Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T16:35:48.010Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Cognitive linguistics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Cognitive linguistics is a new development in one of the basic sciences of psychiatry. It takes a novel approach to metaphor that is having an impact on philosophy and cognitive neuroscience, offering a perspective on questions about the development of language and the embodiment of mind that may have an impact on psychiatry. Likewise, our expertise in mental pathology may be required for further development in cognitive linguistics (Lakoff, 1997).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal College of Psychiatrists 2002 

Cognitive linguistics is a new development in one of the basic sciences of psychiatry. It takes a novel approach to metaphor that is having an impact on philosophy and cognitive neuroscience, offering a perspective on questions about the development of language and the embodiment of mind that may have an impact on psychiatry. Likewise, our expertise in mental pathology may be required for further development in cognitive linguistics (Reference Lakoff and SteinLakoff, 1997).

Metaphor and metonymy

Cognitive linguistics focuses on the ubiquity of metonymy and metaphor in language (Box 1).

Until relatively recently it was assumed that it must be possible to provide an accurate, objective (i.e. literal) description of reality for the purpose of scientific advancement. For the modernist, metaphors characterised rhetoric, not scientific discourse. They were vague, inessential frills, appropriate for the purposes of politicians and poets, but not for those of scientists (Reference Ortony and OrtonyOrtony, 1993).

This perspective put the science of psychodynamics, with its emphasis on metaphor, symbolisation and transference, outside the remit of acceptable scientific discourse (Reference HolmesHolmes, 1985).

Traditionally, metaphor was seen as concerning ‘live’ or ‘novel’ descriptions, the kind of metaphor that is found in poetry and rhetoric. Idiomatic expressions were dismissed as ‘dead’ metaphors; ones that had once been bright and new, but had become worn and dull with overuse.

Box 1 Metaphor and metonymy

‘Metaphor’ is a type of figurative language in which one thing is described in terms of some other thing. For example,

‘Do not go gentle into that good night’

‘He had a good innings’

‘Metonymy’ is a type of figurative language in which the name of one thing is replaced with another commonly associated with it. For example,

‘And did those feet in ancient time Walk upon England's mountains green?’

‘Who is going to chair the meeting?’

Metaphor and thought

Since 1980, a growing number of linguists have been attempting to elucidate the ways in which language reflects the manner in which human beings perceive, categorise and conceptualise the world (Reference Lakoff and JohnsonLakoff & Johnson, 1980). The results suggest that accurate, objective, literal descriptions may be elusive. According to the linguist Reference Lakoff and OrtonyGeorge Lakoff (1993), we use our basic bodily understanding of places, movement, forces, paths, objects and containers as sources of information about life, love, mathematics and all other abstract concepts.

Embodiment of mind

Cognitive linguistics suggests that we use metaphor intuitively and unconsciously to understand the mind, emotions and all other abstract concepts. Such metaphors enable us, as embodied beings, to make sense of a concept such as ‘mind’, which we cannot see with our eyes or grasp with our hands. It allows us to ‘take a view’ on the debate and to ‘get to grips’ with the subject. Cognitive linguistics suggests that, without such conventional metaphors, there would be no abstract thought. It also suggests that metaphors may ‘privilege’ some understandings and exclude others (Reference Schön and OrtonySchšn, 1993). If we do not acknowledge metaphor, it may distort our understanding of the nature of abstract concepts.

Conceptual metaphor

Through field research, Lakoff and his colleagues have collected large numbers of metaphorical expressions (Reference Lakoff and JohnsonLakoff & Johnson, 1980; Reference LakoffLakoff, 1987). Analysis has led them to believe that these are derived from a smaller number of conceptual metaphors. Both creative, novel metaphors and ‘dead’, conventional metaphors are derived from conceptual metaphors. Known also as schemata, these can be thought of as line drawings (Reference JohnsonJohnson, 1987). Metaphorical expressions take some detail from a schema and colour it in for greater immediate effect. For each of the conceptual metaphors in Box 2, there are many more conventional metaphorical expressions.

Box 2 Common conceptual metaphors (CAPITALS) and examples of metaphorical expressions (italics)

STATES ARE LOCATIONS: I fell in love. He pulled himself up by his bootstraps. Her finances are in a real mess.

