1 Introduction
In preventative health decisions, such as the decision to undergo an invasive screening test or treatment, people may be deterred from selecting the test because its disutility relative to not testing is greater than the utility associated with prevention of possible disease. For example, people may feel that the anticipated disutility of a colonoscopy for colorectal cancer screening is great enough relative to the expected utilty of prevention of possible colorectal cancer to dissuade them from seeking colonoscopy.Footnote 1
The prospect theory editing operation (Kahneman & Tversky, Reference Kahneman and Tversky1979; Tversky & Kahneman, 1992), by which a decision maker’s reference point is determined, can have important impacts on the perceived disutility of the test. The work of Rothman, Salovey, and colleagues on message framing has tested prospect theory predictions of how the description of test outcomes as gains or losses (as well as the conceptualization of the purpose of the test as preventative vs. diagnostic and the consequent perception of whether the test is “safe” or “risky”) can affect test rates (Rothman & Salovey, Reference Rothman and Salovey1997; Rothman, Bartels, Wlaschin, et al., Reference Rothman, Bartels, Wlaschin and Salovey2006). Specifically, message framing theories predict that when a procedure is perceived as risky (e.g., cancer screening tests may cause a patient to find out that they have cancer), loss-framed messages will promote testing more strongly than gain-framed messages, because people favor risky prospects over sure prospects in the domain of losses. On the other hand, when a procedure is perceived as safe (e.g., sunscreen prevents sunburn and skin cancer), gain-framed messages are predicted to be more effective because people prefer sure prospects to risky prospects in the domain of gains. Several public health intervention studies have examined message framing and generally found evidence favoring the predictions (Apanovitch, McCarthy, & Salovey, Reference Apanovitch, McCarthy and Salovey2003; Moxey, O’Connell, McGettigan, et al., Reference Moxey, O’Connell, McGettigan and Henry2003; Rivers, Salovey, Pizzaro, et al., Reference Rivers, Salovey, Pizarro, Pizaaro and Schneider2005; but see Finney & Iannotti, Reference Finney and Iannotti2002 for a failure to confirm the predictions).
On the basis of the prospect theory value function, this paper develops two approaches to reducing perceived disutility by directing the decision maker’s attention to either (actual) past or (expected) future losses that can serve as reference points and are not consequences of the test itself. These approaches thus differ from message framing, which focuses on how the test outcomes are described and manipulates gain and loss framing. We instead derive the potential impact of directly refocusing the decision maker’s reference point.
After providing a graphical description of the approaches and a mathematical proof of the direction of their effect on judgment, we illustrate the potential value of these approaches with examples from qualitative research on prostate cancer treatment decisions.
2 Graphical Description
Figure 1 depicts a stylized prospect theory value function, which defines the value associated with gains or losses from a reference point R 1, designated by the origin of the graph. The function displays the three salient characteristics of the PT value function: diminishing marginal value for gains (the gain portion of the curve is concave down), diminising marginal value for losses (the loss portion of the curve is concave up), and loss aversion (the loss curve is steeper, at all points, than the corresponding point on the gain curve).
Consider a decision maker who faces a decision between undergoing or avoiding an invasive screening procedure. The decision maker’s status quo is his baseline health, shown as X 0 in Figure 1; this point is also labeled R 1 to indicate that it is the reference point from which evaluation takes place. The decision maker is evaluating the difference in value associated with the invasive procedure, shown as Xc. Δ v 1 then represents the disutility that the decision maker expects as a result of undergoing the procedure.
Consider now a decision maker who faces the same decision, with the same objective outcomes (i.e., current health, X 0, or current health and an invasive procedure, Xc), but whose reference point is somehow shifted to the right (through an editing operation) relative to R 1, to the point marked R 2 on Figure 2. This decision maker, who now sees even their baseline health as poor (as X 0 is in the domain of losses relative to R 2), expects less marginal disutility from the invasive procedure, because the distance between Xc and X 0 now results in a value difference of Δ v 2, which is perceived to be on a flatter portion of the loss curve, and is therefore smaller in magnitude than Δ v 1. Compared with a relatively poor health state, the incremental loss associated with an invasive procedure is perceived as “less (additionally) bad.”
Finally, consider a third decision maker who faces the same decision, with the same objective outcomes (i.e., current health, X 0, or current health and an invasive procedure, Xc), but whose reference point is somehow shifted to the left (through an editing operation) relative to R 1, to the point marked R 3 on Figure 2. This decision maker now interprets her baseline health, with or without an invasive procedure, as a relative gain, as X 0 and Xc are in the domain of gains relative to R 3. Therefore, the decision maker expects less marginal disutility from the invasive procedure, because the distance between Xc and X 0 now results in a value difference of Δ v 3, which is perceived to be on the gain curve, which is at all points flatter than the steepest portion of the loss curve, and is therefore smaller in magnitude than Δ v 1. From the standpoint of a low reference point, the marginal disutility associated with an invasive procedure is valued as a foregone gain, and is thus perceived as less bad.
