1. Introduction
In this article, I argue that some scientific models and modeling claims are fruitfully diagnosed as a particular kind of speech act, namely, as dogwhistles. Footnote 1 Dogwhistles, broadly speaking, are communicative acts that send different, conflicting, and often differentially inflammatory messages to different listeners, as when Republican politicians in the United States use “inner city” to evoke racial stereotypes (Saul Reference Saul2017, Reference Saul, Fogal, Harris and Moss2018). I argue that dogwhistling can arise in the context of scientific modeling in at least two ways. First, models may be dogwhistles when their targets are characterized in ways that allow differentially inflammatory interpretations among listeners, which I call representational dogwhistling. Second, claims about the adequacy of particular models for certain purposes may be dogwhistles when these purposes are characterized in ways that allow for conflicting interpretation, which I call fit-for-purpose dogwhistling. Importantly, both representational and fit-for-purpose dogwhistling can occur independently of any ill intentions of either speakers or listeners.
If I am right, this diagnosis has important consequences for our understanding of both dogwhistling and scientific communication. Because dogwhistling may effectively insulate a speaker from certain kinds of criticism, it may threaten the epistemic as well as the moral goods of science (Longino Reference Longino1990). Furthermore, Saul (Reference Saul, Fogal, Harris and Moss2018) and, to a lesser extent, Santana (Reference Santana2021) argue that diagnosing dogwhistles can play a critical role in allowing us to challenge and potentially neutralize harmful dogwhistles. If this is correct, scientists and philosophers of science might make good use of the dogwhistle diagnosis to ameliorate some harmful models and modeling claims. Furthermore, I propose that the possibility of models as dogwhistles also has important consequences for philosophers of language: it shows that unintentional dogwhistling is worthy of far more philosophical attention than it has received so far.
In section 2, I offer a brief primer on dogwhistles, drawing on recent work in linguistics and philosophy of language, especially Saul (Reference Saul, Fogal, Harris and Moss2018). In section 3, I show that models and modeling claims are the sorts of things that could, in principle, be dogwhistles. In section 4, I propose representational and fit-for-purpose dogwhistling as two ways in which this might arise. In section 5, I illustrate both representational and fit-for-purpose dogwhistling using an example from computational social science: the diversity trumps ability theorem (Hong and Page Reference Hong and Page2004). I conclude by reflecting on possible implications of models as dogwhistles and of dogwhistling more broadly for the social epistemology of science, namely, the threats it may pose to the objectivity of science and the ameliorative strategies that might prevent dogwhistles from escaping criticism in the context of peer review.
2. What are dogwhistles?
In linguistics and philosophy of language, the notion of a dogwhistle has come to refer to a particular kind of speech that only some listeners can hear. For our purposes, it is useful to think of dogwhistles as speech acts that have different, often differentially inflammatory, effects on different listeners. The differences in these effects often correspond to listeners’ affiliations with distinct social groups, their possession of some relevant background knowledge, or, as Quaranto (Reference Quaranto2022) suggests, broader “socio-politically structured linguistic practices” in their communities. For instance, the use of the phrase “inner city” by Republican politicians in the United States is now widely understood to be used in place of “Black” or “African American” in a way that invites a racist response from constituents who hear the dogwhistle, while maintaining deniability of such racism on the part of the speaker. So, when American congressman Paul Ryan remarked in 2014 that “we have got this tailspin of culture, in our inner cities in particular, of men not working and just generations of men not even thinking about working or learning the value and the culture of work,” some audience members heard only the vague “inner cities,” whereas others, who were sensitized to the dogwhistle (perhaps by racist or antiracist awareness of stereotype), heard Ryan allege that African Americans living in inner cities were lazy. Footnote 2
To be more precise, following Saul (Reference Saul, Fogal, Harris and Moss2018, 377–78), I take it that we ought to think of a dogwhistle as a perlocutionary speech act. A speech act, in the tradition indebted to J. L. Austin (Reference Austin1955), is a speaker’s action in making an utterance. For instance, if I say “I would like a double espresso” to a barista, I do not merely describe my desire; rather, I make a request. A perlocutionary act (or a perlocutionary effect) is the reaction I actually produce in my listeners with my speech act, for instance, convincing my colleagues of a particular belief. Though speakers may intend certain perlocutionary effects, we can think of these as entirely dependent on listeners’ reactions (Pagin Reference Pagin and Zalta2014). Footnote 3
A dogwhistle is best understood in terms of these perlocutionary effects, specifically, as a type of perlocutionary act that produces different effects in different listeners (Saul Reference Saul, Fogal, Harris and Moss2018). In a canonical instance, like the use of a code word, this might depend on listeners who are “in the know” making an inference that others cannot (Khoo Reference Khoo2017, Reference Khoo, Khoo and Sterken2021). In more complicated cases, everyone may “hear” a dogwhistle that violates a social norm, and listeners may respond differently because they differ in their commitment to the norm (Santana Reference Santana2021). Santana’s approach, though not defined in terms of perlocutionary effects, captures a key feature of dogwhistles that distinguishes them from other, more ordinary cases in which a speech act produces multiple effects or interpretations. This is because Santana points out that a critical function of a dogwhistle is to provide plausible deniability to a speaker for an interpretation that might constitute a norm violation when heard by the wrong audience (see also Fear Reference Fear2007; Witten Reference Witten2023; Quaranto Reference Quaranto2022; cf. Saul Reference Saul, Fogal, Harris and Moss2018; Drainville and Saul, Reference Drainville, Saul, Anderson and Leporeforthcoming). So, following Saul, I take a dogwhistle to be a speech act that produces at least two distinct perlocutionary effects, and following Santana, I expect that one of these effects amounts to a norm violation and that ambiguity about which effect was intended affords a speaker plausible deniability about violating the norm.
That being said, I follow Santana (Reference Santana2021) closely but not blindly. Santana argues that we should restrict the definition of dogwhistling to speech involving norm violations having to do with egalitarianism. I disagree. Although many dogwhistles are political, they need not be: for instance, Witten (Reference Witten2023) gives examples of coded messages for adult audiences within children’s television programming, such as sexual innuendos that children do not “hear,” and Drainville and Saul (Reference Drainville, Saul, Anderson and Leporeforthcoming) argue that artistic practices like iconography can also constitute visual dogwhistles. As I’ll argue, dogwhistles that promote multiple interpretations of a model are bad because they insulate scientists from criticism, and they do this even when the interpretations themselves are not antiegalitarian.
Thinking of dogwhistles as perlocutionary acts is helpful for two reasons. First, Saul (Reference Saul, Fogal, Harris and Moss2018) convincingly argues that this description can adequately account for much of what philosophers take to be interesting and important about dogwhistles: that they may be intentional or unintentional and that they may be overt (transparent to the listener) or covert (opaque to the listener, such that the listener is not conscious of their effects). What Saul characterizes as unintentional dogwhistles, or “unwitting use of words and/or images that, used intentionally, constitute an intentional dogwhistle, where this use has the same effect as an intentional dogwhistle” (368), may be just as pernicious as intentional dogwhistles. Because of this, it is important that characterizing dogwhistles in terms of perlocutionary effects also allows us to diagnose dogwhistling without knowledge of speaker intentions. Knowing other people’s intentions is often epistemically risky business at best and intractable at worst. Furthermore, we want our account of dogwhistling to at least potentially accommodate a good deal of actual scientific communication, and the widespread practices of collaboration and coauthorship make intentions even more unpalatable for these purposes. Relatedly, this framework allows us to challenge a dogwhistle without accusing a speaker of ill intentions, which they can often simply deny. For instance, if our challenge to Paul Ryan’s dogwhistle hangs on our allegation that he intended to say that African Americans are lazy, he can deny (as he did; see Corn Reference Corn2014) that he intended any such meaning. Although intentions likely matter for other important projects, I want to diagnose dogwhistles independently of speaker intentions; otherwise, it may be impossible in practice.