ACTIVITIES ARE CONTAINERS: How did Mary get out of doing the washing up? He was in the middle of writing. She was absorbed in a book.

CONTROL IS UP: You need to get on top of the problem. He got the upper hand. I went over his head and spoke to the boss.

KNOWING IS SEEING: Do you see what I mean? What is your view on that? His judgement was clouded.

THE PART IS THE WHOLE: We need some new blood in this organisation. The head of the company. I'm getting the 07:17 from Loughborough.

ESSENTIAL IS CENTRAL: The central point of the argument. The heart of the matter. His core contribution. You need to peel away the layers.

ATTRIBUTES ARE OBJECTS: He caught a terrible cold. She got fatter and fatter. He has such an awful attitude to women. My mother has an awful temper. I don't know where she gets it from.

EVENTS ARE ACTIONS: The deceased passed over. The child came into the world. Dawn broke. The party was in full swing.

TIME IS MONEY: Can you spare me 5 minutes? I spent too much time on that. Don't waste my time. How much leave can you afford to take at Christmas?

THOUGHT IS MATHEMATICAL CALCULATION: It just doesn't add up. Give me an account of your actions. I don't think that counts. What's the bottom line?

Sources and targets

For Reference Lakoff and OrtonyLakoff (1993), the locus of metaphor is not in language at all but in the way we conceptualise one mental domain in terms of another. This is what he means by conceptual metaphor and, following his convention, I have written these in CAPITALS. Words given in italics are thought of as metaphorical expressions. Conventionally, conceptual metaphors are written: TARGET DOMAIN IS SOURCE DOMAIN. The target is the subject under discussion. The source is the (usually more concrete) concept from which we draw inferences about the target.

Novel metaphor

LOVE IS A JOURNEY (We're not getting anywhere. This marriage is in a rut)

GOOD IS UP (She's way above him. They have high moral standards)

The idiomatic expressions above, exemplifying two conceptual metaphors, are commonplace, unpoetic and do not, perhaps, strike us as particularly metaphorical. Someone can say ‘This marriage is in a rut’ and the statement is taken at face value. If someone were to say, ‘Even a Massey Ferguson wouldn't have salvaged my marriage’, we hear the statement as something new. Metaphorically, an impediment to the continuation of a marriage is an impediment to a journey continuing, such as a rut. On a real journey, you might ask the local farmer to haul your car out of a rut with a tractor. To create a novel metaphor, essential for poetry and humour, the speaker has taken an aspect of the Source of the conceptual metaphor that is not usually associated with the target. In doing so, the speaker has made the metaphor explicit and brought it back to life.

Generative metaphor

A generative metaphor is one that enables us to see aspects of reality that the metaphor's production helps to constitute (Reference Schön and OrtonySchšn, 1993). For example, since LOVE IS A JOURNEY we can commit ourselves to going the distance with someone. A relationship can founder and be on the rocks. We might want to bail out. The image of a journey privileges the aspects of relationships that are analogous to a journey. It suggests that it is possible to go our separate ways and not look back. It has less to say about the role of loving relationships in the context of an extended family. The image of two people in a vehicle together not only enables us to think about love but may also prevent us from seeing aspects of love that are outside of the metaphor.

Other theoretical approaches

Lakoff and Johnson's theory of deep conceptual metaphor challenges the view that literal language is primary and that metaphor is a complex, later development. However, theirs is not the only perspective.

Reference GlucksbergGlucksberg (2001), for example, is directly critical of Lakoff and Johnson's theory of cognitive linguistics. His class-inclusion model assumes that, when deciphering metaphors, the listener looks for superordinate categories and qualities that make the target and source similar, unconsciously converting metaphor into simile. His theory is a less radical departure from classical, truth-conditional theories of language and has considerable influence in the field of psycholinguistics.

By contrast, Reference TurnerTurner (1996) and Reference FauconnierFauconnier (1985) have developed Lakoff and Johnson's ideas further to take account of metaphors that depend on the combination of a number of different frames. They have developed the idea of conceptual blends, proposing that language develops by ‘parable’ and by the ‘blending’ of mental spaces. Their theories provide elegant approaches to more complex literary and poetic language.

Bridging the gap

As pragmatic clinicians, it is probably less important for us to ask which of these models will eventually be proved true. What is more relevant is to ask which is fit for our purpose. Lakoff and Johnson's theory provides a bridge between linguistics and our understanding of the body and the brain and this has been acknowledged as coherent with other research in cognitive science (Reference DamasioDamasio, 1999; Reference Núñez and FreemanNœ–ez & Freeman, 2000; Ramachandran, 2001). From a psychoanalytic perspective, its theory of ‘body-based fantasies parallels the psychoanalytic notion of unconscious processes’ (Reference HollandHolland, 1999: p. 362). It offers a perspective on Freudian theories of libidinal development that is ‘highly consonant with psychoanalysis, with which it shares an emphasis on how our experience of the body helps to shape our perspective on the world’ (Reference MelnickMelnick, 1997: p. 997). It also provides an easily taught, practical tool for discourse analysis that can deepen our understanding of patients’ communications in the consulting room. While acknowledging that there have already been further developments in the field, here I will simplify matters by limiting myself to the approach taken by Lakoff and Johnson.

Metaphor and transference

The term ‘metaphor’ comes from the Greek, meaning to carry over. Another translation is ‘transference’, a term more familiar to us from psychoanalytic theory. The idea that we take attitudes from one area of experience and use them to approach and understand another is fundamental to many of the psychotherapies. For example, in a paper exploring the links between cognitive linguistic and psychoanalytic approaches to metaphor, Reference BorbelyBorbely (1998: p. 931) sees ‘The cure É as resulting from helping the analysand regain blocked creativity or metaphorical potential by linking transferentially coloured present experience with sequestered past experience’.

Psychotherapists of many different persuasions use metaphor in their work. Family therapists may offer metaphors as strategic interventions (Reference BarkerBarker, 1996). A client's metaphors may be explored and expanded to allow the development of new attitudes to difficulties (Reference KoppKopp, 1995). Dynamic therapists may consider their own stray thoughts to be a metaphor for something in the therapy that cannot be communicated in words (Reference OgdenOgden, 1997).

The ‘unconscious’ of cognitive linguistics is not necessarily seen as being formed by repression as is the classical Freudian unconscious, but there are many other similarities. What Freud called ‘symbolisation’, ‘displacement’, ‘condensation’ and ‘reversal’, a cognitive scientist would recognise as ‘conceptual metaphor’, ‘conceptual metonymy’, ‘conceptual blending’ and ‘irony’ (Reference Lakoff and SteinLakoff, 1997). As Miller Reference MairMair (1977) put it, ‘man is a maker and user of metaphors and is not to be explained by any particular metaphor’.

Metaphors for the mind

According to cognitive linguistics, our understanding of the human mind and human emotions are constructed through metaphor (Reference Lakoff and JohnsonLakoff & Johnson, 1999). We routinely carry over aspects of the world that we relate to as embodied beings in order to generate new ways of seeing ourselves and the world. That last sentence is itself constructed using metaphors: IDEAS ARE OBJECTS that we can carry; a system of ideas is a BUILDING that we can construct; to bring something into existence is to give birth – to generate; KNOWING IS SEEING.

To make sense of the mind and emotions, we use fundamental conceptual metaphors, which can be seen as deriving one from another (Box 3). At its most basic level, STATES ARE LOCATIONS. Thus, a state of mind is a location in space. The mind itself can be seen as a location in space, leading to the view that THE MIND IS A CONTAINER. That is, it is a place that ideas, since they are objects, can be in.

Box 3 Conceptual metaphors that structure our understanding of mind, and some metaphorical expressions

THE MIND IS A CONTAINER: I just don't know what goes on inside that head of yours. Some ideas just seem to pop into your head. He just pushed it to the back of his mind. It went clean out of my head.

IRRATIONALITY IS BEING OUTSIDE THE MIND: Are you out of your mind? He's away with the fairies. The lights are on but no one's at home.

NORMAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND CONTROL IS CO-LOCATION (and vice versa): Pull your-self together. She's all over the place. I just don't know if I'm coming or going. I feel pulled in all directions

CONTROL IS UP: I don't know what came over me. When I get on top of things again. He was under the impression.

AN ATTRIBUTE IS A POSSESSION; THE SELF IS A POSSESSION: Get a grip on yourself. He's lost it. He regained consciousness. She's really self-possessed.

NORMAL CONSCIOUSNESS IS NORMAL POS-SESSION OF THE SELF BY THE SUBJECT: The past still holds him back. It's like he can't let go of something. I got caught up in the mood.

True Self Model 1, in which ESSENTIAL IS CENTRAL: He rarely shows his real self. She's not very revealing. You only get to see the mask. I bet he's a real sweetie deep down.

True Self Model 2, in which KNOWING IS SEEING: You can always judge a man by the state of his shoes. Actions speak louder than words. Handsome is as handsome does.

Since being in one's mind is the normal state of affairs, IRRATIONALITY IS BEING OUTSIDE THE MIND.

Being able to see ourselves, it is possible to know ourselves both as the viewer (or subject) and as the viewed (or self). This allows us to construct a division of the subject and self. In general situations, COMPATIBILITY IS CO-LOCATION. When a married couple get on well we describe them as close or really together. A mentally healthy person can also be described as someone who is together. Since ATTRIBUTES ARE OBJECTS, the self can be seen as an object that the subject possesses and controls.

The self, being an object, can be divided into parts, which may be incompatible and reside in different locations in the mind. The conceptual metaphor ESSENTIAL IS CENTRAL leads to the idea that the inner, unseen, hidden self is the True Self Model 1. By contrast, since KNOWING IS SEEING, it is the public self that is the True Self Model 2.

Metaphor and the psychotherapies

Psychological theories draw on these conventional conceptual metaphors in order to understand the abnormal mind. The Freudian division of the mind into conscious and unconscious spaces makes intuitive sense because it builds on the conceptual metaphor already present in language and thought that the MIND IS A CONTAINER. If compatibility of subject and self is a harmonious co-location, the abnormal mind can be seen as divided and at war with itself. The idea of psychic conflict between personified aspects of the self, such as superego and id, has its roots in conventional conceptual metaphors. Winnicott's model of the True and False Self in dynamic psychotherapy assumes True Self Model 1. Behaviourism assumes that a person's observable actions are the best guide to their true nature, in accordance with True Self Model 2.

Metaphor analysis in psychiatry

Analysis of which conventional conceptual metaphors a patient prefers can give an insight into how they construct their difficulties (Reference EynonEynon, 2001). For example, it can be frustrating to meet with a patient, clinic after clinic, who discusses ‘my depression’ or ‘my alcohol problem’ or even ‘my personality disorder’ at great length and yet makes no change. It is as if they have brought a child, a pet or some other object with them, over which they have no control. Metaphor analysis suggests that this attitude is not idiosyncratic but is supported by the conceptual metaphor, ATTRIBUTES ARE OBJECTS. As we have seen, even the attribute ‘self’ can be viewed as an object, separate from the subject. Emotional states and personality characteristics can be considered as if they were external objects. Psychiatry itself may unwittingly make the situation worse by describing the patient as ‘mentally unwell’. Conventionally, NORMAL CONSCIOUSNESS IS CONTROL OVER THE SELF. In declaring patients ‘mentally ill’, we may be seen as sanctioning their giving up control of the attributes of their self and fostering the expectation that we will take this troublesome ‘object’, their ‘illness’, out of their hands.

Somatic complaints

A diagnostic category for which this kind of discourse analysis may be particularly useful is somatisation. The conventional metaphorical expression, ‘I can't bear it’, is derived from the conceptual metaphor DIFFICULTIES ARE BURDENS. We might say of someone ‘He's got a lot on his shoulders’ or ‘I don't know how she carries on’. The posture of someone with depression may be stooped, as if ‘weighed down with the cares of the world’. For some patients, physical symptoms may be somatic analogues, as if their body is ‘saying’ what they are unable to admit in words.

Case vignette 1: A cognitive–behavioural example

An anxious patient had a fear of losing control of her bladder. Behavioural analysis suggested that her problem might relate to fear of losing control, per se, but therapy was made difficult by her rather irritable personality. Although it was evident that her difficulties become worse when she had to relate to people she disliked, she was reluctant to accept an emotional basis for her urinary problem.

Her fear of wetting herself extended to a reluctance even to discuss words related to urine. As behavioural exposure therapy progressed, the therapist was able to suggest that the patient's fear of losing control of her bladder might relate to her fear of losing control of her temper. She might be rather pissed off (LOSS OF CONTROL OF SELF IS LOSS OF CONTROL OF BODILY FUNCTIONS). This interpretation not only injected some humour into the sessions and enhanced the therapeutic alliance but also gave the patient a metaphor that made sense of her symptoms and how they might relate to her moods.

Case vignette 2: A psychodynamic example

A patient with a problem of overeating could not, initially, see why she had been referred for dynamic psychotherapy. Her problem was, purely and simply, her size. She insisted that ‘My fatness obscures everything else about me’.

This sentence can be deconstructed to show the conceptual metaphors on which it relies. The use of the word ‘obscures’ depends on the common conceptual metaphor, KNOWING IS SEEING. It also implies that something is hidden. There is a hidden inside and a visible outside, as in the True Self Model 1 described above, in which ESSENTIAL IS CENTRAL. The attribute ‘fatness’ is being seen as if it were an ‘object’ that gets in the way of people knowing her (ATTRIBUTES ARE OBJECTS).

The patient does not wish people to apply True Self Model 2 (Box 3) and see her merely as a ‘fat person’. She is arguing that True Self Model 1 should apply, that her ‘fatness’ prevents others seeing and appreciating her essential True Self. On the other hand, she also believes that if only she could lose weight, all would be well; she is here using True Self Model 2, believing that by changing her external appearance she could change her Self.

During assessment, the therapist suggested to the patient that by insisting that her ‘fatness’ was the problem, she was preventing herself from seeing how this was obscuring the issues in her relationships, which led her to comfort herself by eating.

In taking this stance, the therapist is choosing between the two conflicting True Self models, preferring the idea that ESSENTIAL IS CENTRAL, that the True Self is hidden. As a dynamic therapist, this choice is coherent with her theoretical model. She then extends the metaphor, arguing that the ‘essential’ issue that is bringing the patient to therapy is likewise ‘hidden’. The argument is persuasive because it builds on the patient's own existing conceptual framework.

Dream analysis

Reference Lakoff and SteinLakoff (1997) has suggested that metaphor analysis may be a fruitful way of analysing dreams. The images in a dream can be viewed as a visual form of metaphorical expressions in which, for example, abstract ATTRIBUTES are portrayed as physical OBJECTS. For example, a despised attribute may be represented by a despised substance.

A patient who had long-standing difficulties in asserting herself in relationships described a dream in which faeces were pouring out of her mouth. For this woman, having a voice in relationships and expressing her feelings was ‘bad’. The colloquial expression ‘you're talking shit’ could be seen as a verbal representation of the same idea.

Dreams as messages

Some dreams may be seen as messages to the medical team.

Case vignette 3: interpretation of a dream

A patient who had been admitted with a severe depressive illness made considerable improvements on antidepressants. In the multi-disciplinary ward round, her consultant suggested that she might be ready for trial leave. The next day, the patient reported a dream to one of the nursing staff. A ship had sunk to the bottom of the ocean. It was being raised, but was still only halfway up to the surface.

The terms ‘depression’ and ‘low mood’ are directly related to the conceptual metaphors GOOD IS UP. The STATE of depression is a LOCATION, the sea, the place the patient now finds herself in her LIFE, which IS A JOURNEY. An ‘interpretation’, by tracing the metaphorical route from source to probable target using idiomatic language derived from the same sources, puts the images into words.

The patient's mood is clearly further up than it was, but she is not out of the water yet. She is not yet ready to sail through her life and is afraid that if the staff let her go too soon that she will sink into depression again.

The patient told the psychiatric team this dream believing that they would want to interpret it as a communication. In common parlance and in psychotherapy, ‘depression’ is seen as having an existence that is not entirely independent of its construction in language.

Metaphor analysis and poetry

The science of cognitive linguistics can also expand our awareness of the way that poetry reaches out to us (Reference Lakoff and TurnerLakoff & Turner, 1989). Christina Fletcher's poem ‘Untitled’ (Box 4) conveys a mood that is poignant and sad. Like patient communications, poetry is often not explicit about the target of the metaphor. Nevertheless, the reader can feel moved by the poem and have an emotional understanding of the poet's intention without necessarily gaining an intellectual understanding of the means by which this was achieved.

Box 4 ‘Untitled’, by Christina Fletcher

Lines move: up a fraction, down a fraction and are erased.

I measure the distance from peach to wall up a fraction, down a fraction.

I mark paper but in the end, see nothing.

Light fades. Shadows melt to darkness.

Moths tumble around my monitor.

I move words but cannot find poetry.

I would fool the computer by moving time backwards but to what purpose?

In the morning the peach will shrivel a fraction.

In the evening more words will be deleted.

I will look harder, find less

And hope to understand.

(© Christina Fletcher; reproduced with permission)

In the first two stanzas, the sources are mathematics and light. In the fourth, a living thing decays, words are deleted. The last word, often of great significance, is ‘understand’. The poem depends on a movement from ‘calculation’ and ‘seeing’ as metaphors for understanding to a realisation that, when it comes to issues such as age, loss and despair, these metaphors (metonymically, the words) are inadequate.

The reader does not have to conduct a formal metaphor analysis in order to be affected by the poem. The conceptual metaphors used to construct the poem are familiar to us. We use them unconsciously in everyday speech. A poem can reach us at this deeper level and need not stir the surface, which is perhaps why Murray Cox found it effective to use poetry in his work with seriously disturbed patients in Broadmoor (Reference Cox and TheilgaardCox & Theilgaard, 1997).

Forensic psychotherapy

Cognitive linguistics suggests that language is fundamentally related to bodily actions. James Gilligan, writing about his work as a forensic psychiatrist, suggests that, when working with violent offenders, rather than seeing language as symbolic action ‘we must reverse the procedure and learn to interpret action as symbolic language – with a ‘symbolic logic’, so to speak, of its own’ (Reference Gilligan, Cordess and CoxGilligan, 1996: p. 478).

In a clinical example, he describes how a murderer's action of cutting out the eyes and tongue of an already dead woman can be seen as an attempt to prevent himself being shamed in her eyes and her from giving tongue to what she knows about his inadequacy. Murray Cox's (1997) descriptions of the archetypal language of offender patients seems to suggest that some people act out symbolic language as if the conventional metaphors are not dead, but very much alive.

Case vignette 4: therapy in a forensic setting

A 14–year-old boy who has a history of offending and has been diagnosed as having a conduct disorder is in therapy with a female social worker. After many months, they are beginning to be able to discuss the therapeutic relationship. The therapist is curious as to what has made that so difficult up to now. The patient explains:

‘That would be playing with fire.’

‘Literally?’ enquires the therapist.

‘No, not playing with matches and stuff,’ the patient replies.

The patient is an arsonist and the object of one dangerous attack was an older woman.

The psychiatrist is curious about the patient's choice of idiomatic language. Perhaps it is a communication both about the offence and about the risk of an intimate relationship with a woman? The general conceptual metaphor EMOTION IS A PHYSICAL FORCE (see Box 5) underlies such phrases as ‘I was all fired up’ and ‘She's a real firecracker’. In making this link, the therapist is drawing on conventional conceptual metaphors and using them to reason about the confused emotions and thought processes that may have motivated the patient's offending behaviour.

Box 5 EMOTION IS A PHYSICAL FORCE

ANGER IS HEAT: He was steaming. I thought he was going to explode. Wait until you've cooled down.

LOVE IS HEAT: She positively glowed. He gave me an icy stare. Come on baby, light my fire.

LOVE IS (MAGNETIC) ATTRACTION: We're poles apart. I keep being drawn back to her. She turns heads wherever she goes.

ANXIETY IS A BURDEN: It's been a great weight off my mind. He had been labouring under that assumption for a long time. Let me shoulder some of your worries for a while.

SADNESS IS A BURDEN: It's weighing me down. It's the last straw (that broke the camel's back). I keep being dragged under.

Future research

Cognitive linguistics can help us to understand the way that the mind is constructed, in both folk and formal psychology. It can therefore help us to examine how ordinary people understand the abnormal mind. That said, research is based on examining normal language produced by normal subjects. In stating that abstract concepts are constructed by metaphorical extension from normal bodily experience, it assumes that this is so. As yet, it has little to say about how abnormal bodily experience might affect the developmental processes that lead to normal linguistic capability. What follows are some conjectures as to how a cognitive linguistic approach to mental pathology might lead to some testable hypotheses.

Theory of mind

Since KNOWING IS SEEING, we can, by seeing another person, know them. We can follow their gaze and see what they see and, by inference, know what they know. If development goes normally, we have a theory of mind. Children with autism lack such a theory of mind. Cognitive linguistics, which assumes the embodiment of mind, suggests that accession to the concept of other minds should depend, in some fundamental way, on the same neurological base as seeing.

Interestingly, it is said that parents of such children report very early deviance from normal development of quite basic interpersonal skills, including failure to make eye-contact and failure to use gaze to regulate interaction (Reference Baron-Cohen, Tager-Flugsberg and CohenBaron-Cohen et al, 1993).

Developmental disorders

Some children with developmental coordination disorder, which affects the ability to make sense of location and space, have more difficulty with small words, such as prepositions that denote space and time, than with longer words (Reference Ripley, Daines and BarrettRipley et al, 1997). As we have seen, such little words can be evidence of metaphorical expressions that use LOCATIONS and CONTAINERS as the source for making sense of abstract targets.

Schizophrenia

Schizophrenia is characterised not only by thought disorder, but also by motor abnormalities. Cognitive linguistics suggests that language develops out of the way our body relates to the world as we move in space, make journeys, change locations, handle objects and so on. A subtle disorder of somatosensory perception or control might have an elusive but significant effect on thought and language. A passage by Reference Lakoff and TurnerLakoff & Turner (1989) discussing poetic language might be equally applicable to the language of psychotic illness:

‘Any discussion of the uniqueness or idiosyncrasy of a metaphor must, therefore, take place on two levels: the conceptual level and the linguistic level. A given passage may express a common conceptual metaphor in a way that is either linguistically commonplace or idiosyncratic. An idiosyncratic conceptual metaphor is another matter. By its very nature, it cannot be deeply conventionalised in our thought and, therefore, its linguistic expression will be necessarily idiosyncratic in at least some respect. Modes of thought that are not themselves conventional cannot be expressed in conventional language. In short, idiosyncrasy of language may or may not express idiosyncrasy of thought, but idiosyncrasy of thought requires idiosyncratic language’ (Reference Lakoff and TurnerLakoff & Turner, 1989: p. 50).

Conclusions

Cognitive linguistics assumes that language develops by metaphorical extension. Basic bodily experiences, such as moving in space, seeing people and handling objects, provide the foundations of language.

Cognitive linguistics offers a method of discourse analysis which can help psychiatrists to become more fully aware of the way that folk and formal psychological theories have been constructed. It assumes that language, and the abstract thought that language allows, develops out of normal bodily experience. Psychiatry, with its emphasis on abnormal thought processes, may have a role to play in testing these ideas and developing them further.

Multiple choice questions

  1. 1. Cognitive linguistics:

    1. a provides an accurate objective description of reality

    2. b considers metaphor as fundamental to human thought

    3. c assumes that language is independent of the body

    4. d is based on field research with normal subjects

    5. e was developed by George Lakoff and Mark Johnson.

  2. 2. Metaphor analysis can be used to:

    1. a understand patients’ communications

    2. b deconstruct psychological theories

    3. c determine the literal truth of scientific ideas

    4. d analyse dreams

    5. e inform therapeutic interpretations.

  3. 3. The following metaphorical expressions are correctly paired with an underlying conceptual metaphor:

    1. a I bet he's a softie underneath; True Self Model : ESSENTIAL IS CENTRAL

    2. b I keep turning it over in my mind; IDEAS ARE OBJECTS

    3. c she's risen in my estimation; CONTROL IS UP

    4. d he has some low habits; GOOD IS UP

    5. e we need to get patients’ views on this; KNOWING IS SEEING.

  4. 4. ‘Cognitive linguistics, by focusing on the ubiquity of metonymy and metaphor in language has built on and expanded the constructivist agenda.’ This sentence uses the following conceptual metaphors:

    1. a TIME IS MONEY

    2. b KNOWING IS SEEING

    3. c IDEAS ARE OBJECTS

    4. d A SYSTEM OF IDEAS IS A BUILDING

    5. e MIND IS A CONTAINER.

  5. 5. Freud's topographical theory of the mind can be seen as constructed from the following conceptual metaphors:

    1. a MIND IS A CONTAINER

    2. b COMPATIBILITY IS CO-LOCATION

    3. c CONTROL IS UP

    4. d GOOD IS UP

    5. e STATES ARE LOCATIONS.

MCQ answers

1 2 3 4 5
a F a T a T a F a T
b T b T b T b T b T
c F c F c F c T c T
d T d T d T d T d T
e T e T e T e F e T

References

Barker, P. (1996) Psychotherapeutic Metaphors: A Guide to Theory and Practice. New York: Brunner/Mazel.Google Scholar
Baron-Cohen, S., Tager-Flugsberg, H. & Cohen, D. J. (1993) Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives from Autism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Borbely, A. F. (1998). A psychoanalytic concept of metaphor. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 79, 923936.Google ScholarPubMed
Cox, M. & Theilgaard, A. (1997) Mutative Metaphors in Psychotherapy; the Aeolian Mode. London: Jessica Kingsley.Google Scholar
Damasio, A. (1999) The Feeling of What Happens: Body, Emotion and the Making of Consciousness. London: Vintage.Google Scholar
Eynon, T. (2001) Metaphor: the impossible translation? British Journal of Psychotherapy, 17, 353364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fauconnier, G. (1985) Mental Spaces: Aspects of Meaning Construction in Natural Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gilligan, J. (1996) Exploring shame in special settings. In Forensic Psychotherapy: Crime, Psychodynamics and the Offender Patient (eds Cordess, C. & Cox, M.) pp. 475489. London: Jessica Kingsley.Google Scholar
Glucksberg, S. (2001) Understanding Figurative Language. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holland, N. N. (1999). Cognitive linguistics. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 80, 357363.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Holmes, J. (1985) The language of psychotherapy: metaphor, ambiguity, wholeness. British Journal of Psychotherapy, 1, 240253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, M. (1987) The Body in the Mind; the Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination and Reason. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kopp, R. R. (1995) Metaphor Therapy; Using Client-generated Metaphors in Psychotherapy. New York: Brunner/Mazel.Google Scholar
Lakoff, G. (1987) Women, Fire and Dangerous Things; What Categories Reveal about the Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakoff, G. (1993) The contemporary theory of metaphor. In Metaphor and Thought (2nd edn) (ed. Ortony, A.) pp. 116. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lakoff, G. (1997) How unconscious metaphorical thought shapes dreams. In Cognitive Science and the Unconscious (ed. Stein, D. J.) pp. 89119. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Press.Google Scholar
Lakoff, G. & Johnson, M. (1980) Metaphors We Live By. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Lakoff, G. & Johnson, M. (1999) Philosophy in the Flesh. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Lakoff, G. & Turner, M. (1989) More than Cool Reason: A Field Guide to Poetic Metaphor. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mair, M. (1977) Psychology and psychotherapy: some common concerns. British Journal of Medical Psychology, 50, 2125.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Melnick, B. A. (1997). Metaphor and the theory of libidinal development. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 78, 9971016.Google ScholarPubMed
Núñez, R. & Freeman, W. (eds) (2000) Reclaiming Cognition: The Primacy of Action, Intention and Emotion. Thorverton, Devon: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
Ogden, T. (1997) Reverie and metaphor. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 78, 719732.Google ScholarPubMed
Ortony, A. (1993) Metaphor, language and thought. In Metaphor and Thought (2nd edn) (ed. Ortony, A.) pp. 116. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ramachandran, V. S. & Hubbard, E. M. (2001) Synaesthesia – a window into perception, thought and language. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 334.Google Scholar
Ripley, K., Daines, B. & Barrett, J. (1997) Dyspraxia, a Guide for Teachers and Parents. London: David Fulton.Google Scholar
Schön, D. A. (1993) Generative metaphor and social policy. In Metaphor and Thought (2nd edn) (ed. Ortony, A.) pp. 137163. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, M. (1996) The Literary Mind: The Origins of Thought and Language. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.