Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T22:04:03.560Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Persistence and Determination1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 June 2008

Extract

Roughly speaking, perdurantism is the view that ordinary objects persist through time by having temporal parts, whilst endurantism is the view that they persist by being wholly present at different times. (Speaking less roughly will be important later.) It is often thought that perdurantists have an advantage over endurantists when dealing with objects which appear to coincide temporarily: lumps, statues, cats, tail-complements, bisected brains, repaired ships, and the like. Some cases – personal fission, for example – seem to involve temporary coincidence between objects of the same kind. Other cases – a cat and its flesh, a statue and its lump – seem to involve objects of different kinds.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Balashov, (1999): ‘Relativistic Objects’, Noûs, 33: 644662.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balashov, (2000): ‘Persistence and Space-Time: Philosophical Lessons of the Pole and Barn’, Monist, 83: 321–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, Karen (2004): ‘Global Supervenience and Dependence’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 68: 501–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Black, Max (1952): ‘The Identity of Indiscernibles’, Mind, 61: 153164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Effingham, Nikk (2007): On the Restricted Composition of Material Objects, University of Leeds Ph.D. thesis.Google Scholar
Gibson, Ian and Pooley, Oliver (2006): ‘Relativistic Persistence’, Philosophical Perspectives 20: 157196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, John (2006): ‘Three-Dimensionalism’, in his Metaphysical Essays, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawley, Katherine (2005): ‘Fission, Fusion and Intrinsic Facts’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71.3: 602621.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirsch, Eli (2002): ‘Quantifier Variance and Realism’, Philosophical Issues, 12: 5173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langford, Simon (2007): ‘How to Defend the Cohabitation Theory’, Philosophical Quarterly, 57: 212224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David (1983): ‘Survival and Identity: Postscript’ in his Philosophical Papers vol. 1, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lowe, E.J. (2002): ‘Material Coincidence and the Cinematographic Fallacy: a Reply to Olson’, Philosophical Quarterly, 52: 369–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markosian, Ned (1998): ‘Simples’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76: 213226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGrath, Matthew (2007): ‘Four-Dimensionalism and the Puzzles of Coincidence’, Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 3, edited by Zimmerman, Dean: 143176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Kristie (2005): ‘The Metaphysical Equivalence of Three and Four Dimensionalism’, Erkenntnis, 62.1: 91117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Leary-Hawthorne, John (1995): ‘The Bundle Theory of Substance and the Identity of Indiscernibles’, Analysis, 55: 191–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parsons, Josh (2000): ‘Must a Four-Dimensionalist believe in Temporal Parts?’, Monist, 83.3: 399418.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W.V.O. (1976): ‘Grades of DiscriminabilityJournal of Philosophy, 73: 113–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan (forthcoming): ‘On What Determines What’Google Scholar
Shagrir, Oron (2002): ‘Global Supervenience, Coincident Entities and Anti-Individualism’, Philosophical Studies, 109: 171–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, Theodore (2001): Four-Dimensionalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, Theodore (forthcoming): ‘Yet Another Paper on the Supervenience Argument against Coincident Entities’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.Google Scholar
Wasserman, Ryan (2002): ‘The Standard Objection to the Standard Account’, Philosophical Studies 111: 197216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar