Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-13T14:52:36.845Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

In Search of Greene's Argument

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 June 2018

NORBERT PAULO*
Affiliation:
University of Graz and University of Salzburgnorbert.paulo@uni-graz.at

Abstract

The moral psychologist Joshua Greene has proposed a number of arguments for the normative significance of empirical research and for the unreliability of deontological intuitions. For these arguments, much hinges on the combination of various components of Greene's research – namely the dual-process theory of moral judgement, ‘personalness’ as a factor in moral decision-making, and his functional understanding of deontology and consequentialism. Incorporating these components, I reconstruct three distinct arguments and show that the Personalness Argument for the claim that empirical research can advance normative ethics and the Combined Argument against deontology are both sound and interesting in themselves. They do not, however, cast doubt on traditional deontology or reserve a specific role for neuroscience. The Indirect Route argument overcomes some of the other arguments’ limitations. It is, however, invalid. I conclude by pointing out the broader philosophical relevance of Greene's arguments as shedding light on second-order morality.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Greene, Joshua D., ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality: Why Cognitive (Neuro)Science Matters for Ethics’, Ethics 124.4 (2014), pp. 695726, at 695-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 See, for example, Berker, Selim, ‘The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience’, Philosophy & Public Affairs 37.4 (2009), pp. 293329CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kamm, Frances M., ‘Neuroscience and Moral Reasoning: A Note on Recent Research’, Philosophy & Public Affairs 37.4 (2009), pp. 330–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Singer, Peter, ‘Ethics and Intuitions’, The Journal of Ethics 9. 3–4 (2005), pp. 331–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Dean, Richard, ‘Does Neuroscience Undermine Deontological Theory?’, Neuroethics 3.1 (2009), pp. 4360CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Mihailov, Emilian, ‘Is Deontology a Moral Confabulation?’, Neuroethics 9.1 (2015), pp. 113CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nichols, Shaun, ‘Process Debunking and Ethics’, Ethics 124.4 (2014), pp. 727–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kahane, Guy and Shackel, Nicholas, ‘Methodological Issues in the Neuroscience of Moral Judgement’, Mind & Language 25.5 (2010), pp. 561–82CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Kahane, Guy, ‘On the Wrong Track: Process and Content in Moral Psychology’, Mind & Language 27.5 (2012), pp. 519–45CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Lott, Micah, ‘Moral Implications from Cognitive (Neuro)Science? No Clear Route’, Ethics 127.1 (2016), pp. 241–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rini, Regina A., ‘Making Psychology Normatively Significant’, Journal of Ethics 17.3 (2013), pp. 257–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Dancy, Jonathan, ‘Intuition and Emotion’, Ethics 124.4 (2014), pp. 787812CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Foot, Philippa, ‘The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of Double Effect’, Oxford Review 5 (1967), pp. 515Google Scholar; Thomson, Judith Jarvis, ‘Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem’, The Monist 59.2 (1976), pp. 204–17CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

4 Greene, Joshua D. et al., ‘An FMRI Investigation of Emotional Engagement in Moral Judgment’, Science 293.5537 (2001), pp. 2105–8, at 2104CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; cf. Berker, ‘The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience’.

5 Sauer, Hanno, ‘Morally Irrelevant Factors: What's Left of the Dual Process-Model of Moral Cognition?’, Philosophical Psychology 25.6 (2012), pp. 783–811CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Kahane, Guy et al., ‘The Neural Basis of Intuitive and Counterintuitive Moral Judgement’, Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 7.4 (2012), pp. 393402CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kahane, Guy, ‘Sidetracked by Trolleys: Why Sacrificial Moral Dilemmas Tell Us Little (or Nothing) about Utilitarian Judgment’, Social Neuroscience 10.5 (2015), pp. 551–60CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Kahane, Guy et al., “‘Utilitarian” Judgments in Sacrificial Moral Dilemmas Do Not Reflect Impartial Concern for the Greater Good’, Cognition 134 (2015), pp. 193209CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Greene, Joshua D., ‘The Secret Joke of Kant's Soul’, Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, vol. 3 (Cambridge, MA, 2008), pp. 3580, at 43Google Scholar. In a later paper, he adds that there is a second relevant factor, namely whether the victim is harmed as a means or as a side effect (Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 709). However, since he regards this second factor as less normatively relevant and since his own research focuses on personalness, I will not discuss the means/side effect distinction.

8 Greene, ‘The Secret Joke of Kant's Soul’, p. 43; critically Kahane and Shackel, ‘Methodological Issues in the Neuroscience of Moral Judgement’, Kamm, ‘Neuroscience and Moral Reasoning’, Mihailov, ‘Is Deontology a Moral Confabulation?’.

9 Greene et al., ‘An FMRI Investigation of Emotional Engagement in Moral Judgment’.

10 Haidt, Jonathan, ‘The Emotional Dog and its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment’, Psychological Review 108.4 (2001), pp. 814–34, at 818CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

11 Joshua D. Greene, ‘Notes on “The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience” by Selim Berker’ <https://static1.squarespace.com/static/54763f79e4b0c4e55ffb000c/t/54cb945ae4b001aedee69e81/1422627930781/notes-on-berker.pdf> (2010), p. 20.

12 Cf. Rational Intuition: Philosophical Roots, Scientific Investigations, ed. Lisa M. Osbeck and Barbara S. Held (Cambridge, 2014); Bengson, John, ‘How Philosophers Use Intuition and ‘Intuition’, Philosophical Studies 171.3 (2014), pp. 555–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, ‘Framing Moral Intuitions’, Moral Psychology: The Neuroscience of Morality, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, vol. 2 (Cambridge, MA, 2008), pp. 4776, at 47Google Scholar; Brink, David O., ‘Principles and Intuitions in Ethics: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives’, Ethics 124.4 (2014), pp. 665–94, at 680CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Dancy, ‘Intuition and Emotion’, p. 790.

14 Sinnott-Armstrong, ‘Framing Moral Intuitions’, p. 47.

15 Greene, ‘The Secret Joke of Kant's Soul’, p. 39.

16 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, pp. 699–700, emphasizes this divergence. Kamm, ‘Neuroscience and Moral Reasoning’; Mihailov, ‘Is Deontology a Moral Confabulation?’; Dancy, ‘Intuition and Emotion’ and other commentators fail to take Greene's distinction between the functional and the traditional philosophical understandings of deontology and consequentialism into account.

17 Greene, ‘The Secret Joke of Kant's Soul’, p. 37.

18 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, pp. 699–700.

19 Greene, ‘The Secret Joke of Kant's Soul’, pp. 69f.

20 Berker, ‘The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience’, p. 321.

21 Greene, ‘Notes on “The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience” by Selim Berker’, p. 12.

22 I should emphasize that I use ‘neuroscience’ here and in the whole article in a narrow sense, as utilizing high-level technologies such as MRI, fMRI, SPECT, PET, DTI, DOT or KO for neuroscientific inquiry and thereby excluding pencil-and-paper studies. The latter would arguably be included in a wider understanding, such as the one stated in the Merriam-Webster dictionary, where neuroscience is defined as ‘a branch (as neurophysiology) of the life sciences that deals with the anatomy, physiology, biochemistry, or molecular biology of nerves and nervous tissue and especially with their relation to behavior and learning’. I suspect that Berker and Greene also have a narrower understanding in mind, see Berker, ‘The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience’, pp. 293–5; Greene, ‘Notes on “The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience” by Selim Berker’, pp. 7-8. Also, the main work in neuroscience seems to include high-level technologies, cf. Poldrack, Russell A. and Farah, Martha J., ‘Progress and Challenges in Probing the Human Brain’, Nature 526 (2015), pp. 371–9CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

23 Berker, ‘The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience’, p. 325.

24 Greene, ‘Notes on “The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience” by Selim Berker’, p. 13; Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 716.

25 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, pp. 709-10; for a discussion of Greene's earlier distinction between ‘personal’ and ‘impersonal’ see his Greene, Joshua D., ‘Reply to Mikhail and Timmons’, Moral Psychology, ed. Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, vol. 3 (Cambridge, MA, 2008), pp. 105–17Google Scholar.

26 Greene, ‘Notes on “The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience” by Selim Berker’, p. 16.

27 Since Greene does not offer such support, the Argument from Morally Irrelevant Factors, as stated above, is far too wide in scope and its conclusions thus not warranted. It is thus not a sound argument against deontology.

28 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 713.

29 Greene, ‘Notes on “The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience” by Selim Berker’, p. 12.

30 Greene also tried to build a new argument against deontology on the Indirect Route Argument as discussed in section VI, cf. Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, sec. VI; Lott, ‘Moral Implications from Cognitive (Neuro)Science?’. However, since the latter argument is not sound, this attempt is doomed to fail and will not be discussed here.

31 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, pp. 698–9.

32 For the latest collection of supportive research from neuroscience, as well as from other sciences, see Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, pp. 700–6; for a critical discussion of this evidence, see Chelsea Helion and Kevin N. Ochsner, ‘The Role of Emotion Regulation in Moral Judgment’, Neuroethics (2016), pp. 1–12, doi:10.1007/s12152-016-9261-z.

33 Although he never explicitly makes this argument, I believe that this formulation accurately represents the ideas in Greene, ‘Notes on “The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience” by Selim Berker’; Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’.

34 Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for highlighting this point.

35 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, pp. 699-700 and 714-15; Kumar, Victor and Campbell, Richmond, ‘On the Normative Significance of Experimental Moral Psychology’, Philosophical Psychology 25.3 (2012), pp. 311–30, at 313CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36 Hooker, Brad, Ideal Code, Real World: A Rule-Consequentialist Theory of Morality (Oxford; New York, 2001), p. 32Google Scholar.

37 Singer, Peter, ‘Famine, Affluence, and Morality’, Philosophy & Public Affairs 1.3 (1972), pp. 229–43Google Scholar.

38 Greene, ‘The Secret Joke of Kant's Soul’, p. 46.

39 Appiah, Kwame Anthony, Experiments in Ethics (Cambridge, MA, 2009), p. 96Google Scholar.

40 I do not include Appiah's further demand that the moral question has to be decided under pressure of time. Most philosophers and legions of philosophy students studying and writing about Trolleyology have had plenty of time to decide in favour of one option or another.

41 Compare Lott, ‘Moral Implications from Cognitive (Neuro)Science?’, p. 243.

42 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’.

43 Musschenga, Bert, ‘Was ist empirische Ethik?’, Ethik in der Medizin 21.3 (2009), pp. 187–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

44 Christen, Markus and Alfano, Mark, ‘Outlining the Field: A Research Program for Empirically Informed Ethics’, Empirically Informed Ethics: Morality between Facts and Norms, ed. Christen, Markus et al. (Heidelberg and New York, 2014), pp. 327CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

45 Cf. Christensen, J. F. and Gomila, A., ‘Moral Dilemmas in Cognitive Neuroscience of Moral Decision-Making: A Principled Review’, Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews 36.4 (2012), pp. 1249–64CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

46 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 713.

47 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 714.

48 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 714.

49 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 715.

50 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 715.

51 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 715.

52 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 715.

53 Greene, Joshua D., Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason, and the Gap between Us and Them (New York, 2013), pt. IIGoogle Scholar.

54 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, pp. 696–7.

55 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 715.

56 E.g. Greene, ‘The Secret Joke of Kant's Soul’, p. 72.

57 Greene, ‘The Secret Joke of Kant's Soul’, p. 71.

58 Walzer, Michael, Interpretation and Social Criticism (Cambridge, MA, 1993)Google Scholar.

59 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 713.

60 Railton, Peter, ‘The Affective Dog and its Rational Tale: Intuition and Attunement’, Ethics 124.4 (2014), pp. 813–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Railton, Peter, ‘Moral Learning: Conceptual Foundations and Normative Relevance’, Cognition 167 (2017), pp. 172–90CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Kumar, Victor, ‘Moral Vindications’, Cognition 167 (2017), pp. 124–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Richmond Campbell, ‘Learning from Moral Inconsistency’, Cognition (2017); Sauer, Hanno, Moral Judgments as Educated Intuitions (Cambridge, MA, 2017)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

61 Greene, Joshua D., ‘The Rat-a-Gorical Imperative: Moral Intuition and the Limits of Affective Learning’, Cognition 167 (2017), pp. 66–77CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

62 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 700, emphasis added.

63 Lott, ‘Moral Implications from Cognitive (Neuro)Science?’, p. 244.

64 Greene, ‘Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality’, p. 721.

65 Lott, ‘Moral Implications from Cognitive (Neuro)Science?’, p. 252.

66 Note that this point is different from the criticism Lott anticipates, namely that deontologists are inevitably bound to rely on their automatic settings, i.e. that all their reflections on normative reasons just rehash intuitions subject to debunking. This is a blunt overstatement of what Greene called the ‘psychological essence of deontology’. And Lott is correct to argue that ‘nothing in the empirical data shows this. . . . Thus we have no reason to think that the results of reflective reasoning will be limited to what comes from automatic settings’ (‘Moral Implications from Cognitive (Neuro)Science?’, p. 256).

67 Lott, ‘Moral Implications from Cognitive (Neuro)Science?’, p. 242.

68 Cf. Sauer, Hanno, Debunking Arguments in Ethics (New York, 2018)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

69 Hooker, Ideal Code, Real World, p. 13.

70 Hooker, Ideal Code, Real World, p. 28.

71 For helpful comments and discussion, many thanks to Robert Audi, Johannes Brandl, Bettina Bussmann, Christoph Bublitz, Tom Douglas, Joao Fabiano, Christopher Gauker, Guy Kahane, Neil Levy, Fergus Peace, Thomas Pölzler, Thomas Schramme, Nicholas Shackel, Joshua Shepherd, and two anonymous reviewers for this journal. Thanks also to an anonymous reviewer for Analysis who provided very constructive feedback on a much earlier version of this article.