Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-b6zl4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-08T15:46:38.227Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Qualia and Ontology: Language, Semiotics, and Materiality; an Introduction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2025

Lily Chumley*
Affiliation:
New York University
*
Contact Lily Chumley at Dept. of Media, Culture, and Communication, 239 Greene Street, 8th Floor, New York, NY 10003 (chumley@nyu.edu).
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Qualia—sensory experiences of abstract qualities such as heat, texture, color, sound, stink, hardness, and so on—focus attention on prototypically “material” entities. But how is the ontological category of materiality constituted by conventional qualities, or qualisigns? For instance, how does the sound made by knuckles knocking on a table come to be an exemplary experience of, and a conventional sign for, “materiality”? What ontologies might undermine the seeming naturalness of this category, and to what effect? This issue contributes to the growing literature on semiotic approaches to materiality by arguing that attention to qualia, as sensorial and somatic experiences mediated by cultural qualisigns of value (Munn 1986), offers a useful analytic approach to the dialectics of matter (substrate, affordance) and nonmatter (idea, concept, category). The articles in this issue describe how modes of being and becoming are represented in and organized by discourses on qualia and demonstrate the crucial role of qualia and qualisigns in “ontological politics” (Mol 1999).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2017 by Semiosis Research Center at Hankuk University of Foreign Studies. All rights reserved.

Of the first philosophers the majority thought that the causes in the form of matter were alone the principles of all things. The thinkers in question were after the truth about the things that are. But they supposed the things are to be restricted to the sensibles.

—Aristotle, Metaphysics

Contemporary anthropological theory is profoundly concerned with the thing-in-itself. The ontological turn, which began with ethnographies of Amazonian worlds, links to an environmentalist concern to theorize “other kinds of realities beyond us” (Kohn Reference Kohn2014), an us that might refer to modern, Western, or otherwise privileged subjectivities, to the human species, or to sentient life forms generally.Footnote 1 Likewise, the literature on materiality, which emerged in part from science and technology studies and from the anthropology of commodities,Footnote 2 has lately been concerned with the “affordances” of things-in-the-world: those aspects of stuff and things that lie beyond and below human capacities of representation (see, e.g., Miller Reference Miller2005). Under the banners of ontology and materiality scholars in the humanities and social sciences have increasingly turned their focus toward nonhuman entities: inanimate stuff and things (Povinelli Reference Povinelli1995; Harman Reference Harman1999; Hull Reference Hull2012; Manning Reference Manning2012); other animals and plants, especially dogs (Haraway Reference Haraway2003, Reference Haraway2008; Kohn Reference Kohn2014) but also poultry (Kockelman Reference Kockelman2011), pigs (Blanchette Reference Blanchette2013) and fungi (Tsing Reference Tsing2015); infrastructures (e.g., Bear Reference Bear2007; Elyachar Reference Elyachar2010, Reference Engels2012; Parks and Starosielski Reference Parks and Starosielski2015); architectures (e.g., Fennell Reference Fennell2016), global assemblages (Ong and Collier Reference Ong and Collier2005; Tsing Reference Tsing2005), algorithms (Kockelman Reference Kockelman2013; Maurer Reference Maurer2013b), and massively distributed “hyperobjects” such as climate change (Morton Reference Morton2013) and pollution (Lai Reference Lai2014; Voyles Reference Voyles2015).

These scholars echo Engels (Reference Engels and Dutt1940; see also Vygotsky Reference Vygotsky2012, 96–98) in calling into question the original subject-object of social science: the culture-bound human, set apart from animals and their natural instincts by the tendency to generate and obey the “rules” of kinship systems and language.Footnote 3 It bears repeating that the human/animal distinction has always been a way of organizing legal, political, and economic relations in which “humanity” serves as an ostensibly absolute value but systematically excludes people not treated as human (e.g., Spillers Reference Spillers1987, 79) and those whose value is not considered absolute (Ralph Reference Ralph2015). The literatures on ontology and materiality share a welcome interest in finding alternative foundations for ethics and politics (Keane Reference Keane2013, Reference Keane2015; Povinelli Reference Povinelli2016). We don’t have to be willing to attribute volition to nonsentient beings, as in the “bridge that wants to sell itself to you” (Kafka Reference Kafka2015) to develop a more nuanced and less “human”-centered account of will, intention, and behavior. To ask, “What is it like to be a bat?” (Nagel Reference Nagel1974) is to accept that qualia are not unmediated reflections of the world as it is. But neither can qualia be attributed to the perceptual mechanisms of the species: seemingly “material” objects (including people’s bodies) can appear quite different to “others,” even within our own communities (Stasch Reference Stasch2009; Rosa Reference Rosa2016), and such perceptions are formed in and by institutions and cosmologies (Houtman and Meyer Reference Houtman and Meyer2012; Flores and Rosa Reference Flores and Rosa2015).

However, if the literature on ontology has resisted the sanctity of “the human,” the literature on materiality has not always resisted the sanctity of “the real,” a category of equal political significance (as Galloway [2013] argues). Many of the theorists cited above declaim any simple binary opposition of material and immaterial; however, this opposition continues to inform the uptake of their work (as Keane [Reference Keane2003] points out). Materiality has frequently been posited as a corrective to an alleged idealist bias in the academy: an excessive concern with human modes of perception and apperception and the discourses, texts, and signs that mediate them.Footnote 4 Insofar as studies of materiality are organized around non-speaking subjects, some forgo the examination of interactional text in favor of ethnographically thick descriptions of commonsense objects—or, in the case of relatively arcane objects and substances, reported descriptions by authorial others who have access to the equipment needed to encounter forms of matter too large or too small for the built-in perceptual mechanisms of the average scholar in the social sciences. In both cases, of course, the noumenon remains embedded in linguistic categories, multimodal representations, discourse, and text, suggesting the need for a linguistically informed semiotic analysis. If the urgency of climate change, among other things, suggests a need for a detente with positivists (Latour Reference Latour2004), our empiricism must be “skeptical and ethical” (Rutherford Reference Rutherford2012), and our understanding of perception cannot be methodologically individualist (Burge Reference Burge2010). Epistemological naturalism (Quine Reference Quine1968) can nevertheless avoid naturalizing and essentializing discourses, which leverage ontological claims of materiality into political claims for inevitability (Irvine and Gal Reference Irvine, Gal and Kroskrity2000).

Recognizing this problem, scholars in linguistic anthropology have demonstrated the relevance of language and semiotics, and emergent “interactional text,” to the study of the material world.Footnote 5 Peircean semiotics, as both metaphysics and epistemology, reconfigures any simple binary distinction between phenomena (sensation, perception) and noumena (the unmediated really-real, referent) as an irreduceably triadic relationship of sign, object, interpretant; qualisign, sinsign, legisign; rheme, dicent, argument; and firstness, secondness, thirdness.Footnote 6 Peircean semiotics does not presume systematicity or intentionality, though it can incorporate both; the semiotic process by which signs generate signs has frequently been described with crystalline metaphors; both Irvine and Gal (Reference Irvine, Gal and Kroskrity2000) and Deleuze (Reference Deleuze, Tomlinson and Habberjam[1983] 1986) make use of the metaphor of fractal, crystalline growth to describe emergent meaning in interaction and cinema, respectively.

Peircean semiotics as a model is highly ontologically flexible: signs, objects, and interpretants may be prototypically “material” or “immaterial” (or, for that matter, “real” and “imaginary,” “concrete” and “abstract,” as Kockelman [Reference Kockelman2006] demonstrates). Porcelain might be a sign of monarchical power for a royal house (Gal, this issue), and brands a sign of elite status for YouTube comedy video viewers (Reyes, this issue). Interpretants—which assert a relation between a sign and an object—need not be human thoughts or behaviors; as Kohn (Reference Kohn2015) and Kockelman (Reference Kockelman2011) have argued, this model is useful for describing the ways that other species are responsive to forms of signification “as in consequentiality, as in effects and effectiveness of semiotic practice as [social] action” (Silverstein Reference Silverstein2013, 329). Peircean semiotics is highly scaleable, adaptive to massive system-level phenomena and to small-scale nuances in interaction (see Silverstein Reference Silverstein and Sanders2006; Bloomaert Reference Blommaert2015; Carr and Lempert Reference Carr and Lempert2016). Time-spaces (chronotopes) shift over semiotic process, as interpretants are converted into new signs, linked together in infinite chains. To take the case of “wastelanding” (Voyles 2015), for example, burnt feet can signify massive long-term widespread uranium pollution for an interpreting environmental scientist or activist and to their audiences. Conversely, uranium pollution can signify systematic geographic racism for the interpreting ethnographer: “Wastelanding reifies—it makes real, material, lived—what might otherwise be only discursive. Like race, which is a social construction made material by the embodied consequences of racism … ideas about the value of environments are manifested by the material consequences of environmental destruction.” (Voyles 2015, 10). This sentence converts a moment of insight, itself converted into a new sign (field notes perhaps), into yet another sign—the published book—for a new interpretant—the reader—and finally into this description: this is a chain of signification. The process of materialization Voyles describes is itself made up of such chains of signification: discourse is not turned into matter all at once, like straw into gold, but rather discourse and matter dialectically refract through one other over ritual and historical space-times (see Manning [Reference Manning2012] for liquid examples and Moore [Reference Moore2013] for visual ones).

Building on the foundation of semiotic anthropology, the essays collected here demonstrate the productivity of the concepts of “qualia” and “qualisign” (Munn Reference Munn1986; Parmentier Reference Parmentier1994; Chumley and Harkness Reference Chumley and Harkness2013; Harkness Reference Harkness2015) for what Annemarie Mol called “a semiotic analysis of the way reality is done” (Reference Mol, Law and Hassard1999). Each essay shows how qualia expressed in qualisigns (descriptive and evaluative terms and other meta-signs) serve as grounds for “naturalized kinds,” (Kripke Reference Kripke, Davidson and Harman1972; Putnam Reference Putnam1975; Burge Reference Burge1979; Reyes Reference Reyes2007; Harkness Reference Harkness2013; Ball Reference Ball2014) framed by languages, registers, practices, knowledges, and technologies. In each of these cases, qualia and qualisigns invoke ontological categories (real/unreal, material/immaterial, bodily/mental, etc.) with social consequences. Each essay thus provides a semiotic analysis of the ways that qualia figure in “various performance of reality” (Mol Reference Mol, Law and Hassard1999), demonstrating the significance of qualia for ontological politics, which Mol outlined in the questions, “What is at stake?”; “Are there options?”; “How to choose?”; and “Who gets to choose?”

In this introduction, I offer a framework for these essays, first, by describing the relationship of ontology to languages of qualia (or named/conventionalized qualisigns); second, by considering how an ethnographic approach grounded in qualia frames the question of materiality; third, by offering an example of how a semiotics of qualia might operate as an ontological politics; and, finally, by tracing the links between the arguments in the collected essays.

Ontology, Language, and the Work of Theory

In the essay “Carnap’s Views on Ontology” (Reference Quine1966), Quine defines the “ontological commitments of a theory” as “What, according to that theory, there is”: “what entities there are from the point of view of a given language.” Commitment to entities of any sort comes through the variables of quantification (all, any, none, some, etc.), not the mere use of names (reference/referring expressions).Footnote 7 But of course, “to discern what entities a given theory presupposes is one thing, and … to determine what entities there really are, is another” (Reference Quine1966). In the division of academic labor the first task has historically been our job as anthropologists: we describe the entities that people “believe in,” or behave toward, translating and transfiguring multiple ontologies, while engaging the ethical paradoxes and politics of radical interpretation.Footnote 8 In this frame anthropologists serve as “diplomats” for ontological and metaphysical multiplicity (Kohn Reference Kohn2015) in part by translating “language” (grammatical categories, words, discourses, genres, registers, voices, writing systems, etc.), assuming in and through such acts of translation that other ontologies are not impenetrable barriers (see Quine Reference Quine1968; Davidson Reference Davidson1973) and should not be Otherizing stigmas (see McWhorter Reference McWhorter2014). As language is one of the forms of signification crucial to the formation of somatic and phenomenal experience—not least because in naming such experience as color, taste, and so on, we map some feature of one kind of sensation (the hardness of tables, say) onto another kind of entity (the hardness of sciences).Footnote 9 Consequently, insofar as qualia play a key role in ontological discourse, anyone engaged in the anthropological work of describing the entities to which people are committed must be attentive to language, as one of the “technologies of transaction that afford ontological transformation” (Maurer Reference Maurer2013a, 70).

The job of deciding what things there are really, on the other hand, has been assigned by positivists to natural scientists, especially physicists and chemists, and to a lesser degree psychologists and quantitative sociologists.Footnote 10 However, social scientists, including anthropologists, have also made commitments to all sorts of entities: not just culture and social facts, but hau, praxis, dividual, chronotope, subjectivity, actant, rhematization, dicentization. Theories commit us to entities that are not in any conventional sense material, not just theoretically but personally and professionally; indeed, just as in the Tlingit economy of names (Roth Reference Roth2009), academics rely on the ownership and restricted presentation of such words. Nevertheless, our ontological commitments are always up for “revision and retention” (Quine Reference Quine1966), constructed analogically when we set ethnographies of disparate and distant sites against each other to occasion similarities and differences: through the forms of translation and transfiguration that set, for instance, Melanesian categories of gender and person against Western feminist ones (Strathern Reference Strathern1988).

Ontology, whether as first-order truth claims or second-order accounts of the theoretical commitments of other truth claims, operates as a metalanguage, distinguishing existential quantifications from mere propositions. If ethnographies offer propositions regarding ontologies, theory offers ontological claims for the academic community, investing certain signs with the power of denotation (see Russell Reference Russell1905; Strawson Reference Strawson1950): the referential efficacy emphasized by qualifiers such as “literally” and “in a very real sense.” Such denotations are always, in discourse (or interactional text), complexly mediated by referring expressions. In social theory as in social life, the invocation of categories depends on chains of references from “baptismal events,” within a linguistic division of labor (Kripke Reference Kripke, Davidson and Harman1972; Putnam Reference Putnam1973). In committing to (or quantifying over) qualia we are not just talking about ontology but also doing it.

Categories, Properties, and Differentia

Categories, concepts, and qualities materialize: they are manifested in and through substrates such as paper, light, sound waves, particulate matter, fabric—or proprioceptively, within the body—for instance, as it is trained to produce beautiful sounds (Harkness, this issue) and as it is subjected to speed and slowness and threats of violence (Yeh, this issue). Insofar as such materializations are perceived sensorially they are qualia; insofar as they manifest ethnographically they are significations. Just as gold (or for that matter, cloth or shells) only becomes money in certain social relations, formations of atoms and energy signify as objects only in relation to particular interpretants—as porcelain might seem a technological miracle in the late Renaissance and a charming artisanal craft in the late twentieth century (see Gal, this issue).

Material objects appear to subjects as properties and differentia embedded in substrates. Aristotle (Reference McKeon1947) describes matter as substrate—a bearer or carrier of signifying properties and differentia (as the molecular structure of playdough carries the socially relevant properties of squishiness and yellowness), categories of which any particular object is always a by-degrees inadequate instantiation of the ideal type. By contrast, for Kripke, objects have social lives, in which they are “rigidly designated” by names or rigid designators (including anaphora) passed on link-to-link through discourse—and though objects might have various properties or qualities or differences with other things, they are always malleable and changeable. Gal’s article in this issue provides an example of a particularly long chain in which a sequence of names designate a “thing”—blue and white porcelain—that changes its substrates multiple times, while “retaining” some key properties that are nevertheless transformed as they pass over centuries and through identities dependent on historical, political, and economic circumstances. Porcelain as mundane dishware in Ming dynasty China takes on in Europe the significance of a mystical and mysterious transubstantiation of rough, wet, dirty clay into pristine, hard, white cleanliness. This article, along with Angie Reyes’s in this issue on the formation true conyo elite consumer as a “natural kind,” highlights the reflexive and relative existence of the commodity form as understood by Marx: complex social relations concatenized as apparently material properties inherent to objects.

Since the relative form of value of a commodity—the linen, for example—expresses the value of that commodity, as being something wholly different from its substance and properties, as being, for instance, coat-like, we see that this expression itself indicates that some social relation lies at the bottom of it. With the equivalent form it is just the contrary. The very essence of this form is that the material commodity itself—the coat—just as it is, expresses value, and is endowed with the form of value by Nature itself. Of course this holds good only so long as the value relation exists, in which the coat stands in the position of equivalent to the linen. Since, however, the properties of a thing are not the result of its relations to other things, but only manifest themselves in such relations, the coat seems to be endowed with its equivalent form, its property of being directly exchangeable, just as much by Nature as it is endowed with the property of being heavy, or the capacity to keep us warm.

(Marx Reference Marx and Engels1906, 66)

Such properties have been, in the fields of science and technology studies described as “affordances,” inherent material features that are key to their use value: the wool to keep warm, the alcohol to get us drunk (Manning Reference Manning2012; Harkness Reference Harkness2013). But as Aristotle (Reference McKeon1947; and for that matter, Reference Zhuangzi and LeggeZhuangzi, n.d.) argued a long time ago, things are not just what they are, they are also what they are not. Very good wine (Silverstein Reference Silverstein2013) and knockoff brand clothes (Nakassis Reference Nakassis2016), among other forms of materiality, are experienced as differentia, or contrasts, with the other less well-bred (or less stylish) things that might have taken their place (Bourdieu Reference Bourdieu and Nice[1979] 1984). Jakobson, following Saussure, called this the “axis of selection” (Reference Jakobson and Sebeok1960); Inoue (Reference Inoue2003), following Derrida and Butler, describes this as the absent “supplements” or proximate forms from which any present sign derives its meaning. It is not necessary to indulge in counterfactual thought experiments to activate other possible worlds (Kripke 1980); our phenomenal experience is drenched in and organized by its alternatives, and it is these alternatives that organize the design of our photographic representations of reality (see Ball, this issue). Nor are categories and differentia specific to human subjectivity: a cat responds differently to a can of cat food, a mouse, a vacuum cleaner, and a rubber band, behaviors that a human might interpret as indexes of cat categories (food, prey, threat, and toy) and cat qualia (succulence, chaseability, danger), distinguished from one another as properties and differentia. We do not need to assume that qualia emerge late in evolutionary history either: a paramecium responds differently to light and dark, behavior that—to the observing scientist—indexes evolved stimulus-response mechanisms (Greenspan Reference Greenspan2007).

In this way, perceived or experienced qualia—redness, hotness, smoothness, roughness—link unlike and distant objects across scales, chronotopes, and sensory modalities, such as the pharonic pyramids in Egypt and the pyramid in Las Vegas (Meskell Reference Meskell and Miller2005). Qualia such as “softness” are articulated synaesthetically, through qualic transitivity (Harkness Reference Harkness2013, 2014). Socially significant categories, such as “eliteness” (Reyes, this issue), are frequently generated through laminations or intersections of qualia and qualisigns of value (Munn Reference Munn1986). Likewise, ontological categories—or modes of being and becoming—are generated in and through semiotic forms, from the signature of a particle (Roy, this issue) to the realism of a photograph (Ball, this issue). A case in point is the slippery category of “materiality,” which, as theory, assumes the solidity, gravitas, and transparency of the really-real.

Materiality and Ontology

Materiality as a concept hangs between the physicists’ scale-transcending concept of “matter” and the endemically scalar concept of “thing”: for the matter that matters depends on the size of the interpretant and its modes of perception, even if aided by telescopes and microscopes (Nagel Reference Nagel1974). Shibboleths of perceptibility are highly scale-dependent, as illustrated by the many episodes of Star Trek that involve wandering your giant spaceship into a being you didn’t notice because it was too big. Starting from the assumption of ontological multiplicity implies that ethnographers and others recognize (1) the possibility that the things you see, smell and touch are not particularly important to “others” and (2) the possibility that the most salient entities for others in the situation are invisible or intangible, unreal or non material to you.

“Tickets, timetables, buildings, lists, rooms”: these are all what Quine called “common-sense objects,” of the sort that figure in descriptions of props and sets of the ethnographic scene. But as many scholars of the Anthropocene have emphasized, “tables and sheep are, in the last analysis, on the same footing as molecules and electrons” (Quine Reference Quine1966). Both are apprehended through complex modes of perception, categorization, and discourse—though as Roy shows in this issue the tools involved in the latter case are considerably more elaborate. The ontological turn in anthropology urges attention to the categories of being and becoming invoked in discourses and practices, suggesting that we ought to avoid deciding in advance what is material or real and, to that end, avoid the methodological nominalism sometimes implicit in the use of “materiality” as a theory term. To bridge this gap, it is helpful to show how qualia and qualisigns synaesthetically tranfer from visible/invisible and tangible/intangible entities, while also circulating (Silverstein Reference Silverstein2013, 334) across semiotics chains of phenomenological encounters and communicative events. Attention to qualisigns as they appear in ontological discourses about entities, substances, and processes of transformation and change provides one technique for articulating the multiple relationships of ontologically distinct entities as sign process.

Consider Teri Silvio’s (Reference Silvio2010) theorization of cosplay and related fields of contemporary mediated practice as “animation” rather than performance. To understand these (admittedly elaborate) costumes and masks, she points out, is to recognize that these masks are ways of “animating” a figure that is always elsewhere and multiple: the character (Nozawa Reference Nozawa2013) as a composite of moe elements (Azuma Reference Azuma, Abel and Kono2009). To focus on the common sense objects here and not the abstract and spectacular ones would be like mistaking the cards for the Pokemon. From imaginary weapons in the hands of unarmed people (Rosa Reference Rosa2016) and financial instruments (Maurer Reference Maurer and Miller2005), ancient Chinese burial sites (Lai Reference Lai2015), or the Thai ghosts that appear as energy (Cassaniti Reference Cassaniti2015), tangible forms are only made significant by their relation to intangible ones (and vice versa, across multiple sensory modalities—visible, audible, tasteable, smellable). Attention to qualia allows us to recognize the ways that iconic and indexical signs configure modes of being and becoming.

Language and Ontological Politics

Anyway, a rap on the knuckles is surely earned by anyone who, perceiving things to be thus in what is in any case the statistical exception even of sensibles, extrapolates to the entire universe. Our little corner of the observable universe is unique in its constant exposure to birth and decay.

—Aristotle, Metaphysics

The cases described above, like those in the essays to follow, are attended by what Quine called the “feeling of paradox” or “antinomy,” a genuine conflict in assumptions that might hint at a space of potential “revisions.” Qualia and qualisigns of sense experiences are, as Quine put it, “keyed in with language,” where language is understood not as a stable system, but a ship of Theseus, always under reconstruction, always up for “retentions and revisions.” Sensorial/bodily experience is always already semiotic; for humans, it cannot be extricated from language/culture (and, by extension, history, economy, etc.). The experiences of the body are political as well as technoscientific. To illustrate this claim—and by way of transition to the articles on proprioception—it is helpful to start with the old classic of phenomenal experience, pain, and, more specifically, parturition.

Pain is, within the discourse of medical science and evolutionary psychology, necessarily a negatively valued qualia (see Munn [Reference Munn1986] on positive and negative valuations). Medical gynecology was for decades concerned with eliminating the pain of childbirth, from general anesthesia in our grandmother’s generation, who fell asleep pregnant and woke up mothers, to the epidural. The feminist natural childbirth movement lead in the United States by Ina May Gaskin (following study with midwives in Mexico) sought to recuperate feeling and revalue pain by regenerating discourse. In the birth practice at “The Farm” and in the books (Reference Gaskin1976, Reference Gaskin2003) and, later, websites full of birth stories published and circulated beyond that anchoring center, they replaced words such as “contractions” (which feel “tight” and “scary”) with soothing, open words like “rushes” (which feel “soft” and “natural”); the hospital with the home, “cold” white sheets and fluorescent lights with “warm” afghans and incandescent bulbs, machine monitors with human hands. This was a project of inculcating qualia: using discourse to alter bodily chemistry—releasing endorphins rather than adrenalin—and open the cervix with a preparation during pregnancy through immersion in narrative texts (the birth stories, mostly written by and from the perspective of the mother), and in childbirth through the assistance of doulas, who (among other things) train the mother to feel the right feels by saying the right words and making the right sounds: a deep, open-mouthed, resonant uuuuugh, rather than a high, tight, shrill aaah. The feminist natural birth movement differs from “husband-coached” Lamaze and Bradley methods in focusing less on externally observeable behavior such as breathing exercises that can be shared with male partners and more on internal proprioception, affirming the absolute centrality of somatic experience in birth (e.g., as a way of internally knowing the position of the baby and responsively moving to assist its progress), while also attempting to alter that experience by changing the mother’s response to pain. Gaskin’s books emphasize the causal significance of qualia, to the point of arguing that the standard manual cervical check is a much less accurate assessment of readiness to birth than medical obstetricians claim (because the woman’s discomfort at the introduction of the gloved hand can itself cause the cervix to constrict, a possibility that obstetric science generally does not consider). This approach to childbirth is feminist insofar as it is devoted to changing the grammatical position of the mother in the act of birth: no longer patient, but agent. Those parts of the natural childbirth movement that seek to democratize access to natural labor beyond the mostly wealthy and white circles where birth preparation serves as pecuniary expenditure take this feminism most seriously as politics.

The natural childbirth movement, for all its limitations, offers a model of an ontological politics built on recognition of painful and pleasureable qualia as points of connection between ontological “levels”: discursive, psychological, physicological, biochemical, sociological, institutional. The movement is multi-natural, not attached to any material/immaterial divide, and syncretic about forms of causation; it accepts the possibility that making certain sounds in the larynx could “really, literally” operate on the cervix; that reading a book, and renaming a stimulus (contraction ⇛ rush, hospital ⇛ farm) can transform the qualitative experience of pain, change body chemistry, move anatomy; that repositioning the agent in a sentence and the narrator in a story can make new kind of subjects—and thus that “material” and “semiotic” forms can never be easily extricated from one another. That attention to blankets and words might be equally important. This is a pragmatic model for politics, and a model for doing pragmatist anthropology: one that does not necessarily take such modes of causation as a sign of radically “other,” nonmodern or non-Western ontologies but assumes such multiplicities as genuine possibilities.

The Essays

The contributors consider the problem of semiotics and ontology from a variety of ethnographic perspectives, but with a shared emphasis on the following points:

  1. 1. Qualia and qualisigns are conventionalized through multimodal semiotic processes, including words for sensations (red, soft, sharp, dissonant, etc.), onomatopoeia (especially sounds that serve as indexical icons of sensations, such as “aaaah” for refreshment or “eeek” for horror), and synaesthetic forms (the color red stands for hot water; red skin stands for ripe flavor).

  2. 2. Conventionalized qualisigns of sensory experience often play a crucial role in ontological discourse, and are frequently used as examples or evidence for cultural/ontological concepts such as materiality, abstraction, reality, primacy, and so on.

  3. 3. Ethnographic attention to qualia and qualisigns, focusing on the ways they are conventionalized linguistically and synaesthetically, provides an alternative approach to the study of matter/materials/materiality and to the study of ontologies.

In the first article, Nick Harkness describes the proprioception of qualia in classical singing training—the feeling of the larynx or the pressure of the diagrapham against the throat as the careful elicitation, training, and description of an array of qualisigns that reflexively (through the singer’s attunement or attention) produce the qualia of sound for the audience. A related form of conventionalized qualia is evidenced in Rihan Yeh’s description of the phonosonic calqing of an ontology of movement for “expediters” of transnational logistics of “Just-in-Time” production in Tijuana. The orchestration of bodies in time and space is indexed in the sounds of speeding up, “chchchchcch,” and slowing down, “empuuujala”—qualia of space time and proprioception related to a metaphysics of screaming or not screaming, braking or putting on the gas, which manages both the movements of machine parts through shipping routes and the movement of bodies and cars in relation to bullets on roads.

This institutional account of orchestration links to Arpita Roy’s account of laboratory science in the Large Hadron Collider at CERN; her article shows how Higgs boson particles appear in the lab only retrospectively, and only in the analysis of expert physicists with the capacity to properly interpret large amounts of data: not as laymen imagine, a mere extension of the eye to see better what is already there. Roy argues that in the division of semiotic labor this most elaborate of laboratories—the super collider—allows an anointed class of specialists decide our ontologies for us based on the qualia of their data. This account of the role of qualia in the authority of knowledge is extended in relation to social kinds in Angela Reyes’s article on the uncertain ontology the Phillipine elite. In Reyes’s article, Kripke’s understanding of natural kinds defined by experts is used to frame an analysis of the “bundling of linguistic and bodily qualia” in the identification of the true conyo in parodic youtube videos that demonstrate farcical (but implicitly sociologically accurate) techniques of recognition. Finally, Chris Ball takes up the problem of “qualia of reality” as they manifest in varieties of photographic representation and manipulation, in which versions of reality coalesce around qualisigns of realness, from imagined narratives of immersive journalism to animated replications of lens flare, that each emphasize photographicness.

In the ethnographic situations described in each of these articles, qualia, or experiences of properties, are interpreted as direct indexes of objects (signifieds). Firstness is always imbricated in secondness and thirdness. What seem like material objects (sinsigns) are always signifiying in virtue of some abstracted and conventionalized quality (qualisign) which cannot be located entirely in the “substrate”; but likewise, the qualisign is always encountered in material form. If rejecting nominalism allows us to welcome such abstract entities—types, categories and properties—into our ontologies, attention to qualia reveals the productive contradictions between those categories or attributes and their materializations.

Zhuangzi was walking on a mountain, when he saw a great tree with huge branches and luxuriant foliage. A wood-cutter was resting by its side, but he would not touch it, and, when asked the reason, said, that it was of no use for anything. Zhuangzi then said to his disciples, ‘This tree, because its wood is good for nothing, will succeed in living out its natural term of years’. … As to those who occupy themselves with the qualities of things, and with the teaching and practice of the human relations, it is not so with them. Union brings on separation; success, overthrow; sharp corners, the use of the file … where is the possibility of unchangeableness in any of these conditions? Remember this, my disciples. Let your abode be here - in the Dao and its Attributes.

(Reference Zhuangzi and LeggeZhuangzi, n.d.)

Footnotes

This special issue began as a two-part panel at the AAA, which in addition to all the articles in this issue also included papers by Judith Farquhar, Joseph Hankins, Keith Murphy, Shalini Shankar, and Michael Silverstein. Thanks are due to all of them for their contributions to its conceptualization, as well as to the editors of the journal, Richard Parmentier and Linda Kyung-Nan Koh, though they have no responsibility for its shortcomings. Thanks are also due to Victoria Grubbs, editorial research assistant, for her cogent comments and critiques.

1. See Vivieros de Castros (Reference Vivieros de Castros1992, 2014); Descola (Reference Descola and Scott1994, Reference Descola and Lloyd2013a, Reference Descola, Godbout and Luley2013b); Latour (Reference Latour2013); see also Keane (Reference Keane2013), Kelly (Reference Kelly2014), and Povinelli (Reference Povinelli2014) for reviews and critiques of the foregoing from various perspectives.

2. For STS, thinking in particular of Latour and Woolgar (Reference Latour and Woolgar1979), Law and Hassard (Reference Law and Hassard1999); Mol (Reference Mol2003); and Latour (Reference Latour2005). For the anthropology of things, see Mintz (Reference Mintz1985); Appadurai (Reference Appadurai and Appadurai1986); Myers (Reference Myers2001); Miller (Reference Miller1998, Reference Miller2010).

3. See Lévi-Strauss (Reference Lévi-Strauss and Needham[1949] 1969), Ortner’s (Reference Ortner, Rosaldo and Lamphere1974) feminist critique of this argument, and Sahlins’s (Reference Sahlins1977) defense against sociobiology; cf. Chomsky (Reference Chomsky1956, Reference Chomsky1959).

4. See, e.g., Coole and Frost (2010); and see Leys (2011); Shankar and Cavanaugh (2012); and Latour (Reference Latour2016) for countercritiques.

