mathematical Logic, 8, 1129.Google Scholar
Davies, M., & Humberstone, L. (1980). Two notions of necessity. Philosophical Studies, 38(1), 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dayal, V. (1996). Locality in Wh-quantification: Questions and Relative Clauses in Hindi. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dayal, V. (2016). Questions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fox, D. (2007). Free choice disjunction and the theory of scalar implicatures. In Sauerland, U. and Stateva, P., editors. Presupposition and Implicature in Compositional Semantics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Fritz, P. (2014). What is the correct logic of necessity, actuality and apriority? Review of Symbolic Logic, 7(3), 385414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fusco, M. (2015). Deontic modality and the semantics of choice. Philosophers’ Imprint, 15(28), 127.Google Scholar
Fusco, M. (2019). Naturalizing deontic logic: Indeterminacy, diagonalization, and self-affirmation. Philosophical Perspectives, 32, 165187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fusco, M. (2020a). Free choice effects and exclusive disjunction. Inquiry, 115. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2020.1758768.Google Scholar
Fusco, M. (2020b). A two-dimensional logic for diagonalization and the a priori. Synthese, 116. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02574-7.Google Scholar
Gregory, D. (2001). Completeness and decidability results for some propositional modal logics containing “actually” operators. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 30(1), 5778.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1982). Semantic analysis of Wh-complements. Linguistics and Philosophy, 5, 172233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, C., & Hedden, B. (2016). Self-reinforcing and self-frustrating decisions. Noûs, 50(3), 604628.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, J., & Magidor, O. (2009). Assertion, context, and epistemic accessibility. Mind, 118(470), 377397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hazen, A. P., Rin, B. G., & Wehmeier, K. F. (2013). Actuality in propositional modal logic. Studia Logica, 101, 487503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heim, I. (2004). Lecture notes on indexicality. Notes for class taught at MIT.Google Scholar
Holliday, W., Icard, T., & Hoshi, T. (2013). Information dynamics and uniform substitution. Synthese, 190(Suppl 1), 3155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Humberstone, L. (2004). Two-dimensional adventures. Philosophical Studies, 118, 1765.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Humberstone, L. (2020). Sentence connectives in formal logic. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ spr2020/entries/connectives-logic/.Google Scholar
Kamp, H. (1971). Formal properties of ‘now’. Theoria, 377, 227273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamp, H. (1973). Free choice permission. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 74, 5774.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kanger, S. (1971). New foundations for ethical theory. In Hilpinen, R., editor. Deontic Logic: Introductory and Systematic Readings. Dordrecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel, pp. 36–58.Google Scholar
Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In Almog, J., Perry, J., and Wettstein, H., editors. Themes from Kaplan. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 481–563.Google Scholar
Kaufmann, M. (2016). Free choice is a form of dependence. Natural Language Semantics, 24, 247290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratzer, A. (1977). What must and can must and can mean. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1(3), 337355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratzer, A. (1981). The notional category of modality. In Eikmeyer, H.-J. and Rieser, H., editors. Words, Worlds, and Context. de Gruyter, 3874.Google Scholar
Kratzer, A. (1986). Conditionals. Chicago Linguistics Society, 22(2), 115.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1982). Whether report. In Pauli, T., editor. Philosophical Essays Dedicated to Lennart Åqvist on His Fiftieth Birthday. Uppsala: University of Uppsala Press, pp. 194206.Google Scholar
MacFarlane, J., & Kolodny, N. (2010). Ifs and oughts. Journal of Philosophy, 107, 115143.Google Scholar
McNamara, P. (2010). Deontic logic. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/logic-deontic/.Google Scholar
Meredith, C. A., & Prior, A. N. (1965). Modal logic with functorial variables and a contingent constant. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 6, 99109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Paul, L. A. (2014). Transformative Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paul, L. A. (2015). What you can’t expect when you’re expecting. Res Philosophica, 92(2), 149170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roelofsen, F. (2019). Semantic theories of questions. In Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Linguistics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ross, A. (1941). Imperatives in logic. Theoria, 7(1), 5371.Google Scholar
Segerberg, K. (1973). Two-dimensional modal logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2(1), 7796.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simons, M. (2005). Dividing things up: The semantics of Or and the modal/Or interaction. Natural Language Semantics, 13, 271316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smiley, T. (1982). The schematic fallacy. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 83, 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1975). Indicative conditionals. In Stalnaker, R. Context and Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 63–77.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. In Stalnaker, R. Context and Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 7895.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1981). Indexical belief. Synthese, 49(1), 129151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1977). The only necessity is verbal necessity. Journal of Philosophy, 74, 7185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Veltman, F. (1996). Defaults in update semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic , 25, 221261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlach, F. (1973). ‘Now’ and ‘Then’: A Formal Study in the Logic of Tense Anaphora. Ph.D. thesis, UCLA.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2013). Modal Logic as Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yalcin, S. (2007). Epistemic modals. Mind, 116, 9831026.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yalcin, S. (2015). Actually, actually. Analysis, 75(2), 185191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar