Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T09:53:43.943Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Crises of Care in China Today

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 April 2023

Hans Steinmüller*
Affiliation:
London School of Economics and Political Science, London, UK
*
*Corresponding author: Hans Steinmüller, email: J.Steinmuller@lse.ac.uk
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The introduction to this special section presents an overview of crises of care in China today, specifically as they affect the fields of kinship, health and government. To study care ethnographically, we distinguish between the attentive and active dimensions of care: what people care about, and how they care for others. Acts of care always relate to larger concerns and general values, but they scale up in different ways. The imbalances that emerge are central to the politics of care that our contributors describe. Care as attentive co-growth engages different values, remakes inequality and nourishes political life. The contributors use the same framework of attention, action and politics to investigate crucial issues in Chinese society, including family, health, environment, ritual and animals. In all these fields, care provides a privileged vantage point from which to understand social and moral change in China today.

摘要

摘要

本篇导论对今日中国的照护危机进行概述,尤其是这种危机如何影响亲属、健康和治理层面。我们采用民族志方法对照护进行研究。为此,我们对照护的留意维度和行动维度做出区分,前者指人们关心的东西,后者指人们照料他者的方式。照护的行动总是牵涉到宏大的关切以及共同的价值。然而,个别行为如何升级到宏观的层面,却是通过不同的形式。此升级过程中浮现出来的不平衡是照护政治的核心问题,撰稿人们将会对这些不平衡进行描述。照护,作为一种留意的共生,会介入不同的价值,重塑社会不平等,并滋养政治生活。撰稿人们使用同一组留意、行动与政治的框架,来探讨中国社会的关键议题,包括家庭、健康、环境、仪式和动物。照护为所有这些领域提供了一个绝佳视角,以便我们理解今日中国的社会与道德变迁。

Type
Special Section - Ethnographies of Care: Attention, Action and Politics
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of SOAS University of London

Practices of care give space to others, nourish them and help them grow. As such, they are central to kinship, health and government. In the People's Republic of China (PRC), care has changed radically since the beginning of reform and opening up in the 1980s. In the realm of kinship, the last decades have seen the rise of nuclear families and new ideals of self-realization. Relations of care between family members, and specifically care responsibilities for the old and frail, are very different now, to the extent that people frequently complain that the young do not care for the old. Following broader social developments such as the expansion of market economies and the ageing of the population, healthcare and elderly care industries have grown exponentially. Large parts of these sectors now operate according to market principles; and frequently the emotional and affective labour which maintains these sectors is underpaid and undervalued. At the same time, different government levels care in entirely new ways for the population: by promoting self-reliance and risk-taking on the one hand, but also by distributing benefits and subsidies, especially to the poor and in the countryside. Institutions of state care, and images of caring officials and leaders, are essential to regime legitimacy; and the accusation that officials are uncaring, or worse, only care for themselves, is always looming.

In all these spheres, in fact, expectations of care are only rarely met; and according to many observers, family care, healthcare and state care are in crisis. These crises have to do with large social and moral transformations, including urbanization, consumerism, new inequalities and a new pluralism of lifestyles and attitudes. Such pluralism stands in stark contrast with the moral uniformity of Maoism, where one “heroic” ideal of sacrifice was overshadowing all spheres of everyday life. Rather than acknowledging the new heterogeneity, many complain about moral decline, and point to the selfish individualism of the young, the lack of public trust, and the ubiquity of official corruption.Footnote 1 The main suggestion of this special section is that instead of a moral crisis, the ethical predicament of contemporary China should be understood as several interrelated crises of care.

The care sector itself, defined in the strict sense of the word as healthcare and elderly care, is an obvious starting point: important changes have taken place here in regard to the social dynamics, economics and ethics of care. Childcare, healthcare and elderly care have become increasingly professionalized and commercialized in the past few decades, raising new moral challenges in how to care for the young, the sick and the old. Caring means to heed the needs of others, to purposively act with them and to engage with social institutions, the government and the market: The politics of care thus concern both social action and ethical judgement.

Drawing together the social and the ethical, the politics of care extend far beyond the care sector in the strict sense of the term, that is, modern institutions such as homes for the elderly and hospitals. Even when the sick and old are transferred to such institutions, the duty of care, and often the practice of care, is still with the family. In recent years, the interface between such modern institutions and families has been transformed by the spread of health insurers – in the countryside specifically, cooperative health insurance schemes – as well as other welfare state measures, such as the minimum livelihood guarantee (dibao 低保).Footnote 2 There are also local practices of care and protection that are renewed in popular religion and in ritual.Footnote 3 If rituals thus revive older forms of protective care, care itself can expand to entirely new fields: for instance, in recent years, people have learned to care for the environment in ways unthinkable only a generation ago.Footnote 4 Another important area of moral and ethical innovation is animal welfare: Yufei Zhou's contribution to this special section shows how caring for Tibetan Mastiffs implies different things to different people, and requires a particular positioning toward the commercialization of the same animals.

The topic of care provides a productive focal point to link a number of different fields of enquiry in China studies: looking at the performance of care allows us to study how people practically and concretely build relationships with significant others. Whether or not someone cares, or is seen to be caring, has fundamental implications for the attribution of responsibility. Care thus connects the study of social ethics with classical topics of anthropological and sociological interest, such as kinship, gender and community. To understand care, we need to draw lines between the personal and the political, between morality and law, between the individual and the relational aspects of work.

In this introduction, I briefly outline what the concept of care could mean for China studies, drawing on discussions in feminist philosophy, social anthropology and political science. Care is defined as “attentive co-growth” that is by necessity uneven, and therefore politically charged. The attention, action, and politics of care provide the framework for the ethnographic studies of kinship, health and government that follow.

Care: Attention, Action, Politics

At its most basic, the English noun and verb “care” can refer to the act of noticing and paying attention to (“to care about”), and then acting for the benefit and welfare of, someone or something else, by empathizing with them (“to care for”). It would be a mistake to reduce the former field of “caring about” to a passive impact and the latter (“caring for”) to an active practice: both caring about and caring for are constituted through acts. Care essentially means to attune to others and share agency in co-action and co-growth. Both the attention and action of care are moulded by changing environmental constraints. These two fundamental senses of care – attentive and active care, or to care about and to care for – are the starting points in most definitions of “care.”Footnote 5 What we care about and who we care for are thus fundamental questions in any “ethics of care.”

Important distinctions that follow from here are those between attitudes and action, between discourses and practices, and between forms and intensities of care. Rather than immediate knowledge in action, much discourse about care reflects on what happened after the fact. Separating the action from the reflection is fundamental to our explorations of care: we will look at both what people say and what they do, and compare the two. In this way, attention is drawn to the possibility of ethical posturing or what we might call “pretence care,” as well as gratuitous and unintended care. Such distinctions are drawn both by the observers and by the observed: and various of our contributors start their arguments by analysing vernacular distinctions made between what is said and what is done, and between convention and invention in local practice. But the most fundamental question is always what do we actually care about? That is, what do we notice and what do we ignore?

Attention

People pay attention to very different things; they also care for different beings. Webs of care spread between the nodal points that mark out our existence. They are fuzzy, chaotic and multiple: and, by definition, cannot be captured through formal abstraction alone; because care, as attentive co-growth, is concrete action that is premised on co-presence and thus cannot be abstracted into pure form. Care starts, at its most basic, with the simple act of noticing and paying attention. If you care about someone or something, this object acquires significance for you: note that only a minuscule part of reality emerges from the background noise and acquires significance, comes forward and is cared about. What, when and how something becomes figure against ground depends on the cognitive capacities, the mediatic tools and technologies, and social institutions in play.

Someone or something needs to figure in this way before we can care for this person or thing. At its most fundamental, care requires us to pay attention to – “to care about” – something. In constant online communication during the COVID-19 pandemic, most of us have learned to refocus their attention. However important and radical these recent changes have been, any medium, or, at its most fundamental, any process of formalization, points to a particular structure of attention: it encourages and constrains our choice of stimuli – that is, environmental events that emerge as sensual figures against some background noise. Surely the largest part of what happens around us never appears to consciousness; and out of those very few things that do, we actively engage with an even smaller part: this is the minimal dissection of our environment that we “care about.” This is not to say that attentive care is entirely passive – on the contrary, paying attention also entails choice, judgement and decision-making. And people do not just care about other humans, but also animals, plants and things – even beliefs and ideals. Any object can become a “matter of care,”Footnote 6 and it is the process of this becoming noticeable that is the focus of several contributions that follow: they distinguish what people care about and what goes without saying.