6. Non-intimates of this theory should refer to Parmentier (Reference Parmentier1994) for an introduction, but briefly: the sign is the thing that signifies, such as the gum on the sidewalk; the object is that which it calls up or indicates (the person who spits out gum); the interpretant is the thought or response that relates the sign and object (the observer wondering why so many people spit their gum out on the street).

7. “The entities to which a discourse commits us are the entities over which our variables of quantification have to range in order that the statements affirmed in that discourse be true.” Compare this to Galloway’s critique of Badiou’s use of set theory (Reference Galloway2013).

9. See Chumley and Harkness Reference Harkness2013.

10. And to philosophers, depending on whether you believe in a proper distinction between analytic and synthetic; Quine (Reference Quine1951), “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”; if there is no proper distinction between analytic and synthetic, then there is no basis for a distinction between ontological statements and empirical statements of existence.

References

Appadurai, Arjun. 1986. “Introduction: Commodities and the Politics of Value.” In The Social Life of Things, ed. Appadurai, Arjun, 3–63. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511819582.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle. 1947. “The Metaphysics.” In Introduction to Aristotle, ed. McKeon, Richard, 257–315. New York: Modern Library.Google Scholar
Asad, Talal. 1986. “The Concept of Cultural Translation in British Social Anthropology.” In Writing Culture: The Poetics and Politics of Ethnography, ed. Clifford, James and Marcus, George E., 141–64. Berkeley: University of California Press.10.1525/9780520946286-009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Azuma, Hiroki. 2009. Otaku: Japan’s Database Animals. Trans. Abel, Jonathan E. and Kono, Shion. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Ball, Christopher. 2014. “On Dicentization.Journal of Linguistic Anthropology 24:151–73.10.1111/jola.12046CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bear, Laura. 2007. Lines of the Nation: Indian Railway Workers, Bureaucracy, and the Intimate Historical Self. New York: Columbia University Press.10.7312/bear14002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blanchette, Alexander David. 2013. “Conceiving Porkopolis: The Production of Life on the American ‘Factory’ Farm.” PhD diss., University of Chicago.Google Scholar
Blommaert, Jan. 2014. “Chronotopes, Scales, and Complexity in the Study of Language in Society.Annual Review of Anthropology 44:105–16.10.1146/annurev-anthro-102214-014035CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bourdieu, Pierre. (1979) 1984. Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste. Trans. Nice, Richard. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 1979. “Individualism and the Mental.Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1): 73–121.10.1111/j.1475-4975.1979.tb00374.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 2010. Origins of Objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199581405.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carr, E. Summerson, and Lempert, Michael, eds. 2016. Scale: Discourse and Dimensions of Social Life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.10.1525/luminos.15CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cassaniti, Julia. 2015. “Intersubjective Affect and Embodied Emotion: Feeling the Supernatural in Thailand.Anthropology of Consciousness 26 (2): 132–42.10.1111/anoc.12036CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1956. “Three Models for the Description of Language.IRE Transactions on Information Theory 2 (3): 113–24.10.1109/TIT.1956.1056813CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N.. 1959. “On Certain Formal Properties of Grammars.Information and Control 2 (2): 137–67.10.1016/S0019-9958(59)90362-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chumley, Lily. 2016. Creativity Class: Art School and Culture Work in Postsocialist China. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Chumley, Lily, and Harkness, Nicholas. 2013. “Introduction: QUALIA.” Anthropological Theory 13 (1–2): 3–11.10.1177/1463499613483389CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1973. “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme.Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 47:5–20.10.2307/3129898CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deleuze, Gilles. (1983) 1986. Cinema: The Movement-Image. Trans. Tomlinson, Hugh and Habberjam, Barbara. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.10.5040/9781350251977CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Descola, Phillipe. (1986) 1994. In the Society of Nature. Trans. Scott, Nora. Cambridge: University of Cambridge.Google Scholar
Descola, Phillipe. (2005) 2013. Beyond Nature and Culture. Trans. Lloyd, Janet, with foreword by Marshall Sahlins. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226145006.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Descola, Phillipe. 2013. The Ecology of Others. Trans. Godbout, Genevieve and Luley, Benjamin. Chicago: Prickly Paradigm.Google Scholar
Elyachar, Julia. 2010. “Phatic Labor, Infrastructure, and the Question of Empowerment in Cairo.American Ethnologist 37 (3): 452–64.10.1111/j.1548-1425.2010.01265.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engels, Frederick. 1940. Dialectics of Nature. Trans. Dutt, C. P.. New York: International.Google Scholar
Engels, Frederick. 2012. “Next Practices: Knowledge, Infrastructure, and Public Goods at the Bottom of the Pyramid.Public Culture 24 (1): 109–29.Google Scholar
Fennell, Catherine. 2016. Last Project Standing: Civics and Sympathy in Post-welfare Chicago. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Flores, Nelson, and Rosa, Jonathan. 2015. “Undoing Appropriateness: Raciolinguistic Ideologies and Language Diversity in Education.Harvard Educational Review 85 (2): 149–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gal, Susan. 2013. “Tastes of Talk: Qualia and the Moral Flavor of Signs.” Anthropological Theory 13 (1/2): 31–48.10.1177/1463499613483396CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galloway, Alex. 2013. “The Poverty of Philosophy: Realism and Post-Fordism.Critical Inquiry 39:347–66.10.1086/668529CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaskin, Ina May. 1976. Spiritual Midwifery. 3rd ed. Summertown, TN: Book Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Gaskin, Ina May. 2003. Ina May’s Guide to Childbirth. New York: Bantam Dell.Google Scholar
Greenspan, Ralph. 2007. An Introduction to Nervous Systems. Cold Spring Harbor, NY: Laboratory Press.Google Scholar
Harman, Graham. 2002. Tool-Being: Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects. Peru, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Haraway, Donna. 2003. The Companion Species Manifesto: Dogs, People, and Significant Otherness. Chicago: Prickly Paradigm Press.Google Scholar
Haraway, Donna. 2008. When Species Meet. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Harkness, Nicholas. 2013. “Softer Soju in South Korea.” Anthropological Theory 13 (1/2): 12–30.10.1177/1463499613483394CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harkness, Nicholas. 2015. Songs of Seoul: An Ethnography of Voice and Voicing in Christian South. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Houtman, Dick, and Meyer, Birgit, eds. 2012. Things: Religion and the Question of Materiality. New York: Fordham University Press.10.5422/fordham/9780823239450.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, Matthew. 2012. Government of Paper: The Materiality of Bureaucracy in Urban Pakistan. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Infante, Ignacio. 2013. After Translation: The Transfer and Circulation of Modern Poetics across the Atlantic. New York: Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Inoue, Miyako. 2003. Vicarious Language: Gender and Linguistic Modernity in Japan. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Irvine, J. and Gal, S.. 2000. “Language Ideology and Linguistic Differentiation.” In Regimes of Language: Ideologies, Polities, and Identities, ed. Kroskrity, Paul V., 35–84. Santa Fe: School of American Research Press.Google Scholar