3 Mathematical Exposition
Although Figure 2 motivates the result, it is possible to prove that Δ v 1 will always represent a larger subjective loss than Δ v 2 or Δ v 3. We use the following lemma, whose proof is elementary.
Lemma 1 If f is a concave function over some interval of real numbers with f(0) = 0, then
whenever x,y and x+y are in the domain of f, and
whenever x,y and x+y are in the domain of f.
We suppose a prospect theory value function of the form
where v +,v − are increasing concave functions over the nonnegative reals with v +(0) = v −(0) = 0. We assume v +(x) ≤ v −(x) for all x, in accord with the loss aversion principle.
Let x 0 be the subject’s status quo health state, and xc = x 0 − C be the subject’s status quo health state together with some additional intervention such as colonoscopy, where C > 0. We consider the three reference points mentioned above, namely R 1 = x 0 (the base case), R 2 = x 0 + D (right-shifted reference point) and R 3 = x 0 − D (left-shifted reference point). In the left-shifted case, we assume the left shift D exceeds the decrement C due to intervention. The corresponding decrements in value are
Because xc < x 0, these are all negative quantities.
Proposition 1 (Right-shifted reference point) The decrement in value after a right shift in the reference point is less negative than the original decrement in value, that is,
Proof: Note that we have
Therefore, we have
But the last inequality is true by the concavity of v − and the first inequality in Lemma 1. QED.
Proposition 2 (Left-shifted reference point) The decrement in value after a left shift in the reference point is less negative than the original decrement in value, that is,
Proof: We have
where we have used the assumption that D exceeds C, so that D−C > 0. Then using Δ v 1 = −v −(C), we have
To demonstrate the latter inequality, note that, by the loss aversion principle,
By the concavity of v + and the second inequality in Lemma 1,
Therefore, by transitivity,
so Δ v 3 ≥ Δ v 1. QED.
4 Examples
As shown above, shifts of reference point, either to the right of baseline health or to the left of baseline health plus the invasive procedure, will shrink the disutility associated with the invasive procedure. If the invasive procedure is a recommended preventative screening test, such as colonoscopy, decreasing its disutility could be an important public health goal, if decisions to undergo screening are related to the perceived disutility of the procedure. How might potential screening recipients be induced to view their decision from either of these shifted reference points? Preliminary work with prostate cancer patients has suggested mechanisms which may motivate each of these valuable reference point shifts.
When a decision maker reflects upon his future health as he ages, he may recognize that it is likely to worsen naturally over the course of his life. From his current vantage point, then, this future health state can appear to be a relative loss. In this situation, it is as if the decision maker is examining the future focal health state (X 0) from a reference point (current health) that is significantly higher, such as R 2. When he focuses on his future health as a decrement in functioning, the additional disutility of an invasive procedure (Δ v 2) is made smaller. This experience of “diminishing marginal loss” was reported in focus groups with prostate cancer patients through statements like
“Ten years from now. …if I’m fifty-five, sixty…I’m at the end of, as they so call say, at the end of your rainbow. Ain’t too many people going to be hitting a hundred. If you are, are you going to be functional? I’m just being real … Most elderly people, they need assistance. Ain’t too many walking on their own, taking care of themselves. So hey, I would go with that longevity (and have treatment).”
(Goldberg & Schwartz, Reference Goldberg and Schwartz2007)Conversely, when a decision maker reflects about difficult past experiences, she may recognize that undergoing the invasive procedure, though unpleasant, is still better than the past state - if she handled the past state, she knows she can handle the procedure. From this vantage point (R 3), even the prospect of the procedure (Xc) is an improvement in comparison to past experiences, and treated like a foregone gain in utility rather than an additional loss. Thus, when she uses her past experience as her reference point, the disutility of the invasive procedure (Δ v 3) is again made smaller. This experience of “resiliency” was also reported in focus groups with men at high risk for prostate cancer in interactions like:
“P1: I’d have surgery, I’d get it out.”
“F: … Even though you’re going to live with these side effects.”
“P1: Yeah, I mean, I was partially paralyzed in my left hand, three and a half years, I had nerve damage really bad. So I mean… I’ve been through some rough times, so I mean =”
“P2: You live with it.”
“P1: Yeah, I’d have the surgery.”
(Goldberg & Schwartz, Reference Goldberg and Schwartz2007)5 Other Outcomes of the Screening Decision: Potential Benefit
If decision makers assume a shifted reference point in evaluating the relatively certain unpleasant experience of an invasive procedure, it is also reasonable to ask what the impact of the new reference point might be on their evaluation of other outcomes that should also motivate the decision to accept or reject the procedure. For simplicity, we assume that the primary benefit of a screening test is that it provides a small probability of resulting in an early detection of a treatable medical condition, and thus leads to treatment that provides a benefit that would not have been realized without the test. For example, a colonoscopy or pap smear that detects precancerous tissue may result in the patient receiving effective treatment that prevents the development of cancer, and thus meaningfully improves their quantity and quality of future life; this assumption is generally the rationale for recommendations of screening tests (e.g., see U.S. Preventive Services Task Force, 2003).
It is possible that different reference points may be applied to the evaluation of the utility of the test itself and to the evaluation of its potential benefit. If this is the case, and reflection on past or future experiences can be used to shift the reference point for the evaluation of the test itself without shifting the reference point for evaluation of the benefit, the propositions above predict that patients with such a reference point constellation ought to be relatively more likely to accept testing (because their disutility for the test is reduced while their appreciation of the potential benefit is unchanged).
It is perhaps more likely, however, that the new (shifted) reference point is applied to both the evaluation of the test and the evaluation of the potential benefit, shown as XT in Figure 2. In the case of a right-shifted reference point (e.g. R 2), the benefit will always be evaluated more positively than in the base case, because one portion (from X 0 to R 2) will now be evaluated on the loss curve, which is steeper than the corresponding gain curve, and the remaining portion (from R 2 to XT) will be evaluated on a steeper portion of the gain curve. That is, when the reference point is shifted to the right, the test is subjectively less unpleasant and the potential benefit is subjectively greater, which predicts a greater preference for the test. This result is independent of the probability of the benefit, but does assume that the reference point shift is not so extreme that R 2 falls to the right of XT; that is, decision makers must consider the potential benefit of a true positive screen to be greater than their anticipated natural loss of functioning due to age. For screening tests intended to prevent diseases associated with high mortality and morbidity, like colorectal or cervical cancer, we believe these are reasonable (and testable) assumptions.
In the case of a left-shifted reference point (e.g. R 3), however, the conditions under which a higher expected utility for the test would be perceived require considerably stronger assumptions that have no a priori justification. These conditions are dependent on the probability of benefit and the relative changes in the valuation of the test disutility and potential benefit.
6 Other outcomes of the screening decision: Potential harm
For simplicity, we have also assumed that the disutility of the medical procedure is completely characterized by Xc; that is, we treat the procedure’s outcome as certain. In practice, of course, invasive tests often have small but significant risks; for example, the risk of a perforated colon during a colonoscopy has been recently reported to be 0.2-0.4% in purely diagnostic procedures, and 0.3-1.0% when polyps are removed during the procedure (Bonheur & Korelitz, Reference Bonheur and Korelitz2006). As with the evaluation of Xc, a right-shifted reference point will diminish the subjective disutility associated with other potential negative outcomes, and the predicted greater willingness to accept the test should persist, independent of the probability of the potential negative outcomes.
A left-shifted reference point, however, only unconditionally attenuates the disutility when the new reference point is shifted to the left of the potential negative outcome, and few people are likely to have a salient referent that is worse than bowel perforation (which can constitute a surgical emergency). Accordingly, the impact of shifting the reference point to the left is likely to be dependent on the likelihood of potential negative outcomes and the associated decision weights.
7 Discussion
The prospect theory value function implies two ways that changes in reference points can result in a better evaluation of the anticipated experience of a potentially unpleasant invasive medical procedure: through drawing attention to future disability or through drawing attention to past disability. People who have already committed to the invasive procedure may engage in this sort of hedonic editing to reduce post-decision conflict about their choice; such editing operations have been posited in the past for financial decisions (Thaler & Johnson, Reference Thaler and Johnson1990).
Perhaps more importantly from a public health standpoint, interventions that encourage people to change their reference points in these ways may increase the likelihood of a prospective patient committing to, for example, preventative health screenings. In particular, focus on future disability (the right-shifted reference point), has an impact on prospective decision that remains even when considering changes in the evaluation of the uncertain benefit of the test or potential uncertain risks of the test.
Of the two approaches, focus on future disability is also perhaps more widely applicable as an intervention strategy, as declining health with age is likely to be a universal and universally understood phenomenon. In addition, people seem to be quite capable of making influential comparisons to imagined (counterfactual) states, and this skill ought to extend to imagined future (“antefactual”) states (Kahneman & Miller, Reference Kahneman and Miller1986; Roese & Olson, Reference Roese and Olson1995). In contrast, people who do not have signficantly distressing past experiences may not be moved by appeals to resiliency.
In effect, the reference point shift induces a contrast effect in which smaller losses are discounted in the new context which evokes larger losses (Thaler & Johnson, Reference Thaler and Johnson1990; Tversky & Griffin, Reference Tversky, Griffin, Goldstein and Hogarth1997). Such contrast effects have been observed with past experiences of physical pain (Dar, Ariely, & Frenk, Reference Dar, Ariely and Frenk1995) as well as in the evaluation of health-related quality of life (Ubel, Loewenstein, & Jepson, Reference Ubel, Loewenstein and Jepson2003), but have not, to our knowledge, been derived for health care decision making from prospect theory. We would expect this contrast effect to operate alongside (and independently of) any message framing effects associated with the description of test outcomes.
It remains for empirical investigation to discover the extent to which such an approach is effective in changing valuations, individual differences that may moderate that effectiveness, and the impact of using a combined appeal to both reference points. Because relatively little is known about the number of reference points people use simultaneously or in rapid sequence, or how judgments from multiple reference points are combined or negotiated, there is much work to do.