Action

To care about something or someone is the precondition of caring for them. The act of care re-draws past positions and opens up future horizons. Care is always selective – it is simply impossible to care about everything, let alone to care for everything: if care creates significant others, not to be cared for is the definition of abandonment. Caring for significant others requires the recognition by a third party (an audience, an institution, or an inner voice, for instance), who confirms that care was attentive and emphatic. In the absence of social recognition, directed action toward others might be mere intuition, or aggression and harm, instead of attentive co-growth. “Caring for” is thus based on attention to and empathy for an other, and its recognition as such by a third party. If we follow this definition, it becomes imperative to distinguish between intention and action, discourse and practice, form and intensity of care: people can care in many ways and not act; or act carefully without thinking much about it. Only if the act of care is recognized as such (as something that nourishes and gives freedom to others) does it deserves to be called “care.”

Care is always limited and unequal: simply because it is impossible to care for everything and everyone at the same time. Care thus provides an excellent focus for understanding political complexities: specifically, the lopsided structures of empathy, mind-reading and co-action that are part and parcel of any hierarchy: be it in bureaucraciesFootnote 7 or in relations of gender and race.Footnote 8 Typically, the inferior partners (women, children, racial others) are required to care, whereas the superiors (men, adults, whites) just set the rules. Correspondingly, the “concrete” work of inferiors is devalued in comparison to the “abstract” work of superiors. The self-descriptions of the carers often include the same devaluation of care; just repeating those self-descriptions therefore might simply re-affirm the underprivileged position of the caring part. Capturing the “different voice” of caring, as formulated famously by Carol Gilligan,Footnote 9 would mean to escape these oppressive structures and the denigration of emotional work: it may help us find new senses of community, of self and perhaps even of politics altogether.

Politics

We can identify similar imbalances in China; at the most general level between the ways in which the government cares for its citizens, and how, in turn, citizens care about the government. Imbalances in care have been described for domestic workers in China, who care for the new urban middle classes that care relatively little in return: thus reproducing new relationships of masters and servants.Footnote 10 Global consultancies which operate as joint ventures with local governments in China equally enforce a distinction between “productive” consultants and “costly” back offices.Footnote 11 Civilizing projects in China have tended to infantilize and feminize peripheral subjects, or treat them as ancient and senile; put into inferior positions in the classificatory hierarchies of civilization and modernity, peripheral people have responded by developing ideologies of ethnicity or ethnic consciousness.Footnote 12 Correspondingly, “ethnic minorities” in China are often forced to learn Mandarin and adapt to Han Chinese culture – at any rate, more so than Han Chinese would be required to understand non-Han Chinese.

The act of caring for others relies on and reproduces unequal relations between those who care and those who are cared for. Parents care for their children, and expect their children to care for them in old age.Footnote 13 The government is supposed to care for the people, but in reality local officials only care for themselves, as villagers often complain. Perhaps some officials higher up the ladder actually care for the people: but local officials do not even notice the needs of ordinary people. Such a “bifurcation of the state,” where high-level officials are indeed caring, and local officials corrupt, has been a common perception at the grassroots level of everyday politics.Footnote 14 The relationship between ordinary people and local officials is often characteristically unequal when it comes to care: villagers care very much about officials and frequently discuss their motivations and anticipate their next moves, hoping that the same officials would notice, and would care. Officials, however, care for the people only in the abstract, and in repeated slogans such as “to serve the people.” In everyday life, however, they often simply do not have the time to care about ordinary citizens – as mentioned above, possible attention is always limited, especially for busy officials. The labour of care thus sets into motion a whole series of socio-logics that are essential to politics.

Our enquiries of care in China centre on these three shared concerns: the attention that care affords, the concrete actions through which people care for others and the politics of care, specifically related to the conflicting scales and dimensions of scaling up care. The attention, action and politics of care allow us to understand issues of immense importance in Chinese society today. As the contributions to this collection show, ethnographies of care provide crucial insights into the changing economy, ethics and politics of China today.