Jakobson, Roman. 1960. “Closing Statement: Linguistics and Poetics.” In Style in Language, ed. Sebeok, Thomas A., 147–73. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Kafka, Ben. 2015. The Demon of Writing: Paperwork, Public Safety, and the Reign of Terror. Cambridge: Zone Books.Google Scholar
Keane, Webb. 1995. “The Spoken House: Text, Act, and Object in Eastern Indonesia.American Ethnologist 22 (1): 102–24.10.1525/ae.1995.22.1.02a00050CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keane, Webb. 2003. “Semiotics and the Social Analysis of Material Things.” Language & Communication 23 (3–4): 409–25.10.1016/S0271-5309(03)00010-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keane, Webb. 2006. “Signs Are Not the Garb of Meaning: On the Social Analysis of Material Things.” In Materiality, ed. Miller, Daniel, 182–205. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Keane, Webb. 2013. “Ontologies, Anthropologists, and Ethical Life.HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 3 (1): 186–91.10.14318/hau3.1.014CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keane, Webb. 2015. Ethical Life: Its Natural and Social Histories. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.10.23943/princeton/9780691167732.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, John. 2014. “The Ontological Turn: Where Are We?HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 4 (1): 357–60.10.14318/hau4.1.019CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kockelman, Paul. 2006. “Agent, Person, Subject, Self.Semiotica 162 (1): 1–18.10.1515/SEM.2006.072CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kockelman, Paul. 2011. “A Mayan Ontology of Poultry: Selfhood, Affect, Animals, and Ethnography.Language in Society 40 (4): 427–54.10.1017/S0047404511000467CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kockelman, Paul. 2013. “The Anthropology of an Equation. Sieves, Spam Filters, Agentive Algorithms, and Ontologies of Transformation.HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 3 (3): 33–61.10.14318/hau3.3.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kohn, Eduardo. 2014. “How Dogs Dream: Amazonian Natures and the Politics of Transspecies Engagement.American Ethnologist 34 (1): 3–24.10.1525/ae.2007.34.1.3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kohn, Eduardo. 2015. How Forests Think: Toward an Anthropology Beyond the Human. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul A. 1972. “Naming and Necessity.” In Semantics of Natural Language, ed. Davidson, Donald and Harman, Gilbert, 253–355. Dordrecht: Reidel.10.1007/978-94-010-2557-7_9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lai, Guolong. 2015. Excavating the Afterlife: The Archaeology of Early Chinese Religion. Seattle: University of Washington Press.Google Scholar
Lai, Lili. 2014. “Everyday Hygiene in Rural Henan.positions 22 (3): 635–59.10.1215/10679847-2685404CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Latour, Bruno. 2004. “Why Has Critique Run out of Steam? From Matters of Fact to Matters of Concern.Critical Inquiry 30:225–48.10.1086/421123CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Latour, Bruno. 2005. “What Is the Style of Matters of Concern?” Spinoza Lectures, University of Amsterdam, April and May.Google Scholar
Latour, Bruno. 2013. An Inquiry into Modes of Existence: An Anthropology of the Moderns. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Latour, Bruno. 2016. “How Better to Register the Agency of Things: Part 1, Semiotics; Part 2: Ontology.” Yale University Tanner Lectures, 2013–14. In The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, vol. 34, 79–117. Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.Google Scholar
Latour, Bruno, and Woolgar, Steve. 1979. Laboratory Life: The Social Construction of Scientific Facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Law, John, and Hassard, John, eds. 1999. Actor Network Theory and After. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Leone, Massimo, and Parmentier, Richard, eds. 2014. “Representing Transcendence.” Signs and Society 2 (S1).10.1086/674529CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lévi-Strauss, Claude. (1949) 1969. The Elementary Structures of Kinship. Trans. Needham, Rodney. Boston: Beacon.Google Scholar
Lucy, John. 1997. “Linguistic Relativity.Annual Review of Anthropology 26:291–312.10.1146/annurev.anthro.26.1.291CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manning, Paul. 2012. Semiotics of Drink and Drinking. London: Continuum.Google Scholar
Manning, Paul, and Meneley, Anne. 2008. “Material Objects in Cosmological Worlds: An Introduction.Ethnos 73 (3): 285–302.10.1080/00141840802323997CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marx, Karl. 1906. Capital, vol. 1, A Critique of Political Economy, ed. Engels, Friedrick. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Maurer, Bill. 2005. “Does Money Matter? Abstraction and Substitution in Alternative Financial Forms.” In Materiality, ed. Miller, Daniel, 140–64. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.10.1215/9780822386711-006CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maurer, Bill. 2013a. “Transacting Ontologies: Kockelman’s Sieves and a Bayesian Anthropology.HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 3 (3): 63–75.10.14318/hau3.3.004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maurer, Bill. 2013b. “‘When Perhaps the Real Problem Is Money Itself!’: The Practical Materiality of Bitcoin.Social Semiotics 23 (2): 261–77.10.1080/10350330.2013.777594CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McWhorter, John. 2014. The Language Hoax: Why the World Looks the Same in Any Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Meskell, Lynn. 2005. “Objects in the Mirror Appear Closer Than They Are.” In Materiality, ed. Miller, Daniel, 51–71. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.10.1215/9780822386711-002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mintz, Sidney. 1985. Sweetness and Power: The Place of Sugar in Modern History. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Miller, Daniel. 1998. A Theory of Shopping. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Miller, Daniel. 2005. Materiality. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, Daniel. 2010. Stuff. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Mol, Annemarie. 1999. “Ontological Politics: A Word and Some Politics.” In Actor Network Theory and After, ed. Law, John and Hassard, John, 74–89. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Mol, Annemarie. 2003. The Body Multiple: Ontology in Medical Practice. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.10.2307/j.ctv1220nc1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, Kelli. 2013. “Visualizing Violence: The Ethics of Photographic Evidence in the Domestic Violence Trial and Popular Culture.” PhD diss., University of California San Diego.Google Scholar
Morton, Timothy. 2013. Hyperobjects: Philosophy and Ecology after the End of the World. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Munn, Nancy. 1986. The Fame of Gawa: A Symbolic Study of Value Transformation in a Massim Society. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Myers, Fred, ed. 2001. The Empire of Things: Regimes of Value and Material Culture. Santa Fe: School of American Research Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1974. “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?Philosophical Review 83 (4): 435–50.10.2307/2183914CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nakassis, Constantine. 2013. “Materiality, Materialization.Journal of Ethnographic Theory 3 (3): 399–406.10.14318/hau3.3.022CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nakassis, Constantine. 2016. Doing Style: Youth and Mass Mediation in South India. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226327990.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozawa, Shunsuke. 2013. “Characterization.Semiotic Review 3:1–31.Google Scholar
Ong, Aiwha, and Collier, Steven, eds. 2005. Global Assemblages: Technology, Politics, and Ethics as Anthropological Problems. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Ortner, Sherry. 1974. “Is Female to Male as Nature Is to Culture.” In Woman, Culture, and Society, ed. Rosaldo, Michelle Z. and Lamphere, Louise, 67–88. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Parks, Lisa, and Starosielski, Nicole, eds. 2015. Signal Traffic: Critical Studies of Media Infrastructures. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.10.5406/illinois/9780252039362.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parmentier, Richard. 1994. Signs in Society: Studies in Semiotic Anthropology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Parmentier, Richard. 2016. Signs and Society: Further Studies in Semiotic Anthropology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.10.2307/j.ctt2005snsCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Povinelli, Elizabeth. 1995. “Do Rocks Listen? The Cultural Politics of Apprehending.American Anthropologist 97 (3): 505–18.10.1525/aa.1995.97.3.02a00090CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Povinelli, Elizabeth. 2001. “Radical Worlds: The Anthropology of Incommensurability and Inconceivability.Annual Review of Anthropology 30:319–34.10.1146/annurev.anthro.30.1.319CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Povinelli, Elizabeth. 2006. The Empire of Love: Toward a Theory of Intimacy, Genealogy, and Carnality. A Public Planet Book. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Povinelli, Elizabeth. 2016. Geontologies: A Requiem to Late Liberalism. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1973. “Meaning and Reference.Journal of Philosophy 70 (19): 699–711.10.2307/2025079CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1975. Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers. Vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511625251CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, Willard V. 1951. “Main Trends in Recent Philosophy: Two Dogmas of Empiricism.Philosophical Review 60 (1): 20–43.10.2307/2181906CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, Willard V.. 1966. The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard V.. 1968. “Ontological Relativity.Journal of Philosophy 65 (7): 185–212.10.2307/2024305CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ralph, Michael. 2015. Forensics of Capital: Risk and Liability, Citizenship and Sovereignty, in Senegal. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226198606.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reyes, Angela. 2007. Language, Identity, and Stereotype among Southeast Asian American Youth: The Other Asian. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Rosa, Jonathan. 2016. “American Apprehensions: Racial Profiling in Institutional and Semiotic Perspective.” Paper presented at the American Anthropological Association Annual Meeting, November, Minneapolis.Google Scholar
Roth, Christopher. 2009. Becoming Tsimshian: The Social Life of Names. Seattle: University of Washington Press.Google Scholar
Roy, Arpita. 2014. “Ethnography and the Theory of the Signature in Physics.Cultural Anthropology 29 (3): 479–502.10.14506/ca29.3.03CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1905. “On Denoting.” Mind, n.s., 14 (56): 479–93.10.1093/mind/XIV.4.479CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rutherford, Danilyn. 2012. “Kinky Empiricism.Cultural Anthropology 27 (3): 465–79.10.1111/j.1548-1360.2012.01154.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sahlins, Marshall. 1977. Culture and Practical Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sapir, Edward. 1949. Selected Writings of Edward Sapir in Language, Culture and Personality. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2004. “‘Cultural’ Concepts and the Language-Culture Nexus.Current Anthropology 45 (5): 621–52.10.1086/423971CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2006. “Writing at the Chronotopic Margins of Empires.” In Margins of Writing, Origins of Cultures, ed. Sanders, Seth L., 149–55. Chicago: Oriental Institute of the University of Chicago.Google Scholar
Silverstein, Michael. 2013. “Discourse and the No-thing-ness of Culture.Signs and Society 1 (2): 327–66.10.1086/673252CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silvio, Teri. 2010. “Animation: The New Performance?Journal of Linguistic Anthropology 20 (2): 422–38.10.1111/j.1548-1395.2010.01078.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spillers, Hortense. 1987. “Mama’s Baby, Papa’s Maybe: An American Grammar Book.Diacritics 17 (2): 64–81.10.2307/464747CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stasch, Rupert. 2009. Society of Others: Kinship and Mourning in a West Papuan Place. Berkeley: University of California Press.10.1525/9780520943322CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stasch, Rupert. 2012. “Afterword: On Relationality of Codes and the Indexical Iconicity of Linguistic Otherness within Wider Value Formations.” In “Interlingual Articulations in Asia and the Pacific: Figuring Sociocultural Otherness through Otherness of Linguistic Codes,” ed. Rumsey, Alan and Stasch, Rupert. Special issue. Australian Journal of Anthropology 23 (3): 398–405.10.1111/taja.12007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stasch, Rupert. 2015. “Introduction: Double Signs and Intrasocietal Heterogeneity in Primitivist Tourism Encounters.” In “Primitivist Tourism,” ed. Stasch, Rupert. Ethnos 80 (4): 433–47.10.1080/00141844.2014.940989CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strathern, Marilyn. 1988. The Gender of the Gift: Problems with Women and Problems with Society in Melanesia. Berkeley: University of California Press.10.1525/california/9780520064232.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, Peter F. 1950. “On Referring.Mind 59 (235): 320–44.10.1093/mind/LIX.235.320CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Truillot, Michel-Rolph. 2003. Global Transformations: Anthropology and the Modern World. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.10.1007/978-1-137-04144-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tsing, Anna. 2005. Friction: An Ethnography of Global Connection. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Tsing, Anna. 2015. The Mushroom at the End of the World. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Vivieros de Castros, Eduardo. 2014. Cannibal Metaphysics. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Voyles, Traci Brynne. 2015. Legacies of Uranium Mining in Navajo Country. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.10.5749/minnesota/9780816692644.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vygotsky, Lev. 2012. Thought and Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Whorf, Benjamin L. 1967. Language, Thought and Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Zhuangzi, . n.d. The Tree on the Mountain, trans. Legge, James. http://ctext.org/zhuangzi/tree-on-the-mountain.Google Scholar