Introduction
Although expressivism has been studied in relation to criminal justice since the emergence of modern international criminal law,Footnote 1 an expressivist perspective in norms and criminal justice research has resurfaced in the past decades,Footnote 2 inviting a new viewpoint on the dynamic interplay between norms and symbolic action in International Relations (IR). The expressivist literature situates expressivism as a distinct account of punishment. Yet the problem is that expressivism as an account of punishment has been criticised for being too abstract and lacking an immanent meaningFootnote 3 or for its dialectic position in relation to punishment.Footnote 4 Addressing this theoretical shortcoming, the article seeks to remediate our understanding of norm expressivism, establishing new knowledge of the meaning of norm expressivism in IR theory and criminal justice and clarifying the relationship between expressivism and notions of punishment and criminal justice.
The novelty and overarching value-added of this article consist in demonstrating how expressivism – traditionally seen as a distinct account of punishmentFootnote 5 – can play a normative role even if punishment in the form of trials and prosecution is not embraced. I argue that even in the absence of judicial proceedings in a courtroom, the intentions entailed by expressivist rationales can have a reinforcing effect on the legal order. To this end, the article makes a multidisciplinary theoretical contribution to norm research in IR, International Criminal Law (specifically criminal justice), and penal philosophy. On the one side, the article contributes to the literature on norm research in IR, complementing existing scholarship on norm complexity and interaction. On the other side, it advances norm expressivism frameworks in criminal justice research, in particular, the storytelling framework. Empirically, it unpacks the rhetoric of countries’ delegates at the United Nations in the aftermath of Russia’s full-scale invasion of Ukraine.Footnote 6 I examine several examples of rhetoric expressed in relation to the interconnected ideas of accountability, punishment, or criminal justice: disagreement pronouncements, denunciation of norm violation, postulation of guilt, and penal analogies.
I utilise foundational literature on punitivityFootnote 7 to clarify the relationship between punishment and expressivism. Nietzsche’s scholarship on the genealogy of Guilt is particularly useful to unearth the entanglements between the guilty, the victim, and the IR community and to show how norm expressivism manifests and is practically articulated in the judicial realm. The conceptual rooting of this article in both International Law and IR is underpinned by the multidisciplinary originsFootnote 8 of expressivism, with many theoretical influences still remaining untracked.
To empirically unpack the expressivist rhetoric, this article examines the Ukraine-related debates at the United Nations, both in the United Nations Security Council (UNSC) and United Nations General Assembly (UNGA). I look at the period 24 February 2022–24 March 2023, seeking to untwist the way the expressivist idea of criminal justice and punishment – which I define as a form of penalty, sanctioning, or countermeasure in reaction to a wrongdoing – has appeared during those debates. To this end, this article will empirically enrich the scientific debates on norm expressivism, which, with few exceptions,Footnote 9 largely draw on instances of expressivism in the courtrooms.
The paper proceeds as follows. The next section explains the expressivist framework of analysis and its linkage to norm research in IR and criminal law. Additionally, I seek to deconstruct current debates by referring back to the foundational literature by Nietzsche, in an attempt to have a prima facie moral-philosophical discussion of punishment, which I then apply empirically to IR. The third section explains the hermeneutic-interpretative approach employed in this analysis. The fourth part presents the rhetoric related to norm expressivism at the United Nations in the period studied. The subsequent section discusses the significance of rhetoric and norm expressivism, and how they interact, clarifying the relationship between norm expressivism and criminal justice. I conclude that expressivist action provides the roots of falsifiable propositions with regards to norm breach, as well as guilt and responsibility attribution, creating paths to accountability. Without an expressivist perspective, we would fail to grasp how speech acts play a role in shaping the long-term development of accountability, moral aspirations, and institutional memory within international organisations, shaping political decisions and judicial action.
An expressivist account of criminal justice in IR
Existing scholarship has traditionally situated expressivism as a distinct accountFootnote 10 of punishment.Footnote 11 I define expressivism in IR as practices of representation of, and the articulation of, a moral reaction towards a certain behaviour of a political actor, embodying a reflexive moral commitment or attitude. Through expressivist practices, political actors, such as states or other international agents, project a certain moral desire. Being practised usually in a context of norm violation or law breach, expressivism resembles ‘an articulation of the appropriate reaction to criminal acts on the part of the society, government, or other institution’,Footnote 12 aiming to consolidate trust in norm validity and attribute responsibility.Footnote 13 Norm expressivism and its relationship to criminal justice and punitive practices matter in IR, especially when these pertain to the illegal use of force. War is prohibited under international law, and while one could expect that leaders will seek to avoid commencing wars that enhance their risk of being held accountable and punished, international crimes and atrocities continue to occur. This points to the crisis of authority in world politics, stressing the challenges that established international norms can face.Footnote 14
Norm complexity and norm interactions have increasingly been the object of study in norm research in IR, especially from the perspective of norm-related behaviour and speech acts. Following the seminal article on norm change by Sikkink and Finnemore,Footnote 15 ensuing strands of research have addressed in depth the issue of fragmentation and norm collision in IR,Footnote 16 international norm contestation,Footnote 17 norm robustness and international cooperation,Footnote 18 or norm complexity.Footnote 19 One notable contribution is the work on the conceptual framework of complex relations and interactions between international norms, which points towards the investigation of norms relations, norm interactions, and their effects.Footnote 20 At international organisations (IOs), countries’ delegates can engage in norm linkage in their speeches through various argumentative strategies such as conflict arguments, cluster arguments, or synergy arguments.Footnote 21 While previous studies have identified the justification strategies that can be employed at the level of IOs, the manifestations of norms expressivism in the judicial space, and especially the nexus between expressivism and the idea of punishment and how norm-related behaviour and speech acts relate to individual norms or norm dynamics, have received little conceptual attention in IR.
The idea of studying international responses and normative dynamics in relation to the Russian war in Ukraine is not new.Footnote 22 Theorising the responses to actor’s behaviour in response to Russia’s invasion of Ukraine, Gholiagha and Sienknecht distinguish between responsible, irresponsible, appropriate, and inappropriate behaviour, showing the emergence of a new international norm, that of the responsibility to support.Footnote 23 Examining examples of key lines of argumentation and speech acts, Bosse demonstrates how the European Union’s 2022 response to the invasion was underpinned by normative considerations, among other factors.Footnote 24 Even though generalised punishment (understood in this article as criminal accountability and effective prosecution) through the application of criminal law might take years or might never happen, it is urgently necessary to understand what happens until then, and how this is linked to the idea of punishment. The post-norm violation phase at international level is crucial not only because it shows the articulation of reactions of the global community to an international wrongdoing – which can form the basis for documentation of the norm violations and legitimation of the eventual criminal accountability – but also because an expressivist account embodies a response to norm violations and societal expectations.
In international criminal justice research, expressivism has traditionally been understood as a function of punishment,Footnote 25 with previous studies having examined the semantics associated with criminal justificationFootnote 26 or the normative legacies of narratives in domestic and international law.Footnote 27 Since the influential piece by Feinberg situating expressivism as a distinct account of punishment, it was perceived that an expressivist turn is emerging,Footnote 28 yet this is in the search for meaning. Expressivism in relation to punishment is mainly conceived as an ‘appropriate reaction’Footnote 29 to a criminal wrongdoing, bearing the idea of articulating international norms and conveying meaning.Footnote 30 The link between expressivism and criminal justice’s idea of punitivity is visible at the practice level. Expressivism is a component within a recurring process that involves the dynamic interaction among norms, criminal acts, and the delivery of punishment as a message.Footnote 31 In international criminal justice, expressivism can play crucial functions as a mode of justification for penal practices or as expressivist action taken by an authority in response to norm transgression.Footnote 32 While retribution communicates that there is no excuse and no room for tolerance when it comes to serious human rights violations, retribution alone is not enough to justify punishment.Footnote 33 Expressivist punishment’s conceptual relevance pertains to bridging the ‘divide between deontological and consequentialist justifications of punishment’.Footnote 34 Bringing international criminal justice and society closer to each other, expressivism gives utterance to the crime’s severity and to societal punitive expectations in international criminal justiceFootnote 35 at the same time. Expressivist accounts of criminal justice articulate ‘messages in relation to individual wrongdoing and allocation of responsibility’.Footnote 36 Yet the mode through which this responsibility materialises is conceptually little understood. Seeking to address this shortcoming, one of the aims of this article is to debunk the nexus between the context of responsibility attribution and expressivist criminal justice. To this end, and complementing studies linking expressivism and the penal philosophies of Hegel or Durkheim,Footnote 37 this article employs the work of Friedrich Nietzsche, in particular his genealogy of Guilt, which I explain further in this section.
While punishment can entail distinct forms of penalty, expressivism is associated with a form of penalty or damage at normative, symbolic, and communicative levels. An expressivist account of punishment can produce normative harm by conveying disagreement with the wrongdoer’s actions and postulating the offender’s guilt. Denunciations of norm violations through speech acts and performative practices can contribute to the affirmation and projection of international values and norms.Footnote 38 Whether at communicative, motivational, or symbolic level,Footnote 39 these expressions may manifest themselves via mnemotechnics, the evocation of emotions, or rituals associated with guilt. Expressivism is concerned not only with the construction of messages but also with how these are received by diverse audiences.Footnote 40 In its expressivist meaning, punishment is employed to enable awareness and a historical acknowledging that the law was broken. It is thus the act of expressing and articulating, along with the established agency, that is at the heart of the expressivist account of punishment. Connections in the form of strategic linkagesFootnote 41 can be established to justify positionalities, such as support or opposition for UN resolutions. Here, Nietzsche’s genealogy of GuiltFootnote 42 is useful to better grasp the expressive idea of punishment in order to understand the entanglement between guilt, responsibility, and punitivity, and to comprehend the role of emotions in the punitive behaviour.
Relating expressivism to punitivity and penal philosophy, and drawing on Nietzsche’s genealogy of Guilt, this article shows how the Guilt and responsibility of the offender in relation to a crime is being embedded in the institutional consciousness and international memory. Guilt and responsibility are interlinked: ‘guilt implies the consciousness of guilt, and punishment evidence that the criminal is a responsible person’.Footnote 43 Nietzsche explains the genesis of guilt in the Second Treatise of his book On the Genealogy of Morality: A Polemic. To the question ‘How has Guilt come to be in the world?’, Nietzsche draws the genesis of guilt from the material aspect of Schuld, which in German has double etymology, meaning both guilt and owing someone something such as financial debt, or based on an agreement.Footnote 44 He asserts that guilt is as old as the idea of legal subject and is entangled with notions such as agreement and exchange, emphasising the relational aspect of Guilt.Footnote 45 Nietzsche claims that notions such as responsibility and conscience are genuinely embedded in the moral sphere of Guilt.Footnote 46 In effect, the idea of accountability and punishment in its expressivist manifestation in the post-norm violation phase resembles the idea of establishing a historical moment materialising the responsibility of an offender in relation to a crime.
An expressivist account of international norms, in contrast to a norm complexity approach – which refers to the interactions between norms, and which I discussed earlier in this section – depicts how articulations and speeches at the United Nations, as well as continuous manifestations inducing international shame, damage, and harm,Footnote 47 can be interpreted as activating the remembering of norms due to its production of agony. As Nietzsche puts it: ‘One burns something so that it remains in the memory: only what does not stop hurting remains in the memory.’Footnote 48 This implies that the violation of norms can be understood as a phenomenon of forgetting the rules. Sovereign actors and the idea of free-will are considered to be bounded by responsibility towards norms and conventions.Footnote 49 Pain, which is viewed by Nietzsche as a penalty for being guilty of a wrongdoing, is considered the strongest way to activate mnemonic processes and make norms unforgettable. Pain is defined as the infliction of damage or losses on the wrongdoer.Footnote 50 Punishment is thus an expression of treaty law and norms in the present and its perennialisation through making it part of the institutional memory and reflexive conscience of guilt in IOs.Footnote 51 Emotions are important as they can intermediate the production of guilt perceptions but might also shape whether punitive behaviour is adopted or not.Footnote 52 Recalling past atrocities can highlight the destructive potential of a crime, through leveraging emotions and retrospective processes of remembering past crimes. At speech level, this can create new understandings of when a norm is violated, how a norm violation can be ascertained, and whether it warrants punitive actions and sanctioning.
The reason why the notion of punishment requires an expressivist framework is because expressivism can be seen as an approach to solving the old problem of retributionFootnote 53 (consisting in finding convergence on the objectives and the criteria for retribution) and the problem of consequentialism (which implies a moral system that might leave wrongdoers unpunished). While expressivism and retribution share the idea of holding the wrongdoer accountable, expressivism is one manifestation of punishment, being ‘part of the language, articulation, and representation through which legal agents and the field as a whole manifest themselves in relation to others’.Footnote 54 Both in international criminal justice and IR, retribution is characterised by a series of challenges, such as the challenge of establishing the necessary and sufficient conditions for ‘postulating guilt’,Footnote 55 or having to deal with the problem of ‘postulating guilt in law and in morals’.Footnote 56 Further interconnected challenges are the issue of a ‘fluffy Leviathan’, referring to the fuzziness of international authority and the lack of consolidated judicial structureFootnote 57 in IR, along with uneven, interdependent poles of power in the international order.Footnote 58 These matters have been problems of retribution since the establishment of the system of international law after the Second World War and are exacerbated in a contemporary context of contestation,Footnote 59 as well as by the moral indeterminacy of norms and international law.Footnote 60 An expressivist account of criminal justice in IR is important not only because it shows the articulation of reactions to an international wrongdoing, but also because it marks a response to norm violations and societal expectations. In other words, even though local and global judicial bodies established to prosecute war crimes face difficulties in fulfilling their objectives of punishment for past wrongdoings and discouraging future offences, they can intermediate the advancement of expressivist aims,Footnote 61 and this article unearths the modes through which expressivist aims manifest at the level of IOs.
The proposed conceptualisation of expressivism advances the literature on criminal justice in International Law and norm research in IR. In regard to International Law, and particularly international criminal justice, this article shows how norm violations are illustrated at IO level, and how this is linked to the idea of punishment through, for example, penal analogies. In particular, it advances the norm expressivism framework developed by Carsten StahnFootnote 62 by adding an additional layer helping us to better understand the associations between norm violation and crucial notions, such as guilt, responsibility attribution, accountability, and punishment, in international criminal justice research. Highlighting the role of mnemotechnics or emotions, my framework not only furthers the concept of ‘storytelling’Footnote 63 in norm affirmation dynamics by proposing concrete mechanisms through which storytelling can happen, but it also adds a theoretical distinction to the literature on punishment and norm expressivism by focusing to a greater extent on the penal purpose. A focus on the penal purpose is important for a better understanding of the link between expressivism and punitivity, which has been often criticised for being vague or too abstract. In IR, this article unpacks the nexus between norms and expressivism, complementing existing studies on norm complexity. Specifically, it delineates between different manifestations of norm expressivism within the judicial realm, showing how norm-related behaviour and speech acts connect to individual norms and norm violation.
Methodological considerations
This research builds upon previous studies harnessing UN debates or international narratives to unveil normative aspects of IR and criminal justice. The idea of studying the rhetoric of international elites in relation to reasoning and justifications for criminal law is not new.Footnote 64 Following previous scholarship examining UN debates and international discourses,Footnote 65 I build a methodology showing how meaning unfolds and how words are made to matter in the international judicial realm. I study the expressivist manifestations and responses to norm violation based on the Ukraine-related debates at the UN, both in the UNSC and UNGA, and how criminal justice was implied. I look at references made during the period 24 February 2022–24 March 2023, and I hermeneutically deconstruct how the expressivist idea of punishment has appeared during those debates. I chose to look at this period because all UN resolutions in relation to Russia’s full-scale invasion of Ukraine were adopted during this period. What Russia has attempted with Ukraine – an imperial takeover of a neighbouring territory through a war of conquest in which the aggressor threatens the use of nuclear weapons – has ignited one of the largest armed conflicts in Europe since the Second World War.Footnote 66 After screening the debates in the UNGA and UNSC in relation to Ukraine, I hermeneutically identify the representational modes that seek to unveil crimes or punctuate the violation of specific, identifiable norms. Involving an encounter with philosophy and language, hermeneutics constitutes an interpretative methodFootnote 67 focused on understanding texts and how expressions and representations intermediate cognition and verdict. In this corpus, I examine how guilt, responsibility, or accountability are articulated, but also how the links to judicial prosecution, retribution, attribution and criminal justice more generally are made, creating the institutional memory at the UN. Starting from the assumption that expressivism can break silence around crimes and reinforce the universal non-impunity norm and the idea of ‘Never again’,Footnote 68 I distinguish between several manifestations of expressivism in the international realm.
Manifestations of norm expressivism following Russia’s full-scale invasion
Several rhetorical patterns are related to the idea of punishment and criminal justice and include references involving disagreement pronouncements, denunciations of norm violations, postulation of guilt, and penal analogies. These manifestations can be in a relationship of mutual reinforcement and can often overlap. I lay down the different types of manifestations of normative expressivism in Figure 1.
It is assumed that references are deliberately selected and used by international institutions, and that thus, through language, they try to persuade. Previous research demonstrates that linkages can be explicitly made to promote prosecution and norms,Footnote 69 and my research contributes to a greater understanding of these linkages, investigating their genesis, implications, but also their agentic power. The idea of the discursive agency that can emerge in IOs is reinforced by the Ghanaian UN representative, who claimed that:
As the collective custodians of the peace of our world, we must take every necessary action to strengthen the present fragile order. That includes using these debates to send a clear, unified message of support for the Charter and international law, the bases for a stable international system. Not doing so would lead the world towards a historical path of division.Footnote 70
Disagreement pronouncements
Disagreement pronouncements are international practices that express a judgement of disapproval,Footnote 71 in which judgement is distinct from emotions, condemning international conduct of states or other actors. Expressions of disagreements contain a judgement of the offender’s denial of the legal order. Expressions of disagreement and disapproval involve rhetoric in which agents express their opposition to the wrongdoer’s behaviour and norm denial.
The UN resolution ES-11/4, adopted by the General Assembly during its 11th emergency special session in October 2022, entitled ‘Territorial integrity of Ukraine: Defending the principles of the Charter of the United Nations’, condemned the organisation by the Russian Federation of the illegal so-called referendums and attempted illegal annexation of territories in Ukraine, reaffirming commitment to the sovereignty, independence, unity, and territorial integrity of Ukraine within its internationally recognised borders. It called Russia’s actions in Ukraine ‘a violation of the territorial integrity and sovereignty of Ukraine and inconsistent with the principles of the Charter of the United Nations’ and demanded that Russia ‘immediately, completely and unconditionally withdraw all of its military forces from the territory of Ukraine within its internationally recognized borders’.Footnote 72 The resolution was adopted with a historical level of support with 143 votes in favour, 35 abstentions, and 5 votes against (by Belarus, Nicaragua, North Korea, Russia, Syria). During the meeting, delegates of member states gave speeches and expressed their support for the resolution, while articulating disagreement with Russia’s actions. Disagreement was expressed through clear articulations of condemnation and rejection of the wrongdoing.
During the debate on the voting of draft resolution ES-11/4, expressions of disagreement were articulated either negatively, by expressing condemnation or outrage, or positively, by expressing alignment with a resolution condemning the violation of norms by Russia. The intervention of the Italian delegate exemplifies these two types of expressions of disagreement. Maurizio Massari expressed his country’s alignment with the statement delivered by the representative (observer) of the European Union. He ‘reject[ed] and unequivocally condemn[ed] the illegal attempted annexation by Russia of the Ukrainian provinces of Donetsk, Kherson, Luhansk and Zaporizhzhya’, claiming that ‘such unilateral annexation is void and cannot have any legal effect’ and that ‘Italy deplores in the strongest terms the sham referendums in Ukrainian territories occupied by Russia during its war of aggression against Ukraine’.Footnote 73 Disagreement was expressed through the condemnation of the illegal attempted annexations on the one hand and expression of alignment with the position of the European Union on the other. Alignment with other states produced a multiplicatory effect, expressing a multitude of agencies, and thus gaining additional legitimising potential. Importantly, disagreement with Russia’s actions was expressed by countries from all continents,Footnote 74 showing the global dimension of the antagonism and rejection of Russia’s actions. For example, the Liberian representative condemned ‘the violence, threats of violence and other acts of intimidation increasingly taking place in Ukraine by Russia and joins other Member States in calling for an end to the chaos and tumult’.Footnote 75 Similarly to the Italian representative, Cecilia Forgbe Wreh-McGill of Liberia articulated a dimension of solidarity and unity with the other member states that had expressed their disagreement.
In expressing disagreement, consternation, and condemnation, some countries stressed that the message was targeted towards the political leadership in Moscow, and not to the Russian people, with the Swiss delegate stressing that: ‘Our clear condemnation of the military aggression is based on the principles of the Charter of United Nations and the international legal order in force and is not directed against the Russian people.’Footnote 76
A further manifestation of the proposed expressivist approach is the denunciation of norm violation.
Denunciation of norm violation
The denunciation of norm violation refers to showcasing the wrongdoer's violation of specific, identifiable and tangible norms. The denunciation of norm violations can document the instances of breaking the law, helping to identify the specific legislative provisions that were broken, and, ultimately, for which the offender is perceived responsible. Denunciation of norm violations might have some degree of overlap with disagreement pronouncements, yet references expressing denunciation of norm violation are distinctive, involving a narrative process specifying concrete norms that have been broken. During performative speech acts at the UN, delegates have articulated the concrete norm violations by Russia. Normative moments have been created through the denunciation of the breaches of the UN Charter, or other concrete international law treaties and conventions.
Many countries denounced Russia’s violation of the prohibition of the use of force (Art. 2 of the UN Charter), seen as a cornerstone of international law. For example, the Romanian representative stated that ‘the actions of the Russian Federation are based on the illegal use of force and represent serious violations of the most important principles and norms of international law, enshrined first and foremost in the Charter of the United Nations’.Footnote 77 Other countries, such as San Marino, articulated and condemned the violation of international legal principles of proportionality and protection of civilians. The San Marino delegate stated that his country ‘strongly condemns the indiscriminate and disproportionate attacks on civilians, including through indiscriminate shelling, air strikes and the use of explosive devices in densely populated areas’ and highlighted that ‘the international humanitarian law in this area is clear’, stressing the norm of protection of civilians.Footnote 78 The delegate for Canada stressed the deliberate violation of international law and illegality of Russia’s actions in Ukraine, including of the so-called referendums. He claimed that ‘the actions of the Russian Federation clearly violate the Charter of the United Nations and the customary principle of international law that no acquisition of territory by the threat or use of force shall be recognized as lawful’, highlighting that Russia’s actions in Ukraine constitute ‘an illegal invasion, an illegal occupation and an illegal annexation’.Footnote 79
Some countries have listed the precise violations and infringements of international legal norms by Russia. Papua New Guinea sponsored the resolution ES-11/2 on the humanitarian consequences of the aggression against Ukraine, which was adopted with 140 votes in favour, 5 against, and 38 abstentions. Condemning Russia’s use and threat of use of force, Mr Sarufa claimed that:
Not only is the threat or use of force and of nuclear weapons a clear violation of the United Nations Charter and international law, but it is also contrary to the commitments Russia made in the Budapest Memorandum, the Review Conferences of the Parties to the Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons (NPT) and the statement by the five NPT nuclear-weapons States in January that a nuclear war cannot be won and must never be fought.Footnote 80
Moreover, Italy has also clearly articulated the violation of the Helsinki Final Act, which established the Conference on Security and Co-operation in Europe (later OSCE), created during the Cold War to enable dialogue and cooperation, and to which both Ukraine and Russia are party: ‘Such actions constitute a flagrant breach of the Charter of the United Nations and blatantly violate international law and the principles of the Helsinki Final Act.’Footnote 81 Other countries have emphasised Russia’s non-compliance with demands from the International Court of Justice ordering the suspension of Russian military operations in Ukraine, as the French representatives Mr De Rivière highlighted: ‘It is clear that Russia has in no way complied with that decision.’Footnote 82 Congo has condemned the violation of norms such as the ‘independence, sovereignty and the territorial integrity of Ukraine’ while also seeking legitimation by openly stating, as have many other countries, its voting position in support of the resolution and demanding an end of the norm breach: ‘Democratic Republic of the Congo will vote in favour of draft resolution A/ES-11/L.5, as we did for the first three resolutions on Ukraine.’Footnote 83
Postulation of guilt
Postulation of guilt refers to expressivist practices that unveil and expose the blame and attribution of responsibility for a wrongdoing, enabling moments during which the wrongdoing and the attribution of the responsibility of the wrongdoer for breaking the law are being ascertained. Rhetoric blocks, in the form of short references during speeches expressing postulations of guilt, might have a degree of overlap with denunciation of norm violation. Yet they are distinct from denunciation of norm violation in that they pronounce the guilt and responsibility. Hence, they constitute a more advanced phase than the expression and denunciation of norm violation and represent a phase in which the perpetrator is pronounced guilty. The materiality of the expressions of guilt intermediates what Nietzsche calls a conscience of guilt, which is articulated through contractarian logics of responsibility, accountability, and blame in relation to breaking of a contract or agreement. Nietzsche situates the concept of guilt, conscience, and responsibility in the moral realm of legal and normative obligations. During addresses at the UN, delegates have postulated Russia as being guilty and responsible for: violating the UN Charter, abusing its veto in the UNSC, violating criteria of UN Human Rights Council membership, committing atrocities, or creating a humanitarian crisis, inter alia.
To enable the exposition and subsequent documentation of guilt and responsibility, the resolution A/RES/ES-11/5, ‘Furtherance of remedy and reparation for aggression against Ukraine’, also seeking compensation and support for the victim, was adopted on 14 November 2022, with 94 votes in favour, 14 votes against, and 73 abstentions. The creation of a registry of damages set by the resolution was seen as essential for documenting the instances of guilt and recording evidence for damages, losses, and injuries caused by Russian aggression, as the Montenegrin delegate put it:
With this draft resolution, the General Assembly recognizes the need to establish an international mechanism to compensate Ukraine for the damage caused by Russia’s aggression. The draft resolution recommends the creation of a registry of damages to serve as a record of evidence and claims of damage, loss and injury caused by the aggression of Russia.Footnote 84
Some countries have emphasised the utility of an eventual register of loss and damages by Ukraine to be established through the resolution, as a potential mechanism to punish the wrongdoings and hold the offender accountable through trials and prosecution in the future. As the Mexico delegate put it: ‘Accountability is an inescapable part of the rule of law’, and ‘there are judicial processes under way that may lead to the establishment of mechanisms to repair damages and, of course, to punish those responsible for them’.Footnote 85 Other countries have expressed support for the ongoing investigations, perceived as preparatory retributive steps for punishing and holding the wrongdoer accountable:
We reaffirm our support for the ongoing investigations and processes that would eventually lead to the identification of the perpetrators of all violations in order to hold them to account for their actions, or inactions. The world cannot afford impunity in the face of such egregious violations in Ukraine.Footnote 86
Several states clearly expressed the guilt of the wrongdoer while stressing their expectations for punitive action to enable accountability: ‘The perpetrators must not go unpunished for unleashing such brute force and for violating international peace and security.’Footnote 87 Another delegate highlighted the imminent danger of leaving such conduct unpunished:
Ukraine is a victim of forceful territorial acquisitions, and if that is left unsanctioned it could become the worst precedent of the beginning of the decay of the international order generations have strived to build in the aftermath of devastating world wars to ensure the lasting reign of peace and prosperity.Footnote 88
Leaving the violation of norms unsanctioned was viewed by the two representatives as a dangerous precedent, in the sense of ontologically endangering the legal order enacted by the UN Charter and other treaties and conventions. In addition, failure to hold the perpetrator accountable for the wrongdoing was perceived as bearing the risk of further breaches of sovereignty or other fundamental rights enshrined in the rules-based order.
Expressions of guilt at the UN do not automatically mean that the perpetrator has sensed guilt or perceived itself as guilty. Countries might exhibit shame and guilt or not, depending on their place in and relation to the international system.Footnote 89 Resolutions or statements blaming Russia of being guilty of starting an illegal war of aggression cannot compel Russia to feel guilty, but they can produce knowledge about how others perceive guilt, and what they perceive Russia as being guilty of. Mnemonic processes and the activation of emotions were found to shape the way guilt and penance are expressed.
Penal analogies through mnemotechnics and emotions
Penal analogy refers to the performative reconstruction of a past wrongdoing that was legally and judicially ascertained as a crime, being presented in a fashion of similarity vis-à-vis a current wrongdoing. Through mnemonic processes, the speeches of IOs’ delegates can convey new knowledge and enable the emergence of learning processes. Mnemotechnics is a ‘conscious learning technique’ in which ‘the elements of places and images (loci et imagines) are used to develop a kind of mental script that can be used to write in memory as if on a blank page’.Footnote 90 National and international discourses of memory resonate in these spaces as part of the daily agenda by remembering the past through discourse. Through the incorporation of memory by different states, such as Ghana or Albania, memories of the past are constantly changed in the current time. The process of remembering is continuously influenced by the present as well as present features such as habitus or identity, with remembering being ‘fundamentally reconstructive’, denoting a ‘shift, deformation, distortion, reevaluation’Footnote 91 or a renewal of remembering that can occur in the present.
References to the past have been made to enable a normative moment acknowledging that the law has been broken by using the past to validate actions in the present through an analogy. One example came from the Canadian representative, Bob Rae, who, remembering the past, made an analogy for Russia’s annexation of Ukrainian provinces, comprising a territory ‘about the same size as the three Baltic countries illegally annexed by Stalin in 1940’.Footnote 92 Rae mentioned that ‘we must remember that point because after the occupation of the three Baltic countries by the Soviet army, the rate of participation in the “elections” of the new constituent assemblies reached a staggering 99.6 per cent in 1940 following the invasion and annexation by Stalin’s Government’, and that figure of over 99 per cent ‘resembles the results of the so-called referendums held in the four illegally occupied regions of Ukraine that Russia has just attempted to annex’.Footnote 93
In an intervention at the UNSC, the Ukrainian representative, Serhii Dvornyk, quoted from the Nuremberg trials against the propaganda by the Nazi regime, to enable an analogy to the contemporary propaganda by the Russian government, claiming that ‘the history of the past contains powerful reminders of what happens when one nation, poisoned with propaganda inciting hatred, waged a war of elimination against other nations and peoples’.Footnote 94 Dvornyk revealed in his speech a constatation by the Nuremberg Tribunal in the judgement against Julius Streicher, a prominent Nazi propagandist: ‘In his speeches and articles, week after week, month after month, he infected the German mind with a virus of anti-Semitism and incited the German people to acts of persecution.’Footnote 95 The Ukrainian delegate further made an analogy about the ‘false claims about the discrimination against Germans’ that ‘were used as a justification for aggressive expansionism, annexation and atrocities’ and Russia’s practices in contemporary times.Footnote 96 To ascertain the accountability of those responsible for ordering crimes, Dvornyk argued that a tribunal should facilitate ‘a process of moral penance and deep reflection on the role of that country and its army in the atrocities committed in Ukraine’.Footnote 97
Oftentimes, references to the past are intertwined with emotions. Remembering past atrocities can simultaneously elicit emotions of anger and discontent, exposing the destructive potential that Russia’s actions in Ukraine can have. For example, mentioning the root causes of the Holocaust, the massacres in Rwanda, the genocide in Srebrenica, and ethnic cleansing in Kosovo, the Albanian delegate highlighted that they did not come out of nowhere, but they ‘were planned through well-elaborated programs based on a common elements’ such as ‘words deliberately chosen to dehumanize the other, which would then be followed by bloodshed’.Footnote 98 He continued his speech by emphasising that a similar dynamic is present in the case of Russia’s aggression in Ukraine, too, and that:
Russia’s unprovoked military aggression in Ukraine is being conducted after years of aggressive rhetoric from all levels of the Russian State that has basically asserted that there is no Ukrainian language, culture or church, that Ukraine has no history and that it should have no future.Footnote 99
Emotions and the past are sometimes interwoven by the materialisation of a visualisation and imagination of the destruction and sufferings of the victim. A good illustration comes from the delegate of Guatemala, who stated that:
we are moved by the images of the more than 3.2 million Ukrainians fleeing their country, displaced by force as a result of the aggression of another State. Women, children, men, older persons – all of them fleeing a callous and appalling conflict, bringing to mind very similar images from the Second World War.Footnote 100
Through the employment of emotions and processes of remembering, speech acts at the UN have established new knowledge about when a norm violation is a norm violation and how we know that it deserves punitive action and sanctioning. I explain the entanglements between expressivism rationales and their relationship to international law in the following section.
Expressivism rationales and their relationship to international law
In this section, I elucidate the relationship between expressivism and international law.
From my analysis, expressivism emerges as a phase in which the wrongdoing is empirically ascertained. IOs, such as the UN, can serve as medium through which states articulate their political choices and punitive desires. A moment acknowledging that international law has been broken is established through speech acts at the UN, through condemnation of the norm violation, and through the demand for accountability. Not all speech acts demand punishment or condemn Russia’s actions, as demonstrated by the number of votes against or abstentions in relation to the adopted resolution. UN resolutions related to Ukraine after Russia’s full-scale military invasion have nonetheless been adopted by an overwhelming majority, clearly showing that a majority of UN states reject Russia’s actions in Ukraine.
Expressivism can manifest in different ways such as, for example, a pronouncement of disagreement, denunciation of norm violation, postulation of guilt, or penal analogies through mnemotechnics. Pronouncements of disagreement were expressed by states during UN debates in relation to Russia’s actions in Ukraine, such as the illegal attempted annexation of territories and the use of violence and threats of violence. A majority of states condemned the military aggression as being an unacceptable behaviour. This is demonstrated through the voting preferences displayed for the Ukraine-related UN resolutions. Not all states which voted in favour of Ukraine have delivered a speech. Among those who did, many delegates used strong words to signal positioning and the gravity of the crisis, such as ‘unequivocally condemn’ or ‘deplore in strongest terms’, expressing disagreement and denial of such conduct. In their speeches, states expressed norms such as territorial sovereignty, prohibition of the use of force, and proportionality, articulating how Russia violated some of the foundational principles and norms of international law. Major concern and outrage were expressed in relation to the infringements of the UN Charter, which is the backbone of the modern international legal order. Delegates also mentioned specific legal provisions that Russia infringed, such as the Helsinki Act, the Budapest Memorandum, Review Conferences of the Parties on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons, decisions of the International Court of Justice, and the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide.
Disagreement pronouncements and denunciations of norm violation synergistically overlapped with expressions of guilt, in which delegates postulated the guilt of the offender. Guilt was also expressed through sustained open support for the resolution A/RES/ES-11/5 ‘Furtherance of remedy and reparation for aggression’ that, inter alia, ‘recognizes that the Russian Federation must be held to account for any violations of international law in or against Ukraine, including its aggression in violation of the Charter of the United Nations against Ukraine’.Footnote 101 The resolution recommended the establishment of an international register and evidence-gathering mechanisms run by member states to document norm violations, and losses and damages suffered by Ukraine, to facilitate retributive steps and hold Russia accountable.
Following my analysis, the relation between expressivism and punishment becomes very clear. Expressivism operates within the judicial sphere, manifesting in forms of accountability, as well as guilt and responsibility attribution for identifiable norm violations. Expressivist accountability involves activities like monitoring, reporting, or interpreting behaviours perceived as norm violations, such as atrocities or aggressions. Although the expressivist account of punishment does not de jure punish the perpetrator in the sense of judicial prosecution and sentencing, it enables a historical moment acknowledging and documenting the norm violations, with IOs epitomising the locus where expressivism unfolds. Moreover, shimmering the unique contribution of this article, my analysis shows that expressivism can have a normative effect even in the absence of trials and prosecution in a courtroom.
Although one of the features of the judicial sphere in IR is that it consists of sovereign states, and it lacks an overarching authority that embodies similar levels of power and coercion monopoly that characterise nation-states, my analysis shows how IOs can exert control and coercion as sanctioning actors. UN resolutions have arguably been instrumental for multiple packages of sanctions adopted to sanction Russia’s aggression in Ukraine. Moreover, after it invaded Ukraine, Russia was expelled from the Human Rights Council following the UNGA Resolution A/ES-11/L.3. Hence, IOs constitute an important pole within the judicial sphere in IR, and their legal authority emerges from adopted resolutions. By means of the aggregate performances at the UN, delegates can enable and authorise resolutions stipulating future sanctioning or coercion. Delineating the concrete instances of law breaking might be useful for potential future judicial steps and prosecution. Figures of speech or appeals to emotions can elevate the persuasive potential for support, e.g. for a resolution. They can also have an amplifying effect through expressed multiplication and solidary alignment with the position of other states in the protection of collective legal orders.
The overlap between expressivism and punishment or criminal justice manifests not only at the inferential, but also at the normative level. Both expressivism and the retributive philosophy on which the idea of punishment and criminal justice rest are grounded in a contractarian logic in which the wrongdoer is perceived to have a right to be punished,Footnote 102 and the international community is perceived to have a collective responsibility to enable holding the offender accountable. This contractarian logic illustrates the entanglement of expressivist punishment with Nietzsche’s moral philosophy and interpretation of liability as a debt situation. The wrongdoer is indebted not only to the victim, but also to the order whose rules (s)he has deliberately broken.
A further synergy and overlap between expressivism and a retributive penal philosophy is the ascertainment of guilt and responsibility, and Nietzsche’s genealogy of Guilt helps us to unearth the profound entanglements between expressivism and criminal justice. Here, the offender’s violation of established law and norms is seen as a denial of a contract or agreement, and the punitive action as a negation of this denial.Footnote 103 At the UN, this is enacted through an expression of disagreement and condemnation, and thus as a concrete negation of the wrongdoing. The guilt of the offender is postulated through oral interventions that become written statements and video records, and thus pieces of evidence. This clearly illustrates the idea of punitivity as an expression of an awareness of Schuld.Footnote 104 The guilt is ascertained and embedded in the institutional and international consciousness projected by the UN. The consciousness of the UN is seen as an abstracted form of Self,Footnote 105 working as a palimpsest in which norms and ideas are expressed. The Schuld of the offender is mnemotechnically materialised through expressive performances embedded in the institutional memory. These evoke the wrongdoer’s responsibility towards the legal order associated with the UN. Being bounded by this order, infringements of commitments endanger the ontology of the very legal order. Speeches at the UN represent the medium through which expressions of disagreement, denunciations of norm violations, postulation of guilt, or penal analogies are enacted. What is remarkable is that throughout the period 24 February 2022–24 March 2023, many expressions and phrases of condemnation and postulation of guilt repeated themselves. These repetitions appear as rituals of pain that are embedded in the institutional memory of the UN. As Nietzsche put it: ‘One burns something so that it remains in the memory: only what does not stop hurting remains in the memory.’Footnote 106 While the expressive practices at the UN do not induce the wrongdoer’s concrete pain, they can reinforce actual punitive actions, such as sanctions that cause pain in the form of financial losses and exclusions from international foraFootnote 107 or which can instigate pain in the form of a stigma effect for the wrongdoer.
The use of memory has also been instrumental in eliciting emotions at the UN in relation to Russia’s actions in Ukraine. Through intertwining national and international memory discourses and historical analogies, delegates have sought to legitimise their positions through historical analogies. If a wrongdoing such as, for example, Russia’s annexations of Baltic states in the past was deemed illegal, this was considered to yield illegality for similar actions in the present. Through materialising a visualisation and imagination of the destruction and sufferings of the victim, remembrance of past atrocities, such as the Holocaust, and the genocides in Rwanda or Srebrenica, IO delegates can evince emotions with persuasive potential.
To conclude, expressivism can lay down a phase of condemnation, ascertaining the crime through the exposition of guilt, materialisation of responsibility, and establishment of normative moments acknowledging that the law was broken. In an expressivist philosophy of punishment, states appear as moral agentsFootnote 108 that can exert punitive agency through expressivist practices. During speeches at the UN, states can use certain language and semantic expressions to justify their positionality towards an international wrongdoing. Although concrete punishment that can disenable the wrongdoing has not been taken and actual international trials in a courtroom have not yet started, an expressivist account of punitivity can help legitimise sanctioning, judicial action, and the restoration of rights. Expressivist practices shape the context in which concrete punitive actions, such as sanctions against Russia or the mandate warrant by the International Criminal Court against Russian president Vladimir Putin, are taken. The diverse practices of sanctioning norm violations indicate that IR involve a form of punitive action that is more than just an interim or substitute phase for a criminal law procedure.
The expressivist framework proposed in this article pursues a penological purpose of its own. This embodies the normative expression of disapproval of norm denial as well as postulation of wrongdoer's guilt. This is not to say, however, that the expressivist account of punishment, which through articulations, representations, and performative manifestations takes the shape of a practice in its own rights, can escape contestation,Footnote 109 norm conflict,Footnote 110 deviance,Footnote 111 resistance,Footnote 112 or entanglements with authority, interests, and morals.Footnote 113 This was demonstrated by the lack of support and absence of expression of condemnation by countries that are friendly towards Russia or by previously colonial countries’ low support for the resolution A/RES/ES-11/5 ‘Furtherance of remedy and reparation for aggression’.
Conclusion
This paper examined norm expressivism in International Relations and International Law. The core contribution, and the novelty of this article, consists in showing how expressivism, which is classically viewed as a distinct approach to punishment, can serve a normative function even in the absence of court proceedings and prosecution. I demonstrated that even in the absence of trials, the intentions behind expressivist justifications can have a normative reinforcing function for the legal order. In doing so, the article provided a multidisciplinary theoretical contribution to International Criminal Law (specifically criminal justice), norm research in IR, and penal philosophy.
First, by advancing the literature on criminal justice,Footnote 114 particularly the work by Carsten Stahn, this article shed light on the meaning of expressivism and the relationship in which it stays vis-à-vis punishment. Specifically, this article further developed the ‘storytelling’ framework of norm expressivism proposed by Stahn.Footnote 115 I have illustrated how norm expressivism can manifest as pronouncements of disagreement, denunciations of norm violations, postulations of guilt, or penal analogies. Yet these examples are not mutually exclusive and are non-exhaustive. Moreover, this article has clarified the relationship between expressivism and criminal justice. It has revealed how normative expressivism is associated with conceptual elements of retributive philosophies of punishment through illustrations of expressivist rhetoric and performative practices at the UN in the aftermath of Russia’s full-scale invasion in Ukraine.
Normative expressivism constitutes a performative phase within the judicial sphere, during which the wrongdoing is ascertained, the guilt and responsibility are postulated, and the need for accountability is expressed. Through normative expressivism, agents often seek to justify punitive action. Expressivism enables the establishment of customary knowledge in international normative and judicial spaces, such as IOs. It does so through establishing knowledge that specifies which norms have been violated, and creating normative moments in which norm violations are brought into linkage with punitivity. Although the establishment of new knowledge is dialectic, expressions of disagreement, along with the denunciation of norm violation, postulation of guilt and responsibility, and articulation of penal analogies, immediately create moments that might reinforce smaller punitive actions and countermeasures, such as sanctionsFootnote 116 or stigma-inducing punitive steps.Footnote 117 This becomes exceptionally relevant in the absence of an international Leviathan and universal prosecuting authority. Norm decay can be particularly prejudicial for endeavours seeking to maintain a peaceful international order.
Second, this article contributes to the norm research debate in IR. My article has sought to provide a building block for the norm interaction and norm complexity debate by exploring the nexus between expressivism and norms in the judicial realm in IR. The article complements previous studies on the justification strategiesFootnote 118 employed to promote criminal justice and punishment of mass atrocities at IOs. To this end, it elucidates how norm-related behaviour and speech acts relate to identifiable norms or norm dynamics, by unpacking the judicial space that emerges during international organisations' debates. Not only do these debates identify the specific norms that have been violated, but UN sessions personify instances during which evidence is provided that links the actions of the perpetrator to the infringement of a certain legal norm fixed in existing conventions or agreements.
Third, this article contributes to scholarship in penal philosophy, complementing previous work combining foundational scholarship and criminal justice. An established literature has documented the links between the work by Émile Durkheim and expressivism.Footnote 119 Complementing this literature, my article has added new knowledge on the largely overlooked Nietzschean scholarship. In particular, it demonstrated the utility of Nietzsche’s genealogy of Guilt in deconstructing the nexus between expressivism and criminal justice. Nietzsche’s work on punitivity proved useful to palpably exhume the meaning of the different examples and manifestations of norm expressivism, but also to understand how they mediate the emergence of responsibility attribution and accountability. By those delegates expressing condemnation, denunciating norm violations, postulating the guilt, or articulating penal analogies, the wrongdoer is perceived as deserving sanctioning, since an alternative behaviour compliant with the existing law and norms could have been chosen.Footnote 120
In sum, much attention has been paid to international responses and the positioning of states on the war against UkraineFootnote 121 or norm violations in IR.Footnote 122 While this literature has mostly focused on studying cleavages or alliances in the international system, by applying expressivist lenses, this article expounds how expressivist action epitomises a negation of norm denial. This approach enriches the existing literature in IR and International Law by delineating how expressivist practices contribute to the creation of international norms and accountability mechanisms, through disagreement pronouncements, denunciations of norm violation, postulations of guilt, or penal analogies. The provided examples describe processes of denial of norm violation or denial of treaty infringement. Expressivist action encapsulates a negation (or denial) by large parts of the international community of the initial denial of law by the offender. This bifold negation frameworkFootnote 123 provides the roots of falsifiable propositions with regards to norm violation, creating paths to accountability. Identifying the specific norms that have been broken, and providing evidence that links the actions of the perpetrator to the infringement of a specific legal norm fixed in existing conventions or agreements, the article clarifies how expressivism showcases norms violations and simultaneously reinforces the UN as a judicial space, even in the absence of judicial prosecution in a courtroom. In the UN judicial sphere, as in a panopticon, delegates embody the guardians of international norms and conventions, disavowing impunity and the denial of a victim’s rights to justice. Without the expressivist lens, we would miss the opportunity to capture examples and mechanisms of denial of norm violation. We would also miss understanding how rhetorical acts contribute to the long-term construction of accountability, moral desires, and institutional memory at the UN, shaping future judicial action.
Future research should unpack the metaphysical component of norm expressivism. This intertwining is important to future scientific inquiries, because it provides an understanding of what shapes underlying motivations behind norm adherence or norm violations. In addition, future studies could explore the dimension of norm expressivism in relation to Russia’s aggression in Ukraine between 2014 and 2022. It is simultaneously the violation of norms, the changing imaginaries about the international legal order, and the tension where the states take the freedom of both being and doing, that make the understanding of norms and norm dynamics in International Relations so urgently needed, as Russia’s military invasion in Ukraine has blatantly demonstrated.
Video abstract
To view the online video abstract, please visit: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0260210524000949.
Acknowledgements
The author is grateful to the three anonymous reviewers for their insightful comments and the Review of International Studies editors for their spot-on suggestions on the manuscript along the journey. I would also like to extend my gratitude to Antje Wiener, Rebecca Adler-Nissen, Peter Marcus Kristensen, Henrik Larsen, Halvard Leira, Kevin Jon Heller, Thomas Fraise, Maria Mälksoo, Anders Wivel, Neil Renic, Clemens Binder, Kristin Eggeling, Michele Betsill, Maja Zehfuss, Yevgeniy Golovchenko, Kristian Søby Kristensen, Jens Ladefoged Mortensen, Johan Grøne Christensen, and Mathilde Kaalund for their helpful comments on this paper. Thanks are due to Mark Drumbl, Brent Steele, Nina Græger, Stefano Guzzini, Wolfgang Wagner, Amitav Acharya, Oumar Ba, and Barry Buzan for having talked to me about earlier versions of this research and, through their abundant wisdom, helped me to apprehend some crucial aspects pertaining to criminal justice and punishment in International Relations. Previous versions of this paper have been presented at the ISA Annual Convention in San Francisco, as well as at workshops at the University of Copenhagen, University of Hamburg, and Danish Institute for International Studies.
Funding statement
This research was independently conducted without any external funding support.
Competing interests
I declare that I have no conflicts of interest to disclose.