Ethnographies of Care in China Today

There are vast semantic fields relating to the attention, action and politics of “care” in contemporary Chinese. To care about and notice (zaihu 在乎, zaiyi 在意, jieyi 介意, guanzhu 关注, guanxin 关心); to care for (zhaogu 照顾, zhaokan 照看, zhaoliao 照料); to nourish, foster and rear (yang 养); self-care (yangshen 养身); to take care of something (chuli 处理, fuze 负责); to worry (danxin 担心, fannao 烦恼, youlü 忧虑); protection (baohu 保护, baoyou 保佑); caution (jinshen 谨慎, xiaoxin 小心); and to wait upon (cihou 伺候) are all relevant in this regard. These words describe what people in China today care about, and how they care for others. From the simple act of noticing to emotional labour and paternalist politics, care is essential to human existence, in China and elsewhere.

Many scholars have noted the affinities of care ethics and Confucian ethics, as well as some core differences, for instance, to do with the importance of ritual and convention.Footnote 15 The main point for us, however, is not the comparison of ethical principles, but rather how they are mobilized in practice. The assessment of care in practice is different from the theoretical observation, at least in the minimal sense that frequently it happens “after the fact,” that is, much of the attention and action of care is intuitive, rather than reflective, in the moment of practice. But even so, the reflection that takes place after the event, is equally significant and consequently impacts on future action. In the following we will deal with this combination of intuition and reflection in the practice of care. We will do so specifically in relation to kinship, health and government in China today.

Emphasizing processes and practices close to the actors' own conceptualizations, “care” might well replace older approaches in the study of kinship that emphasized corporate ideologies and kinship systems.Footnote 16 The anthropologist Tatjana Thelen expands on this processual feature in her general definition of care – the “everyday action of creating, maintaining and dissolving relations with significant others” – as fundamental to any form of social organization.Footnote 17 Starting herself from the empirical basis of research on care work in Eastern Europe, Thelen has expanded this focus on care with various collaborators to the boundaries of private and public, concrete and abstract, and local versus state-based forms of interaction.Footnote 18 A focus on care, it has been suggested, can help us to understand the connections between work, kinship and the life course;Footnote 19 on the most general level, it can also help us draw the boundaries (as well as make connections) between the realm of the state and the realm of kinship.Footnote 20

Many arguments in the anthropology of Chinese kinship, similarly, can be reinterpreted as problems of care. For instance, separation and reunion have been shown to be crucial aspects of kinship, as well as of social life in general.Footnote 21 The basic dialectic of being together and being separated – the “separation constraint” that any social relation faces – is perhaps at its most fundamental a problem of “being there” for someone else, of resonating with and responding to others – that is, of care. Kinship expectations differ substantially in these regards for boys and girls: boys are supposed to stay with their parents, while girls have to leave their natal homes.Footnote 22 Similarly, fathers and mothers are supposed to care in very different ways, as embodied in the popular saying of the “strict father and kind mother” (yan fu ci mu 严父慈母). There are many other examples: for instance, the return visits of married women to their natal homes,Footnote 23 the cycles of relatedness and care for children and for the old,Footnote 24 or the gendered nature of work and kinship values.Footnote 25 The actions of sharing, nurture and commensality that make kinship in all these examples are essentially actions of mutual care.

Since the beginning of reform and opening up, care responsibilities in families have shifted a great deal, in correspondence with broader changes in family and gender relations.Footnote 26 The work of care thus helps us track the milestones people reach in work, kinship and in their life-cycle,Footnote 27 as well as in “global care chains,” that is, the various interlinked levels of care work, from personal relations to wider associations and institutions.Footnote 28

In the past few decades, healthcare and elderly care in the PRC have become increasingly professionalized and commercialized. The number of caring professionals has expanded, as has the number of patients being cared for in institutions, including hospitals and care homes.Footnote 29 While most primary healthcare is delivered in public hospitals, large parts of the sector have been privatized. Since the 1980s private health insurance programmes are increasingly common, and in the countryside a cooperative health insurance programme was introduced – the New Rural Cooperative Medical System (NRCMS). But even so, many parents, especially in the countryside, still believe that the best “insurance” for old age is to have a son.Footnote 30 Altogether, families and kinship relations remain central to care, and our contributors analyse healthcare between the realm of the family and government agencies. Changes in elderly care and practices of filial piety in China today cannot be separated from the wider changes in family structures, the commercialization of the health sector, and changing government policies.Footnote 31

Corresponding to institutionalization and commercialization, new separations of “deserving” and “undeserving” recipients of care have emerged.Footnote 32 Healthcare and elderly care are motivated by new forms of “biopolitical paternalism,” which present the government as a caring and parental figure, yet situate care responsibilities within families and tacitly condone practices such as additional medication and home confinement.Footnote 33 At the same time, new ways of self-care and healthcare have emerged outside of the care sector specifically. For instance, the growth of psychology and counselling has been described as a “psy-boom” in urban China; and new forms of mindfulness and spirituality combine with new concerns, such as environmental sustainability. Practices of care provide a microscope to see the huge social and moral changes taking place in China; they also connect the intimately personal with public politics, the self with government.

From the first emperor to Xi Jinping, Chinese rulers were involved in cycles of mutual care with their subjects.Footnote 34 If people were expected to worship the rulers, the emperors themselves were supposed to “cherish all under heaven” (xinhuai tianxia 心怀天下) so as to adjust the forces and flows of government (zhi 治). In the vernacular language of modern China, the mixture of paternalistic care and control typical of government is embodied in the verb guan 管,Footnote 35 which stretches from the loving care of parents to official control and public administration: the particular use of family metaphors thus impacts concretely on people's understanding of care in the “impersonal” realm of public politics.Footnote 36

Contributions

How do local actions of care relate to broader issues of government and political economy? The contributors to this special section provide ethnographic answers. Christof Lammer focuses on the “scale of care” in his analysis of the minimum livelihood guarantee: in principle, it would appear that this should be the government taking over care duties when families are unable to do so; yet what is really happening is that the care work done by families and the support received from government are mutually implicated. This is also one of the main arguments in Charlotte Bruckermann's contribution: on the basis of her long-term ethnographic work in the “coal province” of Shanxi, she lays particular emphasis on how environmental crisis, health problems and family relations are all mutually related – and how people make these relations explicit in the action of care. Through the work of care, local families try to address what Bruckermann describes as a “crisis of reproduction.”

This includes entirely new topics people care about – such as landscapes, water and air in Bruckermann's case, or Tibetan Mastiffs in Yufei Zhou's case. Zhou analyses how Tibetans and Han Chinese pay attention to very different aspects and qualities of dogs: whereas for Tibetan pastoralists dogs are appreciated as guard dogs, Chinese breeders value the ferocious appearance of dogs, and raising dogs that (are supposed to) bite poses all kinds of challenges. Such entanglements of care with market relations, and with government institutions, can lead to situations in which particular local relations of care create a platform to criticize paternalism and “state care.” This is specifically what Stephan Feuchtwang shows in the case of social support, popular religion and ritual. Rather than just covering the areas of social life not directly reached by government agencies, popular care sometimes provides an alternative to state care, Feuchtwang argues. He outlines in broad strokes how care relations can offer alternatives in politics and economics altogether.

In these arguments, we draw on recent literature on care work and care chains, and reject the separation of economic interest and affective relations that commonly appears with concepts such as “emotional” or “affective” labour.Footnote 37 In reality, all “economies” are based on affective labour and care: it's just that we usually fail to recognize them as such. This failure of judgement is deeply engrained in the ways in which contemporary capitalism operates, how social hierarchies are reproduced and how violence is exercized on bodies, in China and elsewhere: fundamentally, these problems all have to do with the ways care is limited to concrete, local and immediate encounters. The core challenge, therefore, is to capture the transformative potential of care: what remains of the empathy and the concrete touch of attentive co-growth when care is extended to global economies, complex institutions and large states? The contributors to this special section rise to the challenge and show in much detail how individuals and institutions respond to the crises of care in China today.

Acknowledgements

Some of the ideas for this special issue were first rehearsed in a session of the China Reading Group chaired by Carwyn Morris, and a workshop that took place online in May 2020. Many thanks to everyone who participated in the discussions and commented on individual papers later. The author of the introduction is particularly grateful to Harriet Evans and Michael Edwards who commented on different versions of this introduction.

Competing interests

None.

Hans STEINMÜLLER is an associate professor in the Department of Anthropology at the London School of Economics. He is the author of Communities of Complicity: Everyday Ethics in Rural China (Berghahn Books, 2013), and has edited (with Natalia Buitron) The Ends of Egalitarianism (L'Homme, 2020).

Footnotes

1 Cf., for instance, Ci Reference Ci2014; Yan Reference Yan2020.

2 See Lammer, Reference Lammer2023.

3 See Feuchtwang, Reference Feuchtwang2023.

4 See Bruckermann, Reference Bruckermann2023.

5 For example, Noddings Reference Noddings1984; Tronto Reference Tronto1993.

18 Read and Thelen Reference Read and Thelen2007; Thelen, Vetters and Benda-Beckmann Reference Thelen, Vetters and von Benda-Beckmann2017.

19 Alber and Drotbohm Reference Alber and Drotbohm2015.

20 Thelen and Alber Reference Thelen and Alber2017. For further overviews, see Buch Reference Buch2015; Black Reference Black2018.

27 Alber and Drotbohm Reference Alber and Drotbohm2015.

28 Nguyen, Zavoretti and Tronto Reference Nguyen, Zavoretti and Tronto2017.

31 Shea, Moore and Zhang Reference Shea, Moore and Zhang2020.

32 Nguyen and Chen Reference Nguyen and Chen2017; see also Lammer, this issue.

34 Dean and Massumi Reference Dean and Massumi1992.

References

Alber, Erdmute, and Drotbohm, Heike (eds.). 2015. Anthropological Perspectives on Care: Work, Kinship, and the Life-course. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bear, Laura, Ho, Karen, Tsing, Anna Lowenhaupt and Yanagisako, Sylvia. 2015. “Gens: a feminist manifesto for the study of capitalism.Society for Cultural Anthropology. 30 March. https://culanth.org/fieldsights/gens-a-feminist-manifesto-for-the-study-of-capitalism. Accessed 2 May 2020.Google Scholar
Bellacasa, María Puig de la. 2017. Matters of Care: Speculative Ethics in More Than Human Worlds. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla. 1987. “The generalized and the concrete other: the Kohlberg–Gilligan controversy and moral theory.” In Benhabib, Seyla and Cornell, Drucilla (eds.), Feminism as Critique: Essays on the Politics of Gender in Late-Capitalist Societies. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 7795.Google Scholar
Black, Steven P. 2018. “The ethics and aesthetics of care.Annual Review of Anthropology 47 (1), 7995.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borneman, John. 1997. “Caring and being cared for: displacing marriage, kinship, gender and sexuality.International Social Science Journal 49 (154), 573584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandtstädter, Susanne. 2009. “The gender of work and the production of kinship value in Taiwan and China.” In Brandtstädter, Susanne and Santos, Gonçalo D. (eds.), Chinese Kinship: Contemporary Anthropological Perspectives. London: Routledge, 154178.Google Scholar
Bruckermann, Charlotte. 2023. “Care for the family and the environment in China’s coal country.” China Quarterly 254.Google Scholar
Buch, Elana D. 2015. “Anthropology of aging and care.Annual Review of Anthropology 44 (1), 277293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chong, Kimberly. 2018. Best Practice: Management Consulting and the Ethics of Financialization in China. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Ci, Jiwei. 2014. Moral China in the Age of Reform. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dean, Kenneth, and Massumi, Brian. 1992. First and Last Emperors: Absolute State and Body of the Despot. Brooklyn, NY: Autonomedia.Google Scholar
Epley, Kelly M. 2015. “Care ethics and Confucianism: caring through li.Hypatia 30 (4), 881896.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feuchtwang, Stefan. 2023. “Care as critique of care: public services, social security and ritual responsiveness.” China Quarterly 254.Google Scholar
Gilligan, Carol. 1982. In a Different Voice. Boston, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Graeber, David. 2012. “Dead zones of the imagination: on violence, bureaucracy, and interpretive labor: the Malinowski Memorial Lecture, 2006.HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 2 (2), 105128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guo, Xiaolin. 2001. “Land expropriation and rural conflicts in China.China Quarterly 166, 422439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrell, Stevan. 1994. “Introduction: civilizing projects and the reaction to them.” In Cultural Encounters on China's Ethnic Frontiers. Seattle: University of Washington Press, 336.Google Scholar
Herr, Ranjoo Seodu. 2003. “Is Confucianism compatible with care ethics? A critique.Philosophy East and West 53 (4), 471489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
