Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T22:20:24.338Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Knowledge of Counterfactuals

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 May 2009

Timothy Williamson
Affiliation:
New College, Oxford

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, A. R. (1951) “A note on subjunctive and counterfactual conditionals”, Analysis 12, 35–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, R. M. J. (2005) The Rational Imagination: How People Create Alternatives to Reality. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. J. (2006) “The foundations of two-dimensional semantics”, in García-Carpintero, M. and Macià, J., eds., Two-Dimensional Semantics, Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, J., Hall, N., and Paul, L. A. (2004) Causation and Counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: M.I.T. Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Currie, G. (1995) “Visual imagery as the simulation of vision”, Mind and Language 10, 1744.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, M. and Stone, T. (eds.) (1995) Mental Simulation: Evaluation and Applications. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Edgington, D. (2003) “Counterfactuals and the Benefit of Hindsight”, Causation and Counterfactuals, (eds.) Dowe, P. and Noordhof, P.. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Evans, J. St. B. T., and Over, D. E. (2004) If. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. (1992) “Empathy, mind and morals”, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 66/3, 1741.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, N. (1954) Fact, Fiction and Forecast. London: Athlone Press.Google Scholar
Harris, P. (2000) The Work of the Imagination. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. (1977) “A causal theory of counterfactuals”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 55, 321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D., and Tversky, A. (1982) “The simulation heuristic”, in Judgement under Uncertainty, (eds.) Kahneman, D., Slovic, P. and Tversky, A.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. K. (1973) “Causation”, Journal of Philosophy 70, 556–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. K. (1979) “Counterfactual dependence and time's arrow”, Noûs 13, 455476.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. K. (1986) Counterfactuals, revised edn.Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McKinsey, M. (1991) “Anti-individualism and privileged access”, Analysis 51, 916.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S., and Stich, S. P. (2003) Mindreading: An Integrated Account of Pretence, Self-Awareness, and Understanding of Other Minds. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S., Stich, S. P., Leslie, A., and Klein, D. (1996) “Varieties of off-line simulation”, in Theories of Theories of Mind, (eds.) Carruthers, P. and Smith, P. K.. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. A. B. (1985) “Imagination, experience and possibility”, in Essays on Berkeley: A Tercentennial Celebration, (eds.) Foster, J. and Robinson, H.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. (1978) Foundations: Essays in Philosophy, Logic, Mathematics and Economics, (ed.) Mellor, D. H.. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Roese, N. J., and Olson, J. (1993) “The structure of counterfactual thought”, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 19, 312–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roese, N. J., and Olson, J. (1995) “Functions of counterfactual thinking”, in What Might Have Been: The Social Psychology of Counterfactual Thinking, (eds.) Roese, N. J. and Olson, J. M.. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1968) “A theory of conditionals”, in American Philosophical Quarterly Monographs 2 (Studies in Logical Theory), 98112.Google Scholar
Williams, B. (1966) “Imagination and the self”, Proceedings of the British Academy 52, 105124.Google Scholar
Williamson, T. (2007) The Philosophy of Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yablo, S. (2002) “Coulda, woulda, shoulda”, in Conceivability and Possibility, (eds.) Gendler, T. S. and Hawthorne, J.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar