1 Introduction
Understanding the effect of future wealth on risk aversion is essential for uncovering the puzzle of why household savings is low in the United States. In particular, there are compelling reasons to believe that many choices are motivated, in part, by how we imagine our future states of wealth. Individuals constantly struggle between “risky” and “safe” options—whether to become a rock star or a music teacher, be an entrepreneur or work for a company, etc.—that are ultimately chosen based on upside or downside potential. But I know of no research that examines the relationship between imagined future wealth and risky decision making.
The relationship between wealth and risk aversion is well-documented in the economics literature (Reference Kihlstrom, Romer and WilliamsKihlstrom et al., 1981; Reference Brunnermeier and NagelBrunnermeier & Nagel, 2008; Reference SousaSousa, 2010; Reference Paravisini, Rappoport and RavinaParavisini et al., 2011). Yet pioneers of the theory of the utility of wealth did not reach a consensus about the direction of this relationship.Footnote 1 Expected-utility theory (EUT) remains the dominant framework for examing the relationship between wealth and risk. EUT predicts that individuals maximize their expected utility based on probabilities and outcome utilities of possible levels of wealth. But extensive research (e.g., Reference Kahneman and TverskyKahneman & Tversky, 1979; Reference RabinRabin, 2000; Reference Rabin and ThalerRabin & Thaler, 2001) has challenged the sufficiency of EUT as a descriptive account. Inquiries about how future reference point realizations could affect (current) economic decisions have not been investigated. In particular, how does imagining a future wealth scenario change our decisions today? This type of question has several economic applications; its implications for savings behavior, in particular, are discussed here.
This paper studies behavior in paired lottery choice experiments to experimentally test whether hypothetical future realizations of wealth alter individuals’ current risk decisions. In particular, I am interested in whether changes in hypothetical wealth frames affect risk aversion. My hypotheses are derived from EUT with decreasing relative risk aversion. I hypothesize that (H1) those who imagine they will be wealthy will take more risks because they are prompted to think that they can afford to take more gambles and (H2) those who imagine they will be poor will take fewer gambles since they believe they cannot afford to take risks. EUT with decreasing relative risk aversion would predict that individuals respond to an exogenous increase in wealth by taking more risks and respond to a decrease by taking fewer. I find that those who are asked to imagine themselves as wealthy in the future make significantly riskier decisions today. Yet those who are asked to imagine themselves as poor in the future are not significantly more risk-averse in their current decisions.
2 Previous work
The existing research on how framing affects choice is extensive (beginning with Reference Tversky and KahnemanTversky & Kahneman, 1981, and Hershey et al., 1982). It is important to note, as well, that framing has real effects on economic behavior. Consistent with prospect theory, researchers have found that gain and loss frames alter choice decisions, even if the underlying decisions are the same. Reference Epley and GneezyEpley and Gneezy (2007) argued that the framing of financial windfalls can change how people spend their income. In particular, income that is perceived as a positive departure from individuals’ reference points (e.g., bonus) is spent more easily than that which is perceived as undoing a negative departure (e.g., refund).
In addition, the outcomes of prior events have been shown to affect identical decisions. Reference Coval and ShumwayCoval and Shumway (2005) found that investor losses in the morning often lead to risky behavior in afternoon trading. In this case, while investment decisions should be based on future returns, they are also based on whether the investor is a winner or a loser at the time of the decision.
While economic theory has predictions for how expectations about the future affect current decisions, empirical and experimental tests are sparse. One such study examining the link between expected future income and risk decisions using survey data found that households that are more likely to face uncertainty about future income or about to become liquidity constrained are more risk-averse (Reference Guiso and PaiellaGuiso & Paiella, 2008). In another study, Reference CarrollCarroll (1994) reports that consumption decisions are unaffected by expected changes in income, which is consistent with consumption smoothing. Reference BinswangerBinswanger (1980) found that wealth reduces risk aversion, but only slightly (and not significantly). But this study, in particular, did not examine future wealth, and its sample comprised unskilled laborers in rural India.
The present study is apparently the first to experimentally test the relationship between imagined future wealth and (current) risk decisions. I examine the effect of future wealth frames (wealthy and poor) on hypothetical risky decisions involving money. These types of frames are common in the psychology literature as experimental tools (Reference Garry, Manning, Loftus and ShermanGarry et al., 1996; Reference AndersonAnderson, 1983; Reference CarrollCarroll, 1978). In one recent example, Reference Beegle, Himelein and RavallionBeegle et al. (2012) asked households in Tajikistan to rank their own economic statuses against theoretical vignettes of other households to see whether they had a frame-of-reference bias with respect to their own welfare. They found that households had diverse scales for assessing their levels of welfare, and that the bias is actually quite small. Here I use similar types of vignettes.
3 Experimental design
Registered undergraduate students at Vassar College were recruited primarily through informal announcements such as Facebook, word of mouth, and email. They were told that the experiment consisted of two sessions (“Session I” and “Session II”), each taking 20–25 minutes. They were also informed that the two sessions would be a week apart and would be completed online. Before each session, directions for logging into the experiment were sent to campus email addresses provided by the subjects.
Subjects were randomly assigned to one of three groups—two treatment groups and a control group. The first treatment group was the “Wealthy then Poor” group. Subjects assigned to this treatment were given a “Wealthy” frame (Appendix A) in Session I in which they were asked to imagine that they became wealthy in the future. After subjects read this frame, they were instructed: “Please put yourself in the position of the person described in this frame and proceed to the decisions.” The subjects then completed a series of 10 paired lottery choice decisions first utilized by Reference Holt and LauryHolt and Laury (2002) to yield a measure of their risk preferences.
A week later, these subjects were given a “Poor” frame (Appendix A) in Session II in which they were asked to imagine that they became poor in the future. After reading the Poor frame, they were given the same instructions they received in Session I and completed the same Reference Holt and LauryHolt and Laury (2002) risk preference assessment.
Subjects assigned to the second treatment group, “Poor then Wealthy”, completed the same risk assessment questions, but were given the frames in the opposite order. Finally, the control group (“Control”) subjects completed the lottery choice questions, but were given neither the Wealthy nor the Poor frames in either session.Footnote 2 For all three groups, Session II lottery decisions were followed by a brief demographic questionnaire.
For each of the ten pairs of risk-assessment questions in the Reference Holt and LauryHolt and Laury (2002) setup (Appendix B), subjects are asked to choose between a “safe” bet (which we call “Option A”) and a “risky” bet (“Option B”). In the safe bet, there is a relatively small differential between the higher payoff amount and the lower payoff amount. In the risky bet, the differential between the payouts is rather large. The respective nominal payouts for Option A and Option B do not change between the ten decisions. What does change, however, is the relative probability of obtaining the higher payoff amount. Instructions for the decision task resembled those given in Reference Holt and LauryHolt and Laury (2002).
Note that by having both Sessions I and II, we are randomizing order of frames within-subjects. However, if we examine only Session I, we have a between-subjects analysis. Results from both analyses are described in the next section.
Subjects included 190 undergraduate students (from a variety of majors), with 65 in each treatment group and 60 in the Control group.Footnote 3 The median time spent between Sessions I and II was 9 days, while the range was 8 to 13 days. Each subject was told that one of her 10 decisions made in each session would be selected at random and that her gamble (fixed by her choice of either Option A or Option B) in the selected decision would be performed to determine her payout. Potential payouts had to be small enough so as to not encourage “erratic” behavior.Footnote 4 For this reason, the payoffs for all treatments were equal to the lowest payoff in the experiments conducted by Reference Holt and LauryHolt and Laury (2002) multiplied by 4.Footnote 5
Subjects were paid the average of their session payoffs from Session I and Session II. Each session payoff was determined by performing one gamble randomly chosen from the list of ten decisions in the elicitation task (Appendix B). For instance, suppose I chose Option B for decision 4 in this particular session, and the computer rolls a 10. My session payoff is $0.40. The same calculation would be done for the other session, and the two session payoffs would be averaged to compute my total payoff. Thus, while payoffs were based on gambles, subjects knew for certain that each of the two sessions would carry equal weight in their total payoffs. To avoid potential time-preference confoundsFootnote 6, subjects received their payoffs by check in their campus mailboxes about a week after Session II was completed. The mean payoff was $4.42, and there were no show-up fees.
4 Results
The only difference between the “Wealthy then Poor” (N=65) and the “Poor then Wealthy” (N=65) treatments is the order in which subjects observed the future wealth frames. The main reason for including these two treatments was to test for order effects. Using Mann-Whitney U-tests to compare the results from the two Wealthy frames and the two Poor frames and a Wilcoxon test to compare the two sessions of the Control group (N=60), we find no statistically significant differences, indicating similar distributions across sessions. Thus we fail to reject the null hypothesis that there were order effects in the experimental treatments. In the absence of order effects, we aggregate subjects within each frame (or lack thereof) rather than within each treatment.
Holt and Laury’s (2002) risk aversion instrument yields implicit risk preferences. Under constant relative risk aversion (CRRA), a risk-neutral subject, for example, will choose Option A (safe bet) for the first four decisions, then Option B (risky bet) for the latter six decisions. Subjects who are risk-averse will choose Option A for more than four decisions before switching to Option B, while those who are risk-seeking will choose Option A for fewer than four choices before switching to Option B.Footnote 7 That said, we expect subjects to switch only once from Option A to Option B.
The vast majority of subjects (178 out of 190) chose Option A for some number of decisions before switching over to Option B, without ever switching again. In 21 cases, subjects chose Option B for every decision.Footnote 8 Only 16 subjects switched between Option A and Option B more than one time.Footnote 9 In the tenth decision—which offers a choice between a sure payoff of $8.00 and a sure payoff of $15.40—only 2 subjects in the entire experiment chose Option A, the lower payoff, most likely indicating that these 2 subjects might not have fully understood the instructions.Footnote 10
To measure subjects’ degrees of risk aversion, I observed the number of times the subject chooses Option A, the safe bet. Recall that payoffs are constructed such that a risk-neutral utility-maximizer under CRRA will select Option A for the first four decisions and Option B for the latter six. CRRA coefficients can be inferred using the number of safe bets chosen by subjects. In particular, if a subject chooses Option A four times, her CRRA coefficient, ρ, is approximately zero (the range could be −0.15 < ρ < 0.15). If the number of safe bets exceeds four, then ρ > 0; if the number is less than four, then ρ < 0.Footnote 11 Since the purpose of this study is to determine whether future wealth frames affect individuals’ degrees of risk aversion, I simply compare how many safe bets they make in the decision experiments under each future wealth frame.
Table 1 reports the number of safe choices (out of 10 possible choices) made by subjects within each frame. Subjects who were given the Wealthy frame make, on average, 3.89 (sessions pooled) safe bets, while those in the Control group make, on average, 5.32 (Session I) and 5.45 (Session II) safe bets. Mann-Whitney U-tests allow us to reject the hypothesis that subjects who saw the Wealthy frame do not make fewer safe choices than those in the Control group (H1). The difference in safe bets made is, in fact, statistically significant in both Session I (p=0.0010) and Session II (p < 0.0001). Also, subjects who were given the Poor frame made, on average, 5.62 (sessions pooled) safe bets. However, Mann-Whitney U-tests do not allow us to reject the hypothesis that subjects who saw the Poor frame do not make more safe choices than those in the Control group (H2). The difference in this case is not significant in Session I (p = 0.31) or Session II (p=0.18). Figure 1 represents the mean number of safe choices by frame with confidence intervals.
In the within-subjects comparison, behavior changes in the expected direction. The vast majority (83 out of 130) of subjects given the frames chooses more safe bets in the Poor frame than in the Wealthy frame, while relatively few (16 out of 130) subjects choose more safe bets in the Wealthy frame. A Wilcoxon signed-rank test finds that difference in behavior across the Wealthy and Poor frames is significant (z=−6.86, p<0.0001). Interestingly, some (31 out of 130) subjects also appear to not change behavior across frames.
By analyzing differences in the number of safe choices made under the future wealth frames (i.e., the Wealthy and Poor frames) and the Control group, we are able to infer differences in risk propensities across these frames. In particular, we find that subjects given the Wealthy frame are significantly more risk-seeking than those given no frame (the Control), and that those given the Poor frame are only not quite significantly more risk-averse than those given no frame. Thus, subjects were significantly more risk-seeking when asked to imagine themselves as wealthy in the future, but not quite significantly more risk-averse when asked to imagine themselves as poor in the future. In other words, imagining oneself as wealthy in the future does, in fact, affect current risk aversion, while imagining oneself as poor in the future may not. Note as well that the between-subjects design alleviates concerns about experimenter demand effects.
These results are confirmed when comparing decisions made under future wealth frames with the Control group within each session.Footnote 12 The results are robust even when we restrict the sample to subjects who never switched from Option A to Option B more than once.
Table 2 reports the summary statistics of the demographic variables collected after Session II. Table 3 reports the results from ordered logistic regressions of the number of safe choices made (a proxy for risk aversion) on sex, race, international student status, income, parents’ education levels, and the number of people in their households. Reported coefficients are proportional odds ratios and each observation is one subject in the experiment. The first two columns report results from the set of regressions in which subjects are pooled by each of the two sessions. This allows us to isolate the effect of each wealth frame compared to the Control on the number of safe choices made by subjects. Here we find that the subjects who see the Wealthy frame can be expected to make significantly fewer safe choices than those in the Control group, all else equal. However, subjects who see the Poor frame do not make significantly more safe choices than those in the Control group.
Coefficients represent proportional odds ratios; standard errors in parentheses
*** p<0.01
** p<0.05
* p<0.1
The second set of two columns reports results from a set of regressions including demographic variables. Here our results are confirmed even when controlling for these demographic factors. Subjects given the Wealthy frame can be expected to make significantly fewer safe choices than those in the Control group, all else equal. Note that this difference is significant at the 5% level in Session I and at the 1% level in Session II. We observe still that subjects given the Poor frame do not make significantly more safe choices than those in the Control group. Certain racial and income categories as well as number of people in household appear to be statistically significant, but not across both sessions, so it is unlikely that these characteristics have robust effects on risk aversion. After employing these controls, the same results hold. In particular, after controlling for demographic factors, those who are asked to imagine they will be wealthy in the future are still significantly more risk-seeking, while those who are asked to imagine they will be poor in the future are not significantly more risk-averse.
To know that we are identifying the true effects of the frame manipulations, we must rule out the alternative explanation that variation in the number of safe choices subjects make is caused by different actual wealth expectations. In other words, we must confirm that these differences in risk aversion are caused by the imagined future wealth frames and not by perceived future wealth. Consider the final (third) set of two columns, which include all the demographic variables as well as expected income brackets. In the survey, subjects were asked to select from a list what they expected their income to be ten years after graduating from college. While this is somewhat subjective, it is appropriate to include these as regressors when subjects were asked to consider hypothetical scenarios about their futures. Note that including these income brackets does not change the main results: we see significant risk-seeking behavior when subjects are exposed to the Wealthy frame and we do not see more risk aversion when subjects are exposed to the Poor frame. This shows us that variation in the number of safe choices is likely not caused by beliefs about expected income.
5 Discussion and conclusion
The results of this study indicate that (H1) individuals who are asked to imagine that they will be wealthy in the future make riskier decisions, but that (H2) those who believe they will be poor in the future do not make less risky decisions. These results are inconsistent with the common assumption of decreasing relative risk aversion. EUT with decreasing relative risk aversion predicts that risk aversion should be a decreasing function of future wealth. Reference Guiso, Jappelli and TerlizzeseGuiso et al. (1996) argued that, if people expect future borrowing constraints then they should optimally keep fewer risky assets in their portfolios, all else equal. In examining the link between risk aversion and financial risk tolerance, Reference Faff, Mulino and ChaiFaff et al. (2008) found that high-income people were more willing to bear financial risk than low-income people. In addition to financial investment decisions, theory predicts similar results for consumption (and thus, savings) decisions (Reference Drèze and ModiglianiDrèze & Modigliani, 1972; Reference LelandLeland, 1968). So, while the results from the Wealthy frame are consistent with these past claims and results, the results from the Poor frame are not.
One possible explanation of the results above is that each frame changes the decision problem subjects face. EUT can be defined in the domain of income (EUI) generated within the experiment, or in the domain of wealth (EUW) which exists outside the experiment. In EUT, consumers integrate payoffs into their wealth positions, yet Reference RabinRabin’s (2000) critique points out that EUT predicts implausible risk aversion when stakes are large. Reference Cox and SadirajCox and Sadiraj (2006) showed that a model which incorporates EUI is immune to Reference RabinRabin’s (2000) critique. In the current paper, the Poor frame might lead subjects to think in terms of EUI since future “wealth” is small. On the other hand, the Wealthy frame might lead subjects to imagine how their overall wealth changes, which could explain large changes in risk-taking in line with EUW. Reference Harrison, Lau and RutströmHarrison et al. (2007) echoed this point that risk attitudes depend on income rather than terminal wealth. The way subjects distinguish between laboratory income and wealth can be partially explained by mental accounting (Reference Heinemann, Cox and HarrisonHeinemann, 2008; Reference Rabin and ThalerRabin & Thaler, 2001).
Much research has been devoted to demonstrating and explaining why Americans tend to save below the optimal rates. Behavioral economics has taught us that myriad reasons might affect savings decisions, including hyperbolic discounting (Reference LaibsonLaibson, 1997), other issues with intertemporal choice (Reference Loewenstein and PrelecLoewenstein & Prelec, 1992), desire to achieve high-wealth status (Reference Cole, Mailath and PostlewaiteCole et al., 1992), and mental accounts (Reference ThalerThaler, 1990). While these behavioral considerations may all partly affect savings decisions, the results of the current paper suggest that people who imagine they will be poor in the future are not risk-averse enough, or that people simply cannot imagine that they will eventually be poor. The latter implies that those who imagine they will be poor do not have enough of a precautionary savings motive to adequately insure against future negative income shocks (Reference KimballKimball, 1990).
That subjects responded to the Wealthy frame, but not the Poor frame is in line with previous research about the use of hypothetical payoffs. Reference Holt and LauryHolt and Laury (2002) measured risk aversion using hypothetical as well as real payoffs and found that when stakes were high subjects were less risk-averse when payoffs were hypothetical. In the current paper, rather than manipulating whether payoffs are hypothetical, we use hypothetical levels of future wealth. Thus it is reasonable that subjects would respond less to the hypothetical Poor frame than they might if actually faced with that level of wealth.
On a related note, the results bring into light an additional methodological concern regarding the Reference Holt and LauryHolt and Laury (2002) risk-elicitation method. Recent studies have shown that risk measures using the Reference Holt and LauryHolt and Laury (2002) task are not only uncorrelated with other risk measures (Reference Dulleck, Fell and FookenDulleck et al., 2011) and other risk-taking behavior in the lab (Reference Lönnqvist, Verkasalo, Walkowitz and WichardtLönnqvist et al., 2010), but are also not stable over different sessions. In the current study, it is notable to also point out that Reference Holt and LauryHolt and Laury’s (2002) risk-elicitation method is not robust to framing, particularly with respect to hypothetical future wealth.
Some issues pose challenges to the extent to which we can generalize these results. First, undergraduate students at elite institutions are not necessarily characteristic of the population at large. In particular, the students in the experiment were relatively homogeneous with respect to socioeconomic background, so it is possible that the Poor frame was less plausible to many of the subjects. Subjects like these might have difficulty imagining themselves as poor in the future; or, alternatively, their current tight budgets might make the Poor frame more real in the present, rather than in the future. Second, since the experiment was conducted in an online laboratory, it is possible that some subjects did not fully comprehend the instructions. But because only a few subjects switched between safe and risky bets more than once, this would not likely change the results. Third, the scenarios posed to subjects could elicit something tantamount to a good news/bad news effect, which could potentially limit the extent to which we can generalize. It could be interesting, for example, to examine how imagined wealth affects current mood. Fourth, this research could be enhanced by the inclusion of more than two wealth frames—specifically less extreme ones—so that more nuanced observations could be made. Finally, future research should consider utilizing more contextualized risk experiments (e.g., insurance decisions) to test how future wealth frames might affect more applied risk decisions.
Appendix A: Frames
Wealthy frame
Imagine that in several years, due to some mixture of wise choices, hard work, and good fortune, you have become very wealthy. You own a large house or apartment with no mortgage or other types of debt. You earn a very high salary at work and have lots of disposable income. You can purchase expensive items, treat yourself to elegant meals, and travel on luxurious vacations. When you see something you like, you do not need to think about whether you can afford it. You never have any financial troubles and paying bills is never an issue.
Poor frame
Imagine that in several years, despite your hard work and seemingly smart choices, you have become very poor. You cannot afford to pay the rent or the mortgage on your small home, and you are burdened with loans that need to be paid off. You earn a low wage at work, have almost no disposable income, and struggle to make ends meet. For the most part, you purchase items only when you absolutely have to. You almost never eat out or treat yourself to nice things. When you see something you like, all you can think about are the bills you have to pay and the payments on your loans. You are in financially dire straits with everything from bills to buying groceries and other essential items.