Though perhaps unintuitive, this independence from intentions is especially important in developing a diagnosis for dogwhistles in scientific practice. This is because listener uptake of public scientific communication is often subject (at least in theory) to a norm of charitability of interpretation. Footnote 4 That is, broadly speaking, listener uptake and criticism of scientific communication are or ought to be governed by an attitude of good faith, which might be directed toward either what meaning we think the speaker intends to convey or what we think the speaker intends to do with their speech act (i.e., what perlocutionary effects they intend). Ideally, we would like our diagnosis of scientific dogwhistling to come apart from the inflammatory listener responses that might result from uncharitable or bad faith interpretation. Footnote 5 To accommodate this, I need my account of dogwhistles in science to be a bit stronger still: I will say that in addition to achieving deniability for a norm violation, a dogwhistle is a perlocutionary speech act that has different and differentially inflammatory effects among different good faith listeners. This adaptation of the perlocutionary account still allows us to cover a lot of ground. If good faith is directed toward the meaning of the speech itself, dogwhistles might allow for conflicting good faith interpretations of the same speech act when different listeners have different background knowledge (I’ll elaborate on this possibility in section 4). If this good faith is directed toward the effects the speaker might intend to bring about, then we can remain charitable while hearing a dogwhistle because dogwhistling can occur whether the speaker intends it to or not. So, the perlocutionary framework can account for the rather obvious fact that scientific speech can have important consequences the speaker didn’t intend, even when speaking to a good faith charitable audience.
3. Models can be speech acts
With this account of dogwhistling more or less in hand, I’ll now argue that both claims about models and models themselves can be dogwhistles. In so doing, I do not by any means purport to exhaust the possibilities for dogwhistling in science; rather, it seems to me that models might not strike us as obvious candidates for a dogwhistling diagnosis, relative to other sorts of scientific speech acts. To the extent that this is the case, it seems to me that they make for a more interesting and, potentially, surprising philosophical target.
Many scientific practices go by the name of modeling, and philosophers recognize a rich taxonomy of models (e.g., minimal models [Batterman and Rice Reference Batterman and Rice2014; Chirimuuta Reference Chirimuuta2014], toy models [Reutlinger, Hangleiter, and Hartmann Reference Reutlinger, Hangleiter and Hartmann2018], physical models [Contessa Reference Contessa2010]). Despite this heterogeneity, philosophers of science generally (though not unanimously) agree that many models have in common a few features that are particularly important for our analysis. First, models depart in some way from complete description or reproduction of their targets, which is some aspect of the world (and where the ontological statuses of both “model” and “target” are compatible with a diverse array of metaphysical commitments or lack thereof) (Morgan and Morrison Reference Morgan and Morrison1999; Contessa Reference Contessa2010; Giere Reference Giere2010).Footnote 6 Second, models are good for something, and some models or combinations of models are better than others for a given purpose (Giere Reference Giere2004, Reference Giere2010; Weisberg Reference Weisberg2012, Reference Weisberg2013; Parker Reference Parker2009, Reference Parker2015, Reference Parker2020). This notion is perhaps best developed in Parker’s (Reference Parker2009) well-known adequacy-for-purpose account, where she writes that “a model is a tool in that it is used in the service of particular goals or purposes; typically these purposes involve answering some limited range of questions about the target system” (235).
To show that models and modeling claims might function as dogwhistles in the sense described, I’ll first need to show that at least some models and claims about models can be appropriately understood as the sorts of things that could, in principle, be dogwhistles. Next, I’ll sketch two ways in which we can subject models to a speech act–theoretic framework. We can understand models and modeling claims as two kinds of speech acts: assertion and representation. If this seems obvious, I invite you to skip ahead to section 4.
3.1 Assertion
First, claims about models can be understood as assertions. Assertion is a term of art in the speech act theory literature, where it refers to a constative speech act, or an action aimed at saying something about matters of fact (Pagin Reference Pagin and Zalta2014). For instance, I might assert that my dog does not enjoy baths. Franco (Reference Franco2017, Reference Franco2019) convincingly argues that we can understand many scientific utterances as assertions and further argues that the commitments of assertion play an important role in the social epistemology of science, including publication. Footnote 7 Following Franco, I take it that among the things that scientists assert (and for our purposes, we can concern ourselves only with what they assert publicly, i.e., in print) are claims about models. Because assertions can produce multiple, differentially inflammatory perlocutionary effects, and this ambiguity can afford a speaker plausible deniability about a norm violation, claims about models, as assertions, are the sorts of things that we can properly understand as dogwhistle candidates.
3.2 Representation
Second, modeling itself can be a speech act. Although I suspect that we could gerrymander assertion to accommodate modeling, I will argue that scientific modeling is a particular class of speech act with its own specific commitments: representation. How might this work? First, a model itself can count as an utterance. According to Pagin (Reference Pagin and Zalta2014), for Austin and many of his interpreters, an utterance can be so permissive as to include any “physical item, event or state of affairs by means of which a speaker communicates.” Footnote 8 For instance, Dixon (Reference Dixon2022) argues that art can be understood in a speech act theoretic framework; see also Novitz (Reference Novitz1977) and Drainville and Saul (Reference Drainville, Saul, Anderson and Leporeforthcoming). Second, in putting forth a model, scientists are (at least sometimes) doing so with the aim of representing. Giere’s philosophy of modeling is helpful here. Giere (Reference Giere2004) argues that as a matter of scientific practice, models are used to represent and that representing is a fundamental activity of science. On his (2010) account, he cashes this out as follows: “Agents (1) intend; (2) to use model, M; (3) to represent a part of the world, W; (4) for some purpose, P” (Giere Reference Giere2010, 269). Giere rather handily ties this account of modeling to linguistic practice for us. Footnote 9
The point of accounting for modeling as representation is not to proliferate distinctions but rather to suggest that representation, as its own kind of speech act, might come with a specific set of commitments. Footnote 10 I propose that we can think of representing as committing the speaker(s) (or modelers) to taking responsibility for defending or providing justification for the model in terms of its adequacy for some particular purpose à la Parker (Reference Parker2020). I suspect that this is an important departure from assertion insofar as it more explicitly allows us to proceed without expecting models to be true, approximately true, or even the sort of thing that could, in principle, be true or false (see, e.g., Elgin Reference Elgin2007; Contessa Reference Contessa2010; Frigg and Nguyen Reference Frigg and Nguyen2016). Because various sorts of departures from the whole truth are often taken to be a defining feature of models, it is important that representation not commit modelers to justifying models as true or false in a sense that we might want to leave open for assertion. Instead, following Parker (Reference Parker2009, Reference Parker2020), I propose that representing invites listeners to proceed as if the model were adequate for the purposes described. Understood as an act of representation, a model (or, perhaps more accurately, modeling) is the sort of thing that we can properly understand as a dogwhistle candidate. As with assertion, this is not simply because the purposes of models may be vague but more specifically because when this ambiguity produces multiple interpretations, one purpose may be a norm violation (say, an illegitimate goal), while another may not; this kind of ambiguity gets a modeler off the hook for the norm violation.
4. Two kinds of dogwhistles
Now that I have established that both models and modeling claims are dogwhistle candidates, let me elaborate a couple of ways in which I think they may be particularly likely to actually become dogwhistles. Recall that, for our purposes, a dogwhistle is a perlocutionary speech act that has different effects among different good faith listeners, that it provides plausible deniability about norm-violating effects, and that these effects might very well be unintentional. I think that there are at least two means by which models can produce different (and differentially inflammatory) effects in distinct groups of charitable listeners, both of which concern the adequacy-for-purpose of models in relation to their targets. The first, which I’ll call representational dogwhistling, concerns the characterization of targets. The second, which I’ll call fit-for-purpose dogwhistling, concerns the characterization of the purposes for which the model is supposed to be adequate. Characterizing representational targets and purposes are obviously closely related in scientific practice, and my concern is not to impose an arbitrary distinction between the two; rather, I aim to suggest that they are worth considering separately for philosophical purposes, even if they are often two sides of the same coin.
4.1 Representational dogwhistling
Recall that, generally speaking, models differ in some way from whatever it is they might be thought to relate to and, furthermore, that this model–target relation is often (if not always) something other than complete description of this target. Whatever we might take a target to be (e.g., “part of the world” [Giere Reference Giere2010], “possible concrete objects” [Contessa Reference Contessa2010]), an important aspect of representation is specifying what the model is, or could be, a model of. In Giere’s parlance, the representation or claim that M is a model of W that is good for some purpose P entails that M is a model of W, and representing involves characterizing what part of the world W in which we are interested. Models and modeling claims can produce different and conflicting understandings of a model’s target in different listeners. Furthermore, depending on the general nature of the target, these interpretations may be differentially inflammatory or norm violating. I’ll call these representational dogwhistles.
Perhaps the most intuitive sense in which this might be the case is when modelers characterize their targets in terms that are particularly vague. This would seem to invite different and perhaps conflicting interpretations from listeners with different background knowledge. For instance, suppose an economist put forth a model for which they characterized their target as “employment in inner-city populations in the United States” (which, as far as I know, nobody has actually done). Those of us who are familiar with the historical use of inner city to mean “African American” might interpret the model as being a model of African American employment, and, depending on the context, this might produce an inflammatory response, perhaps by inciting our racism or (we can hope) by arousing our moral indignation at a perceived instance of racism. By contrast, those who are not aware of this more specific meaning might interpret the model in the more general, innocuous sense.
However, this might be an unsatisfying example because it seems parasitic on a preexisting dogwhistle, inner city. So, consider a different case. A modeler wants to represent some target W that they do not take to exist, say, a possible future scenario, entertained for the sake of argument. Call this target possible-W. If the modeler presents M as a model of W without specifying that they take W to be a possible, not an actual, case, then some listeners may take M to represent W as a feature of the world, whereas others may take M to represent possible-W. At least in some discursive contexts (namely, those that are given to frequently modeling both Ws and possible-Ws), I submit that these conflicting interpretations may both be charitable ones. If this is right, then in the case that positing possible-W as an actual feature of the world is inflammatory (say, the scenario is one in which possible-W is the condition that women are essentially worse at analytic philosophy), we can expect these interpretations to be differentially inflammatory among different listeners. Furthermore, although this possible–actual distinction concerns the target, it could also concern the sort of explanation a model might provide (see Bokulich Reference Bokulich2014). Note that this needn’t be an intention of the modeler: it may just be some intellectual sloppiness on their part, or it may be that they intend their model for an audience who would have the additional background knowledge that Ws are never to be taken as actual in this particular context, but some nonexpert listeners sneak in or eavesdrop. It seems that our nonexperts are not properly thought of as uncharitable in this context but rather as less well informed. If this is right, then we could have a nonparasitic case of unintentional representational dogwhistling on our hands. Footnote 11
4.2 Fit-for-purpose dogwhistling
The second sense in which models can function as dogwhistles depends on our characterization of models as adequate for some purpose and, more specifically, on what we take this purpose to be. If we stick with Giere, model-purpose characterization is an important component of representation, as representing involves not just the claim that M is a model of W but the claim that it is good for P. Here we are interested in characterizing P.
Like target characterizations, purpose characterizations may produce different and conflicting understandings of a model’s purpose in different listeners. Depending on the nature of these interpretations, they may be differentially inflammatory. I’ll call these fit-for-purpose dogwhistles. Like representational dogwhistles, fit-for-purpose dogwhistles can be parasitic on preexisting dogwhistles, but they need not be so. Fit-for-purpose dogwhistles might also arise in cases in which the purpose of a model is sufficiently unclear so as to allow conflicting listener understandings of what that purpose might be. This might include cases in which the purpose of a model is not explicitly specified at all. This is because, if I am right about representing, modeling entails a commitment that the model is good for some purpose, even if that purpose is not specified, and it therefore authorizes listeners to infer that the modeler has some purpose in mind.
To see how model-purpose characterizations might produce differentially inflammatory interpretations of a model’s purpose, consider a model for which the modelers take its purpose to be figuring as a premise in a conditional argument with other inflammatory or norm-violating premises. If a listener believes an inflammatory premise I, then they ought to be convinced by the model M to behave in a particular way. The modelers take the purpose of M to be convincing a subset of listeners who believe I, and the modelers themselves are neutral or skeptical with regard to the goodness of I. If the conditional status of the purpose of M is unclear, a listener may instead infer that the modelers actually believe I and therefore that the purpose of M is to convince everyone, taking I for granted. A listener who infers that the modelers take for granted that the listener believes I may (or may not) be offended by the perceived taking-for-granted of an inflammatory premise.
We can intuitively extend this possibility to sufficiently vague claims about the further purposes to which a model might be put, especially when it may be unclear in virtue of what the model is fit for some further purpose. For instance, if a paper is framed in terms of a purpose of general social interest, such as intervening on the possible causal relationship between socioeconomic status (SES) and obesity, and the paper offers a model of a much more specific phenomenon, such as the correlation between SES and obesity for a number of Pittsburgh zip codes, for the purpose of understanding the distribution of both SES and obesity, it may be unclear in virtue of what the more specific model is adequate for the more general purpose. Footnote 12 Extending a model to additional purposes might involve asserting or assuming that two purposes (or two targets) are similar or analogous in some relevant way. Because claims about the similarity or difference of potential targets may be inflammatory, we might reasonably expect extrapolation from one purpose to another to be another potential source of fit-for-purpose dogwhistling.
These two mechanisms almost certainly do not exhaust the possibilities of model-related dogwhistling in science, but they seem as good a place to start as any other. In section 5, I’ll illustrate how representational and fit-for-purpose dogwhistling might arise in a case of mathematical modeling: Hong and Page’s (Reference Hong and Page2004) diversity trumps ability theorem.
5. The case of the diversity trumps ability theorem
In their 2004 article “Groups of Diverse Problem Solvers Can Outperform Groups of High-Ability Problem Solvers,” Lu Hong and Scott Page present what they call “a general framework for modeling functionally diverse problem-solving agents” (16385). Using a mathematical model and computer simulations, Hong and Page claim to show that a group of diverse agents performs better than a group of highest-performing agents on a hard problem. This is commonly known as the diversity trumps ability theorem (Anderson Reference Anderson2006). We can use the diversity trumps ability theorem to illustrate the possibility of both representational and fit-for-purpose dogwhistling in science. Although this result, and, in particular, the mathematical theorem behind it have been the target of both celebration and criticism (e.g., Thompson Reference Thompson2014; cf. Kuehn Reference Kuehn2017), my concern is to demonstrate how both the target of their model and the purpose for which the model is supposed to be adequate may invite different and differentially inflammatory interpretations. Whether the model is actually a good representation of any target for any particular purpose is beside the point (for evaluation, see Grim et al. Reference Grim, Singer, Bramson, Holman, McGeehan and Berger2019; Reijula and Kuorikoski Reference Reijula and Kuorikoski2021; Kassam, Reference Kassamforthcoming). Footnote 13
5.1 Diversity, ability, and representational dogwhistling
Let’s start with the target or targets of the model. At least one target of the model in Hong and Page (Reference Hong and Page2004) is described in the title as “diverse problem solvers.” The characterization of “diverse problem solvers” has resulted in different and conflicting interpretations of both “diverse” and “solvers.” Specifically, it has been variously interpreted to refer to functionally diverse algorithms (where functionally diverse refers to differences in search strategies for a specific sequential search problem), functionally diverse people, and demographically diverse people (at least to the extent that demographic or “identity” diversity causes relevant cognitive diversity; see Page Reference Page2007a). For instance, Anderson (Reference Anderson2006, 12) characterizes the paper as “initially constructed to model problem solving within firms.” By contrast, mathematician Abigail Thompson (Reference Thompson2014, 1026) writes, “A ‘problem-solver’ strongly suggests an individual person. However as Hong and Page are using the word, a ‘problem-solver’ is an algorithm.” Thompson thinks the move from algorithms to people in this paper is a norm violation: “an example of the misuse of mathematics” (1024), inappropriately applying the idealized model to the context of diversity initiatives in universities. “What the paper emphatically does not contain is information that can be applied to any real-world situation involving actual people,” she writes (1029). In response, Kuehn (Reference Kuehn2017) argues that Thompson’s (Reference Thompson2014) interpretation of the model is incorrect because she does not understand the norms of mathematical modeling in social science. Specifically, Kuehn claims that models in social science “typically illustrate a non-exhaustive set of mechanisms at work in society that have too many moving parts to be fruitfully expressed or convincingly demonstrated using prose,” as opposed to models in the physical sciences, which “reflect actual physical phenomena quite closely” (73). Some (if not all) of these different and conflicting interpretations seem to be charitable: Anderson (Reference Anderson2006) cites Hong and Page to extoll the value of their argument for the epistemology of democracy; Kuehn (Reference Kuehn2017) argues for this interpretation to defend the paper against Thompson, and although Thompson has been accused of being uncharitable in her critique (which also concerns more technical features of the 2004 paper), interpretations of the target as either persons or algorithms are consistent with the language of the paper.
This discussion reflects two possible ambiguities about the model’s target. First, it is unclear whether demographic diversity specifically counts among the legitimate targets of the model. Consider that Hong and Page (Reference Hong and Page2004) frame their paper as an answer to a question about people: “Can a functionally diverse group whose members have less ability outperform a group of people with high ability who may themselves be diverse? The main result of our paper addresses exactly this question” (16385). They characterize their result in terms of agents—“we find that a random collection of agents drawn from a large set of limited-ability agents typically outperforms a collection of the very best agents from that same set” (16386)—and operationalize agents in their mathematical model and computer simulation just in terms of their strategies for a particular difficult search task. While Hong and Page claim to exclusively model functional cognitive diversity and merely frame this in terms of discussions of identity diversity and affirmative action cases, Page (Reference Page2007a, Reference Page2007b) further elaborates conditions under which identity diversity might yield functional diversity. In his book The Difference, Page (Reference Page2007a) explicitly discusses admissions as an application of his argument, which draws on the 2004 paper as well as other models. “The logic in this book can be used to support an instrumental argument for affirmative action…. The extent to which this logic supports race-based affirmative action depends on empirical facts: either identity diversity correlates with cognitive diversity or it does not,” he writes (49).
Second, it is ambiguous whether the model should be understood as figuring in a possible or actual explanation of its target(s). Page (Reference Page2007a, 394) presents empirical data with the caveat that “the models that we covered do not provide the only candidate explanations for the empirical phenomena we discuss. Other models might better explain some or all of these empirical regularities.” This aligns with Page’s (Reference Page2015) argument that the model provides sufficient conditions for a phenomenon, which would suggest that it provides a how-possibly explanation (by analogy to, e.g., Wu Reference Wu2023). Page (Reference Page2015, 10) responds to Thompson along these lines:
The note accuses me of misusing mathematics, claiming that I imply that the mathematical results are somehow fact in the world of people. The accusation is baseless. In my book, I caution readers to apply mathematical models carefully, highlighting the subtleties of moving from the starkness of mathematical logic to the richness of human interactions. Not everyone understands the role of mathematical claims in the social sciences.
Nonetheless, the primary motivation for the book seems to be the actual salience of these models to cognitive diversity in admissions, firms, and teams, and Page devotes careful (even critical) attention to empirical support for their relevance in these contexts. Given that the book was also written for a broad audience, who seem no more likely than mathematicians to be familiar with the norms of modeling in social science, it is plausible that charitable readers could form different interpretations as to whether the model could figure in an actual explanation of anything about its target(s). Kuehn and Page both interpret Thompson’s complaint as stemming from her understanding of the role of the mathematical model; Page uses this to deny the misuse of mathematics. If they are right, and her charge depends on either of these conflicting interpretations of the model’s target or its relation to it, the model is a representational dogwhistle. Footnote 14
5.2 Diversity, ability, and fit-for-purpose dogwhistling
Let’s turn to the purpose of the model. In section 4, I argued that one way fit-for-purpose dogwhistling can occur is when the modelers take a model’s purpose to be figuring as a premise in a conditional argument with another inflammatory premise, I. If the conditional status of the purpose of the model M is unclear, a listener may instead infer that the modelers actually believe I and therefore that the purpose of M is to convince everyone, taking I for granted. If some listeners are offended by the perceived taking-for-granted of an inflammatory premise, this can produce a fit-for-purpose dogwhistle. Now I’ll argue that we can use the diversity trumps ability paper as an example of this sort.
Many philosophers and social scientists have interpreted the purpose of the model in Hong and Page (Reference Hong and Page2004) to be to provide justification for preferring epistemic and sometimes