Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-13T00:41:02.819Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

New Temporalities and a Temporal (Re)Turn in New Testament Studies? The Cullmann/Bultmann Debate Revisited

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 October 2024

Benjamin A. Edsall*
Affiliation:
Australian Catholic University; benjamin.edsall@acu.edu.au
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In light of a recent surge of interest in time across a range of disciplines, a case has been made that New Testament studies has experienced a “temporal turn.” This claim raises an important question about how one understands the relation of recent developments to earlier, long-held debates about time among New Testament scholars. This question is answered here by revisiting the “salvation history” debate between Oscar Cullmann and Rudolf Bultmann, with the help of Paul Ricoeur’s analysis in Time and Narrative and in the context of recent trends in work on “temporalities.” This article argues that, although in many respects recent work on time offers fresh language to describe the kinds of time at stake for New Testament scholarship, it is also true that attending to the earlier debates shows how parts of the temporal turn are in fact a return to questions long considered.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the President and Fellows of Harvard College

Introduction

Across a variety of humanities disciplines there has recently been increased interest in time, often under the broad rubric of “temporalities.”Footnote 1 According to Lynne Moss Bahr, even the field of New Testament studies, which has a long history with “time,” has experienced a “temporal turn.”Footnote 2 In her account, “theoretical developments from other disciplines” have enabled new perspectives, moving beyond the well-known “now-but-not-yet” construal of time for early Christianity long dominant in scholarship.Footnote 3 Even so, identifying a “turn” in intellectual habits or trends is difficult, and it is an open question at this point whether other scholars beyond those surveyed by Bahr would recognize that they have experienced any epochal change in their understanding of time.Footnote 4 Bahr’s claim, then, raises an important question: How should one understand these recent developments in relation to earlier debates about time among New Testament scholars? The purpose of this argument is to sketch an answer to that question by way of a kind of philosophical archaeology, returning to a once-major impulse still felt in New Testament scholarship on “time”: the salvation-history debate.

Debates among New Testament scholars about the shape, character, and meaning of time reached a particular fervor with the salvation history debate in the 1950s and 1960s, closely associated with Oscar Culmann (1902–1999) and Rudolf Bultmann (1884–1976). As I will argue below, while it may seem to have disappeared as a major sphere of intellectual conflict since then, its effects remain ongoing, even as both scholars continue to have a long legacy. Tracing key threads in this debate will offer a two-fold opportunity: first, to redescribe the Cullmann/Bultmann debate with the help of Paul Ricoeur, situating it within a long-standing philosophical debate about the nature of time;Footnote 5 second, to illuminate points of convergence and divergence between the views at stake in the salvation-history debate and some of the “theoretical developments” noted by Bahr. Paul Ricoeur helpfully functions as a common interlocutor for both old and new discussions of time, a Janus figure who can aid New Testament scholars in their movement between intellectual spaces. Revisiting and redescribing the Cullmann/Bultmann debate on Ricoeur’s terms clarifies fundamental issues at stake for those writers and thereby facilitates conversation with recent work on temporality. To begin, I will offer two brief orientations, the first to summarize the context and legacy of the Cullmann/Bultmann debate and the second to introduce some notable trends in recent work on temporality.

The Salvation History Debate and Its Legacy

The debate between Rudolf Bultmann and Oscar Cullmann about the nature of temporality—historical, Christian, existential, etc.—took place in the midst of a hive of scholarly activity, with numerous proposals related to history and eschatology being put forward: from the consistent (konsequente) eschatology of Albert Schweizer and his followers,Footnote 6 to the realized eschatology of C. H. Dodd,Footnote 7 to the Pannenberg circle’s proposals about “revelation as history,”Footnote 8 to the (slightly later) apocalyptic early Christianity of Ernst Käsemann.Footnote 9 Questions about whether or how historical time had meaning pervaded not only theological discussions concerned with the Christian’s relation to history and God, but also philosophical accounts.Footnote 10 In view of this, it is not surprising that the 1946 publication of Cullmann’s Christus und die Zeit generated considerable debate, in which he found himself particularly at odds with Rudolf Bultmann and those convinced by Bultmann’s existentialist hermeneutic.Footnote 11

When Cullmann first worked out his views on salvation history in the early 1940s, he did so at least in part in response to the work of the Marburg theologian; who, indeed, could avoid his influence?Footnote 12 For his part, while claiming to eschew any philosophy of history at all,Footnote 13 Cullmann’s presentation of salvation history was based fundamentally on a “simple rectilinear conception of unending time”Footnote 14 moving from “formerly” through “now” to “then” and generating the classic tension between the “now” and the “not yet.”Footnote 15 Within this schema, the present is defined by its being distinct from both past and future, which are, importantly for Cullmann, “a real past” and “real future.”Footnote 16 That is, the divinely appointed events of the past and future exist objectively,Footnote 17 apart from any particular person or vantage point, and occur along the “entire timeline” of history, running from creation to the eternal succession of the ages in the eschaton.Footnote 18

Bultmann, on the other hand, utterly rejected Cullmann’s linear account of temporality in favor of a radically eschatological and existential account of “the temporality of Christian existence.”Footnote 19 While he did not dispute that time continues in its most banal—even objective—sense, he argued that mere succession is not the important aspect of temporality relative to the New Testament.Footnote 20 Christian temporality is not marked by linear temporal succession but by an encounter with Christ (in the kerygma) as the eschatological event par excellence.Footnote 21 The only way one’s experience in the eschaton can be considered “temporal,” then, is to understand it as existing “in constantly new decisions,”Footnote 22 in a “now” that constitutes “an isolated moment without continuity with all that has gone beforehand.”Footnote 23 Faith, as genuine decision, cannot operate on the basis of “objective guarantees in the world.”Footnote 24 This applies to the past as much as it does the future. The relation of present and future cannot be one of causality and development for Bultmann, because the latter is nothing short of an act of God that stands outside the process of world history and to which one must remain radically open.Footnote 25 In short, where Cullmann prioritizes an objective, linear account of historical time within which the Christian is situated, Bultmann rejects this in favor of a subjective, existential constitution of temporal experience.

Over the course of the 1970s, within the field of New Testament studies, the heated debates about the salvation historical paradigm cooled as scholarly energies shifted to other topics.Footnote 26 Additionally, for many in the latter half of the twentieth century, the perceived theological and institutional entailments of salvation history have placed it beyond the pale: in the context of our present political and ecclesial woes, what sense could there be in sacralizing the status quo, even “sanctifying the sadistic”?Footnote 27 Moreover, the salvation history debate itself became closely connected with the debate around “apocalyptic,” the character of apocalyptic literature and its interest in eschatology, building on and engaging with the work of Ernst Käsemann in particular.Footnote 28 As David Congdon has noted, the result of this link has been that, within current debates about “apocalyptic,” scholars tend to argue either for observable, divinely determined, future events in the world (i.e., analogous to Cullmann’s objective account of historical time) or “something nonliteral, transcendent, and indirectly or paradoxically present” now (aligned with the view of Bultmann).Footnote 29 Of course, aspects of Bultmann and Cullmann’s arguments also remained influential among various other exegetical and theological discussions—from hermeneutics and theological interpretation to ecumenical discussions between Protestants and Catholics—and, indeed, in the beginning of the twenty-first century, each scholar has had something of a renaissance.Footnote 30 The continued presence of both Cullmann’s and Bultmann’s accounts of time (historical, eschatological, Christian, etc.), therefore, is now simultaneous with new works announcing a “temporal turn” in the field, thereby pressing home the question of how the two are related. Before we can begin to bridge the “old” and the “new,” however, a brief orientation to the latter is necessary.

A Brief Trip through Time

Tracing the rise and the various threads of recent work on temporality is highly complicated and fraught with pitfalls, not least because of the inherently self-reflexive quality of such accounts, which requires that one “be alert to the temporal forms of historical analysis and representation, and to temporal assumptions and habits that shape fields and objects of knowledge.”Footnote 31 In the present case, moreover, there is no single fountainhead or trajectory that serves as a reference point for something like “temporality studies.” Instead, there appears to be parallel developments across several disciplines, each of which positions itself within a particular intellectual genealogy.

On the one hand, there has been a steady stream of contributions from the philosophy of history. Scholars such as Hayden White have argued influentially, if controversially, that all historiography is subject to certain narrative conventions inherent to narrative representation, including chronology, teleology, plot (or emplotment), and moral evaluation.Footnote 32 To this discussion, Paul Ricoeur has contributed considerably. His major works—stretching at least from The Symbolism of Evil (1961) to Memory, History, Forgetting (2000)Footnote 33—constitute an extended philosophical reflection on the human experience of the world, mediated through language, represented as narrative (both fictional and historical), implicating both self and other in the process of remembering, memorializing, and forgetting.Footnote 34 Ricoeur’s work has emphasized, among other things, that there are multiple ways of conceptualizing time and that these can and do conflict with one another—cosmological time, monumental time, clock time, human time.Footnote 35 External reference to the world in historiographical accounts always comes by way of representation, of a symbolic “standing for,”Footnote 36 in which the past is (re)present(ed) in and for the present, with the social and political possibilities that implies. Ricoeur’s account of time, history, and narrative has proved influential, not only in subsequent philosophies of history but also across a variety of historiographical and sociological projects.Footnote 37

Among narratologists, debates about the centrality and character of time are long-standing. The early work by Mikhail Bakhtin introduced the (somewhat underdeveloped) term “chronotope,” which attempts to articulate the way in which narrative time is bound to narrative space, and the configuration of the two together constitutes differing modes of representing time within narratives.Footnote 38 Later, in his general theory of narrative, Gérard Genette influentially articulated the distinction between story and narrative in which the chronological order of the underlying story differs from the order of the narrative presentation.Footnote 39 More recently, the disruptive and pluralizing possibilities of this division have been emphasized by Mieke Bal, who expands Genette’s division into a three-tiered narrativity.Footnote 40 The temporality of narratives, on Bal’s account, includes a variety of complicating factors—matters of sequential ordering, rhythm, and frequency—that help to account for what she calls “multi-temporality,” referring to the contemporaneous and conflicting presence of multiple temporal frameworks. She calls this experience “heterochrony.”Footnote 41 Representing temporality in narrative, then, is complex precisely because human temporal experience is itself complex.Footnote 42

Alongside these threads, much recent work on temporality is found in queer theoretical approaches to literary, visual, and historical materials.Footnote 43 One factor that is particularly prevalent is the emphasis on the role affect (or emotion, depending on the writer) plays in temporal frameworks and expectations.Footnote 44 In these works, the oft-presumed chronologies for growth, maturity, (re)production, and so on are illuminated as culturally constructed ways of marking time, conventional narratives, which are disjunctive with other temporal experiences.Footnote 45 For Carolyn Dinshaw, queer historiography is fundamentally an act in which historiographers and readers are affectively engaged with those who have gone before them: historians both engage in and offer their readers a “touch across time.”Footnote 46 This past can be important for retrieving a community over time, a heritage that otherwise risks not-being, and thereby structures actions in the present.Footnote 47

This is far too brief a summary of these intellectual trends, but I hope that it suffices to draw out a few observations. First, however inexorably the arrow of time appears to move forward, time is not in fact simply a uniform category, a precondition for activity or knowledge; it is experienced and even suffered by different people in different ways.Footnote 48 The present is “full and attached rather than empty and free-floating” with relation to both past and future.Footnote 49 The ability of narrative to link past, present, and future as well as narratological possibilities for representing multiple temporal regimes is a strongly recurring theme across these discussions, whether in terms of Ricoeur’s essential linking of narrative and varying conceptions of time, Bakhtin’s chronotopes and Bal’s heterochrony, or Dinshaw’s articulation of asynchrony.Footnote 50 Temporal experience is shot through with multiple temporal rhythms which can and do come into conflict—the time-related conflict experienced by an early career academic with young children jumps to mind, for instance—which can bring experiences of suffering, a sense of being “out of time” in multiple senses of the phrase.Footnote 51 As some recent work in anthropology has argued, moreover, temporal frames differ between cultural contexts, and different “chronotopes”—here, ways of construing the temporality of a relevant context—are able to disrupt one another.Footnote 52 Each moment, on this view, is a “pluritemporality” inhabited by objects and people acting, suffering, changing at different tempos and according to varying temporal logics.Footnote 53 In a related way, then, how we “tell” or “mark” time matters for how individuals and communities navigate questions of identity. Telling time is attached not only to technical skills (such as the development and use of clocks) but is in all cases inextricably bound up with cultural norms. The past may be gone, but it remains present insofar as we experience its traces and insofar as it shapes actions, identities, and possibilities in the present.Footnote 54 As one philosopher has recently put it, the “challenge for a phenomenological and philosophical account of time is not to provide one homogenous theory of time.”Footnote 55 Time and history are here deeply linked with narrative, experience, affect, identity, and plurality. These themes, in various guises, will return variously throughout this argument.

Redescribing the Salvation History Debate

I turn now to redescribing the Bultmann/Cullmann debate with the help of Paul Ricoeur. This accomplishes two principal goals: 1) it shows that any “return” to these thinkers should not aim to be a recapitulation—we shall see that they are insufficient as singular accounts of time—and 2) it will frame Cullmann’s and Bultmann’s accounts of time in a way that facilitates easier conversation with the concerns of recent work in the final section below. The first section here will focus on relating Bultmann and Cullmann to Ricoeur’s typology of philosophies of time, while the latter sections will turn to the “intertwining” of history and fiction in narrative emplotment and the inclusion of the reader in the mimetic interpretive process.

A. Cullmann, Bultmann, and Ricoeur’s Temporal Typology

As I sketched above, Cullmann and Bultmann present themselves as proponents of objective and subjective accounts of time, respectively—the former emphasizing “real” events on a salvation-historical timeline and the latter emphasizing the subjective, existential weight of decisions “now.” These two approaches of temporality occupy a fundamental place in Paul Ricoeur’s analysis in Time and Narrative. “A constant thesis” throughout the work is “that speculation on time is an inconclusive rumination,” with both objectivist and subjectivist accounts unable to incorporate fully the insights and concerns of the other.Footnote 56 Ricoeur’s “rumination” runs along two tracks presented across three pairs of philosophers, three moments of debate between subjective and objective accounts of time. On one side are Augustine, Husserl, and Heidegger, whose phenomenological account of temporality Ricoeur refers to as “the subjective time of the philosophers.”Footnote 57 On the other side we find Aristotle, Kant, and the “ordinary” conception of time rejected by Heidegger, all of whom attempt to ground their accounts of time in objective features in the world, apart from human perception.Footnote 58 Between these two sides lies a fundamental aporia, which neither line of argumentation can itself fill. The divergent views of Augustine and Aristotle set the terms of the subsequent discussion.Footnote 59

In book 11 of the Confessions, Ricoeur finds an account in which the lived experience of time assumes center stage. Time, as such, does not have independent being to which one has access, but it is instead characterized by the distentio animi—a stretching of the mind between memories of the past and expectations of the future. The present is marked by focused attention, intentio, which is attended by the distentio of memory and expectation.Footnote 60 Ricoeur notes, though, that beginning from internal experiences of intentio and distentio obscures the fact that, on Augustine’s own terms, the “mind begins by submitting to [objective] succession and even suffering it, before constructing it.”Footnote 61 In other words, Augustine is unable to derive the measurability of time, a key facet of objective accounts, from the experience of intentio and distentio and in fact tacitly borrows from a time that precedes and grounds human temporal experience. For his part, Aristotle begins from the opposite direction. Time, he notes, is measurable because it is “something of movement.”Footnote 62 That is to say, time is measured by movement and therefore takes on the spacial quality of magnitude in relation to the movement between two points in time, from the “before” to the “after.”Footnote 63 These points in time, like points in space, are inherently countable (if, strictly speaking, innumerable) as features of an objective temporal movement.Footnote 64 Time is, then, a series of instants, marked relative to the infinitely divisible movement of a body through space, without any place for a “present” as a privileged place for human experience.Footnote 65 Aristotle’s “before” and “after” do not map directly onto Augustine’s experience of past, present, and future, nor are they completely independent. Ricoeur argues, on the contrary, that there is a tacit interweaving of the two perspectives: the distentio animi tacitly presupposes a before and after across which the mind is stretched, while Aristotle’s time is “caught between movement … and the soul that observes it.”Footnote 66

As with Aristotle and Augustine, so also with the debate that follows. According to Ricoeur, Husserl’s phenomenological analysis in a way replicates Augustine’s distentio animi through his arguments about retention of the past and protention of the future, ever occurring in the present moment.Footnote 67 On the other hand, on Ricoeur’s analysis, Kant attempts to remove time from human perception; time, as such, is an infinite and infinitely divisible succession that exists outside perception and grounds judgments about duration, coincidence, and the like.Footnote 68 Both sides of the debate, he argues, fail to provide an account of the other that does not already rely on elements of the excluded view: “Each refers back to the other … a mutual borrowing, on the condition of a mutual exclusion.”Footnote 69 When it comes to Heidegger, he attempts to push the phenomenological/subjectivist view as far as he can, trying to account for perceived “objective time” (datability of events, shared/public time, etc.) as already related to a “primordial time” of Dasein, marked by the futurity of “being-towards-death” which determines the past and present.Footnote 70 Ricoeur argues that Heidegger nevertheless fails to provide a complete account of time, because from his “primordial time” one cannot derive a clear place for the priority of the “time of nature”—geological and evolutionary time—that entirely precedes human experience.Footnote 71 Ricoeur concludes his discussion of these two lines of argument by reiterating his central aporia: “we cannot think about cosmological time (the instant) without surreptitiously appealing to phenomenological time, and vice versa.”Footnote 72 In this way, Ricoeur’s typology presents objective and subjective accounts of time as opposing ways of accounting for time that always find themselves mutually implicating.

How, then, do Cullmann’s and Bultmann’s views of time fit into this typology? In view of Ricoeur’s philosophical interlocutors, two initial links are significant. While Cullmann continually denied the influence of any philosophy of history, at least one critic noted the deep affinity between his linear timeline and Aristotle’s objective and measurable series of instants.Footnote 73 For Cullmann, as we saw above, salvation historical events are fixed, divinely determined points of reference for the believer, which precede and exceed one’s own horizon and amid which one positions oneself in faith. Bultmann, however, offers a view of time that, if not indebted to, has at least been shaped by Heidegger’s formulation: the present is determined by its own future that, while radically absent, constrains the person into a position of constant decision.Footnote 74 For him, past and future only exist for the believer in the present “now,” the former radically relativized and the latter radically open. So far, they provide two more examples from the twentieth century that demonstrate the outline of Ricoeur’s temporal aporia.

In fact, the positions of Cullmann and Bultmann do more than this. While both profess to reject the views of their opponent, they do not in practice exclude the other. In the first instance, Cullmann’s salvation history is only intelligible from the perspective of faith—a particular faith, moreover, as articulated within the salvation historical framework as a whole.Footnote 75 Like Aristotle and Kant in Ricoeur’s analysis, Cullmann relies on a subjective, phenomenological aspect of time to authorize his claims about the ostensibly objective temporal succession in salvation history. Crucially for his view, Cullmann argues that while salvation history is an objective fact, open to investigation by all insofar as it speaks about historical events, it is only recognizable as salvation history from a perspective of faith.Footnote 76 The events involved are “not instigated by the readers, nor by the readers’ faith … having taken place apart from their faith—pro nobis, but extra nos.”Footnote 77 But the pro nobis illuminates the central role of a particular faith perspective; under normal historiographical conditions, one would not think of past events happening for the historian. Only from the perspective of “faith” can one see that Christ acts as the decisive “mid-point,”Footnote 78 in whose life, ministry, death, and resurrection all salvation history comes to a point and is accomplished there in nuce.Footnote 79

Bultmann’s existential account, on the other hand, surreptitiously retains a place for a meaningful historical event—something that happens apart from the believer and confronts them in their existential now. To be sure, Bultmann expends considerable effort on excising the Christ event from the normal course of temporal succession: “If the redemptive history were an objective event in a remote past, if it were ‘an objective redemptive history’ in that sense, liberal faith would be perfectly right in repudiating it.”Footnote 80 And yet, as Karl Jaspers noted, for all Bultmann’s criticisms of objective events in history, Christ remains an event experienced “by way of that miracle of about 1950 years ago.”Footnote 81 The Christ event stands as the eschatological event par excellence and it is that which confronts, addresses, affects believers—an actual event in history that, far from being erased or “consumed” by the past,Footnote 82 is consistently affirmed in Bultmann’s arguments.Footnote 83

The Bultmann/Cullmann debate, then, instantiates Ricoeur’s account of the aporia between subjective and objective views of time: neither is fully satisfying on its own and both tacitly borrow ground from the other. With that in view, we can turn to Ricoeur’s discussion of emplotment and mimesis which will set the stage to consider the salvation history debate in relation to recent concerns about the experience of time and the way in which history writing offers a founding “touch across time.”

B. Emplotment and Mimesis in Ricoeur

Ricoeur begins his discussion of narrative poetics, as he does so many other discussions, by turning to Aristotle, who supplies a crucial pair of concepts, muthos and mimesis. Both are taken by Ricoeur to designate a dynamic aspect of composition: the former is the act of emplotment, “organizing events into a system,” while the latter is “the active process of imitating or representing something.”Footnote 84 The former is the primary means of addressing the temporal aporia sketched above, while the latter attends to the larger communicative process within which emplotment is embedded.

The act of emplotment is a mediating activity, which is to say that it refers to bringing together particular and heterogeneous events, agents, interactions, contexts, and outcomes into a plot.Footnote 85 Furthermore, and importantly, plot mediates a variety of temporal characteristics—the anonymous instant, the personal present—in a poetic rather than analytic mode.Footnote 86 As an act of configuration, emplotment brings together this disparate material into a single unit, seen and mapped as whole. The tension between an authoritative “monumental time” and the “living times” of particular individuals, which have been severed by a “divorce between worldviews,” can be represented in narrative form.Footnote 87 Yet the narrative is designed to be read within the time emplotted, “to move forward in the midst of contingencies and peripeteia under the guidance of an expectation that finds its fulfillment in the ‘conclusion’ of the story.”Footnote 88

What is true of fictional narratives, Ricoeur argues, is likewise true of history writing.Footnote 89 Historians encounter a heterogeneous cast of characters, times, locations, motivations, which must be represented in the work of history, the representation of the past in the present.Footnote 90 The historian’s role in selection, arrangement, and representation is an act of emplotment in which the heterogeny is grasped together. Insofar as the historian engages in narrative emplotment—even given an intention of fidelity, of doing justice to the people and events in questionFootnote 91—there remains an inevitable “interweaving (entrecroisement) of history and fiction.”Footnote 92 Accordingly, there is no single narrative of history; the events and characters can always be selected, arranged, and represented from a different angle.Footnote 93 Nevertheless, each emplotment requires a “narrative coherence” in which one event leads to another toward a fitting conclusion, followable by a reader.Footnote 94

The second term Ricoeur borrows from Aristotle, mimesis, comes in at this point, with the engagement of the reader in the narrative process. This term signifies the dynamic quality of narrative composition—emplotment—and the role of imitation within a broader activity of communication.Footnote 95 Put simply, Ricoeur locates the activity of emplotment within a process that terminates not with the work but with the reader. The “entry of the work, through reading, into the field of communication marks at the same time its entry into the field of reference.”Footnote 96 The question of reference here is not a matter of historical verisimilitude—Ricoeur addresses that under the language of “standing for”Footnote 97—but is rather a matter of a relation between the world of the reader and that of the text.Footnote 98 Through a narrative resolution of the temporal aporia by emplotment, a reader’s experience of time can be reconfigured through their mimetic engagement with the temporal configuration in the work. Dissonances between different temporal frameworks—geological, official, political, biological, etc.—can be represented and, perhaps, even held together.Footnote 99 The historical understandings of individuals, communities, and societies are shaped by the narratives they transmit, even as dominant accounts are affirmed, rewritten, challenged, and rejected. The time in which a reader encounters these narratives, their present, is characterized by “acting and suffering,” a time of crisis “in the double sense of a time or judgment and a time of decision.”Footnote 100 As such, it is laden with ethical responsibility, to act well, to choose wisely, to promise, to intervene.Footnote 101 By placing the reader and work in a mimetic framework, then, Ricoeur articulates the reciprocal involvement of both parties, in which the reader interprets the work’s representation of its world, and the work shapes the reader’s experience of her world.

C. Emplotting (Salvation) History

We noted above how Cullmann’s objective account of historical time is achieved by borrowing from a subjective account, inscribing it by acknowledging that salvation history is only visible from a particular faith perspective. For Cullmann, it is this perspective that authorizes his presentation of salvation history as both part of and distinct from world history in its general sense. He notes: “By virtue of our birth we belong to many ‘histories’—the history of our family or the history of our nation.”Footnote 102 Salvation history, then, is simply one more “history” to which believers belong. Furthermore, Cullmann clarifies that salvation history, though linear, “is definitely not faith in an ‘unbroken’ causal connection, but faith in a connection revealed only by God, resting upon a completely incalculable selection of individual events.”Footnote 103 In other words, salvation history is fundamentally selective: only some events are taken up in elucidating the salvation historical schema; others are left behind as of no consequence to the development of salvation as (and in) history. Further, “their selection cannot be explained historically,”Footnote 104 which is to say that they are not inevitable within a supposed web-like continuity of historical causality. This aspect of his schema, Cullmann admits, raises the question about “whether one may properly use the expression ‘salvation history’ (Heils-geschichte).”Footnote 105 Indeed, as a highly constructed, selective account of discrete events, only visible from a particular faith perspective, Cullmann notes in one place that his view of Heilsgeschichte has a specific affinity with narrative.Footnote 106 In terms borrowed from Ricoeur, Cullmann’s salvation historical narrative—his Heilserzählung that runs from tragedy to comedy, the narrowing of election through disobedience and its broadening thanks to the work of ChristFootnote 107—is “a mediation between the individual events or incidents and a story taken as a whole … [and it] brings together factors as heterogeneous as agents, goals, means, interactions, circumstances, unexpected results.”Footnote 108

There is, further, a second level of historiographical selection at work in Cullmann’s account of salvation history, insofar as he admits that a complete narrative of salvation history is not present in any particular New Testament text.Footnote 109 Rather, it is Cullmann himself who articulates it—presenting an otherwise hidden unity of the New Testament witness by reading between the lines, using one text to fill out another, harmonizing apparent differences. In this process, he is interested in finding what “constitutes the common essence, according to the witness of the New Testament.”Footnote 110

Perhaps predictably, Bultmann rejects this account of history and Cullmann’s exegetical practice. On the latter point, he argued that “carrying up the statements of the various New Testament writings to the same level seems … to lead to an illicit harmonization.”Footnote 111 The writings in the New Testament display both variation and development over time, and he rejects any approach that does not give full weight to these differences.Footnote 112 Bultmann’s criticism of Cullmann’s harmonizing tendencies points to another crucial element of emplotment noted by Ricoeur: namely, that history is not a story that can only be told in one way. On Ricouer’s view of emplotted history, Cullmann’s schema, insofar as its emplotment selects and mediates various events, times, agents, can offer itself as a historical account or, at least, as “an analogy to history,” as he put it.Footnote 113 As such, his schema would remain perpetually open to rewriting from other perspectives. As a theological claim, however, it is not so open. Insofar as Cullmann claims to relate the plot within which all others must find their place—a path not subject to alternative itineraries—the “analogy” with history breaks down. Moreover, Cullmann’s claim that salvation history is the plot of history in the New Testament is undermined not only by Bultmann’s exegetical skepticism but by the very act of emplotment itself. There can be no question about whether Cullmann is merely “describing” some historical facet of early Christian thought; his schema extends far beyond the statements of any particular textual witness, encompassing even contemporary history,Footnote 114 and claims to lay hold of something behind the texts, a viewpoint (in faith!) that authorizes a particular reading of them. It is this latter claim, moreover, with its fixity and concomitant closure of (salvation) history, that Bultmann also rejects. As we have seen, Bultmann’s view of Christian temporality rejects development across past, present, and future. The eschatological event has already taken place, and it is what confronts us in the gospel.Footnote 115 Any emplotment of the believer amidst past, present, and future, then, is inherently problematic for Bultmann, insofar as it does not account for the existential position of the Christian in time. This leads, in the end, to the final aspect of this redescription of the salvation history debate, the problem of situating the believer in time.

D. Locating the Believer

As we saw above, for Ricoeur the process of emplotment is intimately connected with his framework of mimetic communication: narratives, particularly historical accounts, quietly include their readers and have the potential to shape their understanding of the self and the world. This experience is temporal as well as affective, ethical, and existential. Similarly, a major, perhaps even central, concern for both Oscar Cullmann and Rudolf Bultmann is to articulate the way in which every Christian relates to Christ—his life, death, and resurrection—who stands as a foundation for their faith and practice. Bultmann, for his part, wears this concern openly: in his “New Testament and Mythology” he famously begins with a concern to make the Christian faith intelligible to his contemporary Christians.Footnote 116 Historical events, as such, are not ultimately meaningful because true meaning requires an encounter between the believer and Christ “in the kerygma.”Footnote 117 It is in the present and presence of this encounter that one stands “in constantly new decisions.”Footnote 118 The enduring objective, external force of the Christ event is admitted into his theological program almost against his will—while maintaining the indelible specificity of the Christ event, it is something he attempts to minimize at every turn in favor of the existential encounter.Footnote 119 Cullmann approaches the inclusion of the contemporary believer from the opposite direction, working from his objectivist account of historical time and salvation history. These objective events, extrinsic to any given person, nevertheless implicate the believer in its totalizing timeline: salvation history comprehends the entire timeline from beginning to end, including the present of the early church and the present of contemporary society. This is not an accidental effect of Cullmann’s argument: it is essential.Footnote 120 Locating the believer within salvation history is what enables the connection between the believer and the saving event of Christ.

As a result of this focus on the particular Christian, every Christian, Cullmann and Bultmann both mark out the present for a special significance. It is the space in which one is confronted with the Christ event—either maximally in the sweep of salvation history or minimally in Bultmann’s stripped back account. Cullmann and Bultmann are both concerned with connecting the believer as directly as possible to Christ. In Cullmann’s own terminology, which could almost be mistaken for a line from Bultmann, all historical periods are “immediate” to this event.Footnote 121 The past is not “purely past. It must constantly give meaning to the present so that the present finds its significance and fulfils its task.”Footnote 122

The Salvation History Debate and New Temporalities

What remains to be done at this point is to highlight the ways in which the old debate between Cullmann and Bultmann, here redescribed with the help of Paul Ricoeur, anticipates, touches on, is developed by, and is otherwise ambivalently related to the recent trends in “temporalities” discussed earlier. There, several important threads were noted: the plurality of time, its affinity with narrative representation, its inextricable link with experience and affect, and the place of individual and communal identity formation in temporal frameworks. If I have done my job well, certain connections between the Cullmann/Bultmann debate and these newer studies should be immediately evident. In what follows, I will group my observations under three categories: 1) the enduring role of narrative emplotment; 2) the connection of temporal experience and affect; and 3) multi-temporality.

A. Narrative Emplotment

The gap between “story” and “discourse,” noted above, continues to be widely acknowledged and, importantly, the distinction between these two narrative levels is fundamentally temporal. The narrative order of events is rarely strictly linear, making use of anticipations, flashbacks, foreshadowing, and other mechanisms for interrupting time. From the perspective of Ricoeur’s arguments, one can see, too, that the gap in fictional narratives carries over into historical accounts, in which the historiographical act of representation likewise proceeds without strict linearity (in its use of appeals to later effects, background factors, comparisons, and structural correlations, among other similar tools). The time of the events and the time of the telling are inescapably different. Here, the Bultmann/Cullmann debate was nearly ahead of its time. From the vantage point of Ricoeur’s analysis and other accounts of narrative temporality, one is able to recognize Cullmann’s grasping together of heterogeneous events and agents for what it is, namely, a constructive act of emplotment. The affinity between salvation history and narrative, therefore, fits easily within a certain narrative-historiographical frame: the lack of direct and successive causal continuity between the events that constitute Cullman’s salvation historical narrative is permitted within the rhetorical and explanatory scope of historical accounts. Both Bultmann’s critique and Cullmann’s defense of his schema, however, show that neither were alert to this possibility; both writers resorted to arguments about the place of selectivity and a lack of successive continuity between events in salvation history.Footnote 123 For neither writer was there any positive role for the constructive activity of the history-writer, which stands in marked contrast with narrative historiographical work subsequently. Furthermore, it leads to a certain closure of Cullmann’s salvation historical schema: to the extent that he did not acknowledge his own role in constructing the account from otherwise disparate material, he conflated his voice and that of the New Testament authors, claiming that the latter only said what the former articulated (and vice versa). Only one salvation historical narrative, then, becomes possible. This does not appear to allow for the multiplicity of temporalities, which will be discussed below. Bultmann objected to such (exegetical and historical) closure, arguing instead for a radically open future and an ambivalent relation of the present and the past.Footnote 124 The multi-temporal and asynchronous possibilities in narratives and human experience, moreover, offer new vantage points on the meaning(s) of history as well as its representation.Footnote 125

B. Time, History, Affect

As we have seen for Cullmann and Bultmann, and in his own way Ricoeur, the place and role of the believer (or reader) is of crucial importance. It is, perhaps, not too much to say that the central point at stake in the Cullmann/Bultmann debate is how the Christian relates to the Christ event. For Cullmann, the grand sweep of salvation history encloses both within a common frame. For Bultmann, it is in the encounter “now,” in the kerygma, that one meets Christ. And yet, as outlined above, both writers retain language of another view: Cullmann epitomizes all salvation history in the Christ event and claims immediacy to that for all Christians; Bultmann retains a certain external, historical distinctiveness for the Christ event. The past remains a force in the present for both writers, not only in general but also for the spiritual life of Christians (individually and in community). The combination of internal, historiographical, and theological impulses in salvation history is never articulated as such. The recent work highlighting the deep links between history, temporality, and affect or emotions, however, sheds a bright light on the debate in question here. In Carolyn Dinshaw’s poetic terminology, what Cullmann’s salvation history offers is a “touch across time,” a historically construed community which is not in fact directly accessible to, and does not stand in direct (successive) continuity with, present readers. Bultmann’s existentialist account attempts to offer a more immediate intimacy with Christ, but even this remains, as we noted, a touch “by way of that miracle of about 1950 years ago.”Footnote 126 Other contributions of queer theory to the issue of temporality are relevant here. Bultmann’s critique of the historical and exegetical closure of Cullmann’s system could be nuanced by attending to the ways Cullmann’s temporal framework may be disjunctive with other temporal and historical experiences. If one accepts Cullmann’s view of salvation history as “chrononormative,” to borrow Elizabeth Freeman’s language, what does one make of voices who argue “salvation” is not a meaningful description of historical experience?Footnote 127 What would be the affective or emotional entailments of a disjuncture between Cullmann’s normative schema and the experience of those ostensibly enfolded by it? This leads, again, to the question of heterogeneous time, with which I will conclude.

C. Multi–Temporality

Perhaps one of the most widespread developments in studies of temporality is the growing consensus (if one can speak of such things) that time itself is plural, multiple, heterogeneous. This leads to categories of “heterochrony” (Bal), “asynchrony” (Dinshaw), and others. Cullmann acknowledged a certain multiplicity of “histories”—that of the family or the nationFootnote 128—though, given his central interest in articulating “salvation history” as the ultimate, cosmically determinative historical frame, he did not devote any space to reflecting on this multiplicity. Indeed, this is one area in which it appears that neither Cullmann nor Bultmann focused on anything remotely in proximity to the plurality of time. One might argue, though he did not, that Bultmann’s radically existential account of the “encounter” with Christ, along with his radically open future, allows for as many temporalities as there are people to experience them. Even more, the experience of the eschatological in the present articulates a kind of multiple-temporality: the banal procession of time does not exclude the eschatological experience any more than the encounter with Christ extracts one from the present world.Footnote 129 It is this kind of plurality, possible in every moment, that is of particular interest to recent discussions. Mieke Bal’s discussion of heterochrony is driven home with the example of the undocumented immigrant, caught in “a kind of social schizophrenia that makes the migrant always rushing and always stagnating at the same time.”Footnote 130 Likewise, Dinshaw’s asynchrony is pursued particularly in accounts of people being out of step with time, those like Rip van Winkle who inadvertently time travel in their sleep. But the endurance of the past in traces that affect the present is another example of such asynchrony.Footnote 131 In the case of the salvation history debate, is it possible for each event within salvation history itself to participate in multiple temporalities? Further, would it be possible for Cullmann’s schema to account for multi-temporal and asynchronous experiences as such, without turning heterochrony into being merely an aberration on a normative, cosmic history of salvation?

It is possible that these questions may be answered in the affirmative, though I do not know what Cullmann might say to such things. Bultmann, perhaps, could have offered an answer to these questions, though he never reflected on them directly. The purpose of the present argument, however, is not to try and retrieve or resuscitate one or the other of these views as an overarching theological paradigm or reading strategy. Rather, with the help of Ricoeur’s work, this article offers a kind of philosophical redescription of the salvation history debate in order to bring its dynamics and concerns into conversation with ideas arising from recent work on temporality. Bahr’s suggestion that New Testament studies has undergone a “temporal turn” is intriguing and helps illuminate the need to account for the relationship between old and new discussions of time. This argument is only an initial step, but what I hope is clear from the above discussion is that whatever the trend is among New Testament scholars, any temporal “turn” invites a return: here, returning to an interest in the way the reader/believer is implicated in the historiographical accounts we produce through our emplotments. And, in attending to the questions that time raises for scholars of the New Testament (and related materials in early Christianity and early Judaism), the new categories, frameworks, and perspectives in recent work on temporalities offer many new avenues of inquiry and much new light to be spilled on old materials.

References

1 See the helpful introduction to the history of “temporalities” in Matthew S. Champion, “The History of Temporalities: An Introduction,” Past & Present 243 (2019) 247–54, which stands as the introduction to a special issue of Past & Present.

2 See Lynne Moss Bahr, “The ‘Temporal Turn’ in New Testament Studies,” CurBR 18 (2020) 268–79.

3 Ibid., 268. Bahr’s article groups these developments under three categories: “social memory and historical narrative; queer and feminist theory; and apocalypticism and messianism.” The developments in question will be addressed below in relation to work on temporality within the philosophy of history, narratology, and queer theory.

4 Note the comments about a “temporal turn” in historiography in David Gange, “Time, Space and Islands: Why Geographers Drive the Temporal Agenda,” Past & Present 243 (2019) 299–312, at 299: “Prophecies of a ‘temporal turn’ have arisen every decade for half a century, with particular intensity at the end of the 1980s and in the present. They have never quite come true.”

5 This is accomplished primarily with the help of Paul Ricoeur, Temps et Récit (3 vols.; Paris: Seuil, 1983), and idem, La Mémoire, l’histoire, l’oubli (Paris: Seuil, 2000). In the discussion that follows, citations will principally refer to the excellent English translations of these works: Paul Ricoeur, Time and Narrative (trans. Kathleen McLaughlin and David Pellauer; 3 vols.; Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), and idem, Memory, History, Forgetting (trans. Kathleen Blamey and David Pellauer; Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004).

6 Albert Schweitzer, Von Reimarus zu Wrede. Eine Geschichte der Leben-Jesu-Forschung (Tübingen: Mohr, 1906).

7 Articulated clearly in C. H. Dodd, History and the Gospel (New York: Scribner, 1938).

8 Offenbarung als Geschichte (ed. Wolfhart Pannenberg; Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1961).

9 See Ernst Käsemann, “The Beginning of Christian Theology,” in New Testament Questions of Today (trans. W. J. Montague; London: SCM, 1969) 82–107, among other places. Cf. the contextualization of Cullmann’s and Bultmann’s views of time in Jörg Frey, “Heilvolle Zeit? Linear und existential verstandene Zeit in der Auslegung des Johannesevangeliums bei Oscar Cullmann und Rudolf Bultmann,” in Rudolf Bultmann, Oscar Cullmann Briefwechsel 1926-1967: Studien zum theologischen und exegetischen Austausch (ed. Michael Jost, Martin Sallmann, and Benjamin Schliesser; Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2022) 191–217, here 192–97.

10 See, e.g., Karl Löwith, Meaning in History: The Theological Implications of the Philosophy of History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1949), who engages with Cullmann on 182–90, and of course, the monumental impact of Heidegger’s Sein und Zeit (1927). Martin Bauspieß, “Geschichte,” in Bultmann Handbuch (ed. Christof Landmesser; Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2017) 314–23, at 314, notes that Bultmann had inherited his interest in the meaning of history from his teacher, Wilhelm Herrmann (1846–1922), while Hans-Georg Hermesmann, Zeit und Heil. Oscar Cullmanns Theologie der Heilsgeschichte (Konfessionskundliche und Kontroverstheologische Studien 43; Paderborn: Bonifacius, 1979) 55, situates Cullmann’s discussion of history within Protestant concerns since Lessing (1729–1781) and Semler (1725–1791).

11 Note the recognition of this fact in Karl-Heinz Schlaudraff, “Heil als Geschichte”? Die Frage nach dem heilgeschichtlichen Denken, dargestellt anhand der Konzeption Oscar Cullmanns (BGBE 29; Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 1988) 1, and Robert W. Yarbrough, The Salvation Historical Fallacy: Reassessing the History of New Testament Theology (History of Biblical Interpretation 2; Leiden: Brill, 2004) 236–37. In his review of Bultmann’s view of history, Bauspieß specifically highlights the critiques offered by Cullmann and Pannenberg; Bauspieß, “Geschichte,” 322–23.

12 As is evident by the recently published Briefwechsel, Cullmann and Bultmann began exchanging letters in July 1926 and maintained a friendly correspondence throughout their lives; Rudolf Bultmann, Oscar Cullmann Briefwechsel 1926-1967 (ed. Jost, Sallmann, and Schliesser), 3–56.

13 Oscar Cullmann, Christ and Time: The Primitive Christian Conception of Time and History (trans. Floyd V. Filson; London: SCM, 1962) xxiv, xxvi–xxvii. In his more developed argument in Salvation in History, Cullmann continued to insist that his view of Heilsgeschichte was established purely by exegetical description, without any appeal to a “philosophy of history” at all; Oscar Cullmann, Salvation in History (London: SCM, 1967) 61, 77.

14 Cullmann, Christ and Time, 35–37, 48. Note that Cullmann later clarified that salvation history cannot be characterized itself as “rectilinear,” though it retains its linear quality, as does his underlying conception of time; Cullmann, Salvation, 55; cf. the further discussion below and in Dietrich Braun, “Heil als Geschichte,” in Zehn Jahre nach Oscar Cullmanns Tod. Rückblick und Ausblick (ed. Martin Sallmann and Karlfried Froehlich; Basler und Berner Studien zur historischen Theologie; Zürich: Theologischer Verlag, 2012) 101–24, at 115, and Krzysztof Góźdź, “Cullmanns heilsgeschichtliche Sicht. Die Geschichte Jesu Christi und ihre Nachgeschichte,” in Zehn Jahre nach Oscar Cullmanns Tod (ed. Sallmann and Froehlich) 125–33, at 126.

15 Cullmann, Salvation, 38, 183; cf. his earlier comments on this tension in Cullmann, Christ and Time, 146, 155.

16 Cullmann, Christ and Time, 53.

17 For Cullmann’s discussion of “event,” see Cullmann, Salvation, 51–54, 84, 88; on the issue of objectivity, cf. Martin Bauspieß, Geschichte und Erkenntnis im lukanischen Doppelwerk. Eine exegetische Untersuchung zu einer christlichen Perspektive auf Geschichte (Arbeiten zur Bibel und ihrer Geschichte 42; Leipzig: Evangelische Verlaganstalt, 2012) 142–45; pace Frey, “Heilvolle Zeit,” 216 who suggests that calling Cullmann’s project “objectivizing” is not an accurate characterization.

18 The phrase “entire timeline” is from Cullmann, Christ and Time, 76. This point also places Cullmann at odds with Dodd, whose emphasis on “realized eschatology” locates the future fulfillment of Old Testament eschatological hope in the Christ event and the church; Dodd, History and the Gospel, 35, 150–59.

19 Rudolf Bultmann, “History of Salvation and History,” in Existence and Faith: Shorter Writings of Rudolf Bultmann (trans. Schubert M. Ogden; London: Collins, 1964) 226–40, at 239; cf. Frey, “Heilvolle Zeit,” 208.

20 Cf. Bultmann’s comments on the absence of significance for any “continuing course of events” after the resurrection in Bultmann, “History of Salvation,” 238; cf. Bauspieß, “Geschichte,” 315.

21 Bultmann, “History of Salvation,” 237: Christ “signifies the eschatological event that puts an end to the old aeon.” See also the comments in Rudolf Bultmann, “A Reply to the Theses of J. Schniewind,” in Kerygma and Myth (trans. Reginald H. Fuller; London: SPCK, 1953) 103–23, at 117; Rudolf Bultmann, “Man between the Times according to the New Testament,” in Existence and Faith (trans. Ogden), 293–315, and elsewhere.

22 “[T]emporal existence means to exist in constantly new decisions”; Bultmann, “History of Salvation,” 239.

23 Rudolf Bultmann, Jesus (Berlin: Deutsche Bibliothek, 1926) 83 (my translation); he continues, “Now is the time to know what to do and what to leave alone [was zu tun und zu lassen], and there are no standards [Maßstäbe] from the past or in general.”

24 Rudolf Bultmann, “The Case for Demythologization,” in Myth and Christianity: An Inquiry into the Possibility of Religion Without Myth (ed. Karl Jaspers and Rudolf Bultmann; New York: Noonday, 1958) 57–71, at 69; cf. the comments in Hans Weder, “Glauben und Verstehen,” in Bultmann Handbuch (ed. Christof Landmesser; Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2017) 219–29, at 221, about faith being “not a phenomenon in the world.”

25 See Rudolf Bultmann, History and Eschatology: The Presence of Eternity (New York: Harper & Row, 1957) 120. This is already present in Bultmann, Jesus, 49, and remains a feature of his thought through to his final letter to Heidegger, from September 1975, in which he still looks toward the future as “eine zukunftsreiche offne Zeit”; Rudolf Karl Bultmann and Martin Heidegger, Briefwechsel, 1925–1975 (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann; Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2009) 256–58; cf. also Folkart Wittekind, “Eschatologie,” in Bultmann Handbuch (ed. Christof Landmesser; Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2017) 323–34, at 325–26.

26 Ulrich Luz, Theologische Hermeneutik des Neuen Testaments (Neukirchen-Vluyn: Neukirchener Verlag, 2014) 39, also notes a shift in cultural priorities after 1968, which meant that fundamental philosophical questions were no longer oriented around existence, meaning, and God, but around food, justice, politics, and peace.

27 Quote from El-P, “Blockbuster Night Part 1,” in Run the Jewels 2 (Mass Appeal, 2014). For a representative statement of this critique of salvation history, see the summary in Friedrich Mildenberger, “Salvation History,” Religion Past and Present Online (Brill, 2011), http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/1877-5888_rpp_COM_09533; and cf. Peter C. Hodgson, God in History: Shapes of Freedom (Nashville: Abingdon, 1989) 11–50, and Bradford E. Hinze, “The End of Salvation History,” Horizons 18 (1991) 227–45. See also the concluding comments in Frey, “Heilvolle Zeit,” 217.

28 See esp. Käsemann, “Beginning,” 82–107. This new framing modified the emphases in the debate, with more recent discussions commonly considering Heilsgeschichte strictly in relation to the question of how to integrate the Christ event with the history of Israel. On this, see recently, J. P. Davies, Paul among the Apocalypses? An Evaluation of the ‘Apocalyptic Paul’ in the Context of Jewish and Christian Apocalyptic Literature (LNTS 562; Bloomsbury: London, 2016), esp. 72–112 (arguing that the opposition between “apocalyptic” and “redemptive history” is misguided); Grant Macaskill, The New Testament and Intellectual Humility (New York: Oxford University Press, 2018), 107–34 (principally siding with the “apocalyptic” over the “salvation historical” reading of Paul); and N. T. Wright, History and Eschatology: Jesus and the Promise of Natural Theology (London: SPCK, 2019), whose critique of Bultmann and “apocalyptic” theologies lands him in a position on history very similar to that of Oscar Cullmann.

29 David W. Congdon, “Eschatologizing Apocalyptic: An Assessment of the Present Conversation on Pauline Apocalyptic,” in Apocalyptic and the Future of Theology: With and Beyond J. Louis Martyn (ed. Joshua B. Davis and Douglas Harink; Eugene: Cascade, 2012) 118–36, at 131–32; cf. also idem, “Kerygma and History: Bultmann’s Hermeneutical Theology in North America Today,” in Rudolf Bultmann und die neutestamentliche Wissenshaft der Gegenwart (ed. Lukas Bormann and Christof Landmesser; Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2022) 79–110. See below for a discussion of the objective/subjective distinction drawn here.

30 Bultmann’s ongoing influence is well illustrated in Bultmann Handbuch (ed. Christof Landmesser; Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2017) and Rudolf Bultmann und die neutestamentliche Wissenschaft der Gegenwart (ed. Bormann and Landmesser), while Cullmann’s legacy was the subject of Zehn Jahre nach Oscar Cullmanns Tod (ed. Sallmann and Froehlich), and the interest continues with the publication of the Bultmann/Cullmann Breifwechsel in 2022 (noted above). The legacy of the salvation-history debate has most recently been picked up in relation to Lukan studies by Bauspieß, Geschichte und Erkenntnis, who treats both Bultmann and Cullmann as important interlocutors, along with the Pannenberg group. Kylie Crabbe, Luke/Acts and the End of History (BZNW 238; Berlin: de Gruyter, 2019), argues against Conzelmann’s non-eschatological view of Luke and Acts, partly by reclaiming aspects of Cullmann’s thought (and note also her engagement with the “apocalyptic” debates). Note also the defense of Heilsgeschichte as an exegetical description in Martin Hengel, “Heilsgeschichte,” in Heil und Geschichte. Die Geschichtsbezogenheit des Heils und das Problem der Heilsgeschichte in der biblischen Tradition und in der theologischen Deutung (ed. Jörg Frey, Stefan Krauter, and Hermann Lichtenberger; WUNT; Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2009) 3–34.

31 Champion, “History of Temporalities,” 247; cf. his comments on the following page about the lack of seminal articles on the theme of “temporality,” as well as his cautions about the idea of a temporal “turn.”

32 Hayden White, Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century Europe (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1974), and note also the early contributions of Reinhart Koselleck, Futures Past: On the Semantics of Historical Time (trans. Kieth Tribe; Cambridge: MIT Press, 1985) (German original from 1979), and Franklin Ankersmit, Narrative Logic: A Semantic Analysis of the Historian’s Language (Martinus Nijhoff Philosophy Library 7; The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1983).

33 Paul Ricoeur, Finitude et culpabilité II. La symbolique du mal (Paris: Aubier, 1961) (Paul Ricoeur, The Symbolism of Evil [trans. Emerson Buchanan; Boston: Beacon, 1967]); Ricoeur, La Mémoire (Ricoeur, Memory).

34 The conceptual links between these works are not only evident to readers but are signaled by Ricoeur himself. On the development from The Symbolism of Evil and Fallible Man (1961) to The Rule of Metaphor (1971), see the appendix printed in Paul Ricoeur, The Rule of Metaphor (trans. Robert Czerny with Kathleen McLaughlin and John Costello, S.J.; London: Routledge, 2003) 372–81. Ricoeur’s works on metaphor and narrative were conceived as “twins” (“sont deux ouverages jumeaux”; Ricoeur, Temps et Récit, 1:11). The link between the questions addressed in Time and Narrative and Oneself as Another is noted explicitly in Paul Ricoeur, “Narrative Identity,” Philosophy Today 35 (1991) 73–81. The mark of Time and Narrative is everywhere on Ricoeur, Memory (Ricoeur, La Mémoire). On Ricoeur’s shift to hermeneutical questions in the 1960s and his subsequent hermeneutical “turns,” see Jean Grondin, “Les tournants herméneutiques de Paul Ricœur,” Études Ricœuriennes 14 (2023) 9–24.

35 This will be elaborated below, but note that François Hartog, Regimes of Historicity: Presentism and the Experiences of Time (trans. Saskia Brown; New York: Columbia University Press, 2015) xvi, has highlighted a distinction between “temporality” and “duration,” found already in the work of Fernand Braudel, which anticipates the kind of distinction drawn by Ricoeur.

36 See further below on the relation with Ricoeur’s mimetic account of writing and reading. The relationship of “standing for” is worked out in particular in Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 3, 157–79. This is predicated in historiography on an unstated “contract” between the historian and the reader; Ricoeur, Memory, 275.

37 Within literary studies, Ricoeur’s phenomenological approach has been appropriated in Rita Felski, The Limits of Critique (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2015), while recent sociological work has likewise used Ricoeur’s work to help provide a theoretical frame for their case studies on memory and change; Emily Keightley and Michael Pickering, Memory and the Management of Change: Repossessing the Past (Palgrave Macmillan Memory Studies; Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan, 2017). Closer to home, in work on early and medieval Christian sources, Ricoeur is likewise present; see Brenda Deen Schildgen, Crisis and Continuity: Time in the Gospel of Mark (JSNTSup 159; Sheffield: Sheffield Academic, 1998); Carolyn Dinshaw, How Soon Is Now? Medieval Texts, Amateur Readers, and the Queerness of Time (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2012); Samuel Byrskog, “Memory and Narrative—and Time: Towards a Hermeneutics of Memory,” Journal for the Study of the Historical Jesus 16 (2018) 108–35; Normand Bonneau, Narrative Time in the New Testament: Essays on Mark, John, and Paul (Terra Nova 8; Leuven: Peeters, 2020).

38 See Mikhail M. Bakhtin, “Forms of Time and of the Chronotope in the Novel,” in The Dialogic Imagination (trans. Caryl Emerson and Michael Holquist; University of Texas Press Slavic Series 1; Austin: University of Texas Press, 1981) 84–258. It is particularly Kristina Wirtz, “The Living, the Dead, and the Immanent: Dialogue across Chronotropes,” Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 6 (2016) 343–69, who notes the lack of sustained theorization for the terminology.

39 Gérard Genette, Narrative Discourse: An Essay in Method (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1980) 32–85, though note the critique of this division in Wolf Schmid, Narratology: An Introduction (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2010) 200, among others. In fact, Genette borrowed this distinction from Tzvetan Todorov, “Les catégories du récit littéraire,” Communications 8 (1966) 125–51, at 126–27, 139–41.

40 Mieke Bal, Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2017) 5.

41 Ibid., 5 and elsewhere.

42 Bal, Narratology, 66–67; cf. also Teresa Bridgeman, “Time and Space,” in The Cambridge Companion to Narrative (ed. David Herman; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007) 52–65, at 64, and David Wittenberg, “Time,” in The Cambridge Companion to Narrative Theory (ed. Matthew Garrett; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2018) 120–31.

43 While some of these writers indicate a debt to Ricoeur and the hermeneutic/philosophical account of philosophy of history (as in the case of Dinshaw, How Soon Is Now), others such as Elizabeth Freeman, Time Binds: Queer Temporalities, Queer Histories (Perverse Modernities; Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2010), draw on poststructuralist and postcolonial resources, including the influential work of Dipesh Chakrabarty, Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008), among others, who articulates a Marxist account of “different orders of temporality” (esp. 90–96).

44 So, e.g., Judith Halberstam, In a Queer Time and Place: Transgender Bodies, Subcultural Lives (Sexual Cultures; New York: New York University Press, 2005) 7 (speaking of emotions); Freeman, Time Binds, 6–7; Dinshaw, How Soon Is Now, 6, 29.

45 See the influential discussion of “chrononormativity” outlined in Freeman, Time Binds, 3 and elsewhere. Note also the comments on asynchrony in Dinshaw, How Soon Is Now, 16; cf. also Anna Wilson, “Petrarch’s Queer History,” Speculum 95 (2020) 716–41, at 718.

46 The terminology is initially from Carolyn Dinshaw, Getting Medieval: Sexualities and Communities, Pre- and Postmodern (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1999).

47 So Katherine M. Graham, “Queer Temporalities, Queer Londons,” in Sex, Time and Place: Queer Histories of London c. 1850 to the Present (ed. Simon Avery and Katherine M. Graham; London: Bloomsbury, 2016) 23–39, at 24.

48 See the comments in Byron Ellsworth Hamann, “How to Chronologize with a Hammer, or, The Myth of Homogeneous, Empty Time,” Hau: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 6 (2016) 261–92, about the contested history of apparently “empty” or neutral historical time.

49 Dinshaw, How Soon Is Now, 5.

50 Dinshaw connects narrative and asynchrony in ibid., 41–2 and elsewhere.

51 So Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 3:230—the present “is no longer a category of seeing but one of acting and suffering.”

52 See Wirtz, “The Living, the Dead, and the Immanent.”

53 See the comments in A. R. P. Fryxell, “Time and the Modern: Current Trends of Modern Temporalities,” Past & Present 243 (2019) 285–98, building in particular on the arguments in George Kubler, The Shape of Time: Remarks on the History of Things (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1962).

54 The language of “traces” is borrowed from Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, vols. 1, 3. The work of Jonas Grethlein helpfully develops the link between experience and narrative representation in historiography, particularly with reference to ancient historiographical narratives; Jonas Grethlein, Experience and Teleology in Ancient Historiography: ‘Futures Past’ from Herodotus to Augustine (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013).

55 Hans Ruin, “Time as Ek-stasis and Trace of the Other,” in Rethinking Time: Essays on History, Memory, and Representation (ed. Hans Ruin and Andrus Ers; Södertörn Philosophical Studies 10; Huddinge: Södertörn University, 2011) 51–62, at 59, emphasis added.

56 Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 1:6.

57 Ibid., 1:227. In relation to the issue of temporality, Ricoeur presents Augustine’s account as something that prefigures the later phenomenological account.

58 The initial debate between Augustine and Aristotle is presented in part 1 (Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 1:5–30) and then traced in more detail through Heidegger in part 4 (Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 3:12–96).

59 Since the publication of Temps et Récit in the early 1980s (with the English translations appearing through 1988), much further work has been done on Augustine’s and Aristotle’s views of time. While all of it updates and clarifies various aspects of their work, some of it is generally consonant with Ricoeur’s interpretations (so Ursula Coope, Time for Aristotle: Physics IV.10–14 [Oxford Aristotle Studies; Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005], on Aristotle; Dinshaw, How Soon Is Now, on Augustine and Aristotle), while other work has presented a more direct challenge to certain aspects of his argument (so David Van Dusen, The Space of Time: A Sensualist Interpretation of Time in Augustine, Confessions X to XII [Supplements to the Study of Time 6; Leiden: Brill, 2014], on Augustine). What I offer here, however, is an account of Ricoeur’s own argument—his typology of theories of time—rather than my own account of Augustine and Aristotle themselves.

60 Ricoeur’s phenomenological reading of Augustine has been followed by Ruin, “Time as Ek-stasis,” 53–55, among others. Note however the critique of Ricoeur in Dusen, The Space of Time, 48–49, who argues that Ricoeur’s introduction of “mind” (esprit) is a fundamental mistake, which leads to a failure to account for the “sensuality” of Augustine’s theory of time.

61 Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 3:16.

62 Ibid., 1:15, 3:13; citing Aristotle Physics 4, 219a4. See now esp. the account of Aristotle’s time in Coope, Time for Aristotle, 5 and elsewhere—“Aristotle’s account represents time as a kind of universal order and … this is why he defines it, oddly, as a number.”

63 Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 3:14–16.

64 Ibid., 3:16.

65 Ibid., 3:17–18.

66 Ibid., 3:18.

67 Ibid., 3:25, 35, and elsewhere.

68 Ibid., 3:45–51.

69 Ibid., 3:57.

70 Ibid., 3:81–84.

71 Ibid., 3:90.

72 Ibid., 3:96; cf. Ricoeur’s similar comments on 57: “a phenomenology of time can be articulated only by borrowing from objective time.” Note the similar conclusion in Ruin, “Time as Ek-stasis,” 59: “While we should be aware of how we are constantly building narratives by interpreting traces as testimonies from a life no longer there, we should not allow this to result in subjectivistic hubris, as if the evolving universe was a construction of the human mind. Nor should we fall prey to the objectivist illusion of an existing Temporal Order.”

73 Cf. James Barr, Biblical Words for Time (SBT; London: SCM, 1969), 158. In relation to Cullmann’s disavowal of philosophy, William Baird, History of New Testament Research (Minneapolis: Fortress, 2013) 488, observed that “every view of history rests on a philosophy of history.”

74 Bultmann, Jesus, 49. While Bultmann’s views are not reducible to an appropriation of Heidegger (so Luz, Theologische Hermeneutik, 37 and David W. Congdon, “Is Bultmann a Heideggerian Theologian?,” SJT 70 [2017] 19–38), in the case of his account of temporality, he does appear influenced by the philosopher; cf. Bauspieß, “Geschichte,” 314, 318.

75 Cullmann, Salvation, 119, 121, 169; cf. Bauspieß, Geschichte und Erkenntnis, 145, and Hermesmann, Zeit und Heil, 88.

76 On the openness of salvation history to historical inquiry, see Cullmann, Salvation, 139–40; for the necessity of faith, see Cullmann, Christ and Time, 93, 219, 225, 228. This is present also in his more nuanced account in Cullmann, Salvation, 119, 121; cf. Oscar Cullmann, “Rudolf Bultmann’s Concept of Myth and the New Testament,” CTM 27 (1956) 13–24, at 19.

77 Cullmann, Salvation, 119.

78 On Christ as “mid-point,” see Cullmann, Christ and Time, 59–81 passim; see xxv in the introduction for Cullmann’s attempt to reframe his language of “mid-point.”

79 This is most explicitly brought out in Salvation in History (see below) but is present in a more subtle form in Cullmann, Christ and Time, 91, 131, 135.

80 Bultmann, “Case for Demythologization,” 69.

81 Karl Jaspers, “The Issues Clarified,” in Myth and Christianity: An Inquiry into the Possibility of Religion without Myth (ed. Karl Jaspers and Rudolf Bultmann; New York: Noonday, 1958) 72–116, at 77.

82 Bultmann, and Heidegger, Briefwechsel, 1925–1975, 258: “Was einmal war, – es ist ja jetzt von hinnen, Verschlungen ist’s von der Vergangenheit.”

83 If it is the case that “[i]n his faith the Christian is a contemporary of Christ, and time and the world’s history are overcome” (Bultmann, History and Eschatology, 153, cf. his comments on Christian existence on 154), this implies that history and time remain things to be overcome, again and again, in faith; cf. David W. Congdon, “Is there a Kerygma in this Text? A Review Article,” JTI 9 (2015) 299–311, at 304. Bultmann’s acceptance of Jesus’s death as a meaningful historical event was recognized by Cullmann; see Cullmann, “Rudolf Bultmann’s Concept,” 17.

84 Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 1:33, discussing Aristotle Poetics 1447a2–1450a15. On Ricoeur’s account of mimesis, see further below.

85 Ibid., 1:65.

86 Ibid., 1:66.

87 These comments are from Ricoeur’s analysis of Virginia Woolf’s Mrs. Dalloway; ibid., 2:106–17.

88 Ibid., 1:66. My interpretation of Ricoeur here is indebted to the distinction between synchronic and diachronic approaches to rhythmanalysis in Lexi Eikelboom, Rhythm: A Theological Category (Oxford Theology and Religion Monographs; Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018) 23–56 passim.

89 Initially articulated in part 2 (Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 1:91–230), these issues return in part 4 (3:104–26, 180–92). Ricoeur’s arguments about historical explanation through emplotment build on the influential work of White, Metahistory, among others. He returns to the role of narration in historical explanation in Ricoeur, Memory, 238–48.

90 The historian encounters these in certain “traces” of the past that remain in documents, archives, testimonies, etc.; see Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 3:119–25.

91 This intention, which operates as a tacit contract with the reader, is the principle separation between writing history and fiction; see Ricoeur, Memory, 275, which is building on Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 1:175–225.

92 Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 3:180ff. This “fictionalization” of history is reformulated in Ricoeur, Memory, 262, as the “interweaving of readability and visibility at the threshold of the historian’s representation.”

93 On this point, cf. the comments in Marc Bloch, The Historian’s Craft (trans. Peter Putnam; Manchester: University of Manchester Press, 1954) 193: “Reality offers us a nearly infinite number of lines of force which all converge together upon the same phenomenon. The choice we make among them may well be founded upon characteristics which, in practice, fully merit our attention; but it is always a choice.”

94 Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 1:67, and see the summary discussion in Ricoeur, Memory, 243–44.

95 Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 1:33. Ricoeur offers a threefold account of mimesis that comprehends the writer, work, and reader in a single communicative process. His initial discussion of this threefold mimesis occurs in part 1 (Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 1:52–87). His focus in parts 2 and 3, on emplotment and time in history and fiction, respectively, is on mimesis 2 (with some of mimesis 1, though the distinction between the first two stages is not always clear), while mimesis 3 comes to the fore in part 4.

96 Ibid., 1:71.

97 See n. 36 above.

98 In relation to fictional works, this is taken up in full in Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 3:157–79.

99 The experience of temporal dissonance is pursued principally in relation to fictional works, not bound by any specific weight of debt to past figures or events, as in Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 2:100–152.

100 Ibid., 3:230, 235.

101 Ibid., 3:231.

102 Cullmann, Salvation, 21.

103 Ibid., 55; cf. the discussion of Cullmann’s rejection of history as progress in Schlaudraff, “Heil als Geschichte”?, 250–52.

104 Cullmann, Salvation, 78.

105 Ibid., 55; cf. Frey, “Heilvolle Zeit,” 207.

106 Cullmann, Christ and Time, 141, for example; cf. the observation in David P. Moessner, “Luke/Acts and Salvation History,” in Zehn Jahre nach Oscar Cullmanns Tod (ed. Sallmann and Froehlich) 135–45, at 139.

107 Cf. Cullmann, Christ and Time, 178–79, and Cullmann, Salvation, 294, who notes that, going forward, salvation history “continues … as the unfolding of the Christ event.” What was narrowed to a focal point in Christ is, therefore, opened out again toward the world.

108 Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 1:65.

109 Cf. the observation in Braun, “Heil als Geschichte,” 106.

110 Cullmann, Salvation, 19, 29.

111 Bultmann, “History of Salvation,” 234. Bultmann put this criticism directly to Cullmann in his letter from 22 January 1948; Brief no. 24 in Rudolf Bultmann, Oscar Cullmann Briefwechsel 1926-1967 (ed. Jost, Sallmann, and Schliesser) 32–4.

112 Bultmann’s source-critical approach to this development, however, as seen in his commentary on John in particular, was in turn viewed with skepticism by Cullmann; so Frey, “Heilvolle Zeit,” 205.

113 Cullmann, Salvation, 78; cf. the comments in Braun, “Heil als Geschichte,” 108. In addition to his debate with Bultmann, this disjunction between salvation history and history per se is critiqued by Pannenberg for its tacitly “antihistorical” outcome; see Bauspieß, Geschichte und Erkenntnis, 147.

114 Cullmann, Christ and Time, 188–89.

115 Bultmann, “History of Salvation,” 237: Christ “signifies the eschatological event that puts an end to the old aeon.” See also the discussion in Bultmann, “Man between the Times.” Note that this point is also present in Bultmann’s letter to Cullmann from 22 January 1948, cited above; cf. Frey, “Heilvolle Zeit,” 202.

116 See Rudolf Bultmann, “New Testament and Mythology,” in Kerygma and Myth (ed. Hans Werner Bartsch; trans. Reginald H. Fuller; London: SPCK, 1953) 1–44, at 3–8. Note also the detailed exploration of the “missionary” impulse that drove Bultmann’s demythologizing program; David W. Congdon, The Mission of Demythologizing: Rudolf Bultmann’s Dialectical Theology (Minneapolis: Fortress, 2015).

117 Bultmann, “A Reply,” 117.

118 “[T]emporal existence means to exist in constantly new decisions”; Bultmann, “History of Salvation,” 239.

119 An unsuccessful attempt in the view of Karl Jaspers, noted above.

120 All human experience, then, holds the possibility of being understood to have a “divinely willed place in the framework of redemptive history”; Cullmann, Christ and Time, 213.

121 Cullmann, Salvation, 166. I say “almost” because for Cullmann the event is described as “this mid-point in salvation history.” In fact, Cullmann is borrowing this terminology from the famous dictum of Leopold von Ranke.

122 The quote is from Cullmann, Salvation, 230.

123 As noted above, Bultmann saw these factors as invalidating it as “history,” while Cullmann defended his view as “an analogy to history.”

124 On the other hand, the extremely close link between temporality and narrative invites the question about what kind of narrative is at stake in Bultmann’s own existentialist account.

125 See further below.

126 Jaspers, “Issues Clarified,” 77.

127 See the comments above, at nn. 27 and 45.

128 Cullmann, Salvation, 21.

129 From the perspective of the “messianism” of Walter Benjamin and Jacob Taubes, among others, the possibility of the eschatological in the midst of the unrelenting peripeteia of everyday time is foundational to the accounts of messianic in Lynne Moss Bahr, “The Time is Fulfilled”: Jesus’s Apocalypticism in the Context of Continental Philosophy (LNTS; London: Bloomsbury, 2018).

130 Bal, Narratology, 67.

131 This is articulated particularly in the final chapter of Dinshaw, How Soon Is Now and is addressed from a different (but I think complementary) perspective in Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, vols. 1, 3.