hooks, bell. 1992. “Representations of whiteness in the Black imagination.” In Black Looks: Race and Representation. Boston, MA: South End Books, 165–78.Google Scholar
Judd, Ellen R. 1996. Gender and Power in Rural North China. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Lammer, Christof. 2023. “Care scales: dibao allowances, state and family in China.” China Quarterly 254.Google Scholar
Li, Chenyang. 1994. “The Confucian concept of Jen and the feminist ethics of care: a comparative study.Hypatia 9 (1), 7089.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Li, Chenyang. 2000. The Sage and the Second Sex: Confucianism, Ethics, and Gender. Chicago, IL: Open Court Press.Google Scholar
Li, Xi, Krumholz, Harlan M., Yip, Winnie, Cheng, Kar Keung, De Maeseneer, Jan, Meng, Qingyue, Mossialos, Elias, et al. 2020. “Quality of primary healthcare in China: challenges and recommendations.Lancet 395 (10239), 18021812.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ma, Zhiying. 2020. “Biopolitical paternalism and its maternal supplements: kinship correlates of community mental health governance in China.Cultural Anthropology 35 (2), 290316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nguyen, Minh T.N., and Chen, Meixuan. 2017. “The caring state? On rural welfare governance in post-reform Vietnam and China.Ethics and Social Welfare 11 (3), 230247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nguyen, Minh T.N., Zavoretti, Roberta and Tronto, Joan. 2017. “Beyond the global care chain: boundaries, institutions and ethics of care.Ethics and Social Welfare 11 (3), 199212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Noddings, Nel. 1984. Caring, a Feminine Approach to Ethics & Moral Education. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Read, Rosie, and Thelen, Tatjana. 2007. “Introduction: social security and care after socialism: reconfigurations of public and private.Focaal 50, 318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sangren, P.S. 2000. Chinese Sociologics: An Anthropological Account of the Role of Alienation in Social Reproduction. London: Athlone.Google Scholar
Shea, Jeanne, Moore, Katrina and Zhang, Hong (eds.). 2020. Beyond Filial Piety: Rethinking Aging and Caregiving in Contemporary East Asian Societies. New York: Berghahn.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shi, Lihong. 2009. “‘Little quilted vests to warm parents’ hearts’: redefining the gendered practice of filial piety in rural north-eastern China.China Quarterly 198, 348363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stafford, Charles. 2000a. Separation and Reunion in Modern China. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stafford, Charles. 2000b. “Chinese patriliny and the cycles of yang and laiwang.” In Carsten, Janet (ed.), Cultures of Relatedness: New Approaches to the Study of Kinship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 3554.Google Scholar
Steinmüller, Hans. 2015. “‘Father Mao’ and the country-family: mixed feelings for fathers, officials, and leaders in China.Social Analysis 59 (4), 83100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thelen, Tatjana. 2015. “Care as social organization: creating, maintaining and dissolving significant relations.Anthropological Theory 15 (4), 497515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thelen, Tatjana, and Alber, Erdmute (eds.). 2017. Reconnecting State and Kinship. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.Google Scholar
Thelen, Tatjana, Vetters, Larissa and von Benda-Beckmann, Keebet (eds.). 2017. Stategraphy: Toward a Relational Anthropology of the State. New York: Berghahn Books.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tronto, Joan C. 1993. Moral Boundaries: A Political Argument for an Ethic of Care. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Yan, Hairong. 2008. New Masters, New Servants: Migration, Development, and Women Workers in China. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Yan, Yunxiang. 2020. “The politics of moral crisis in contemporary China.China Journal 85, 96120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zavoretti, Roberta. 2017. “Get yourself an insurance! Negotiating family and intergenerational care in post-Mao urban China.Ethics and Social Welfare 11 (3), 248260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zhu, Jianfeng, Pan, Tianshu, Yu, Hai and Dong, Dong. 2018. “Guan (care/control): an ethnographic understanding of care for people with severe mental illness from Shanghai's urban communities.Culture, Medicine and Psychiatry 42 (1), 92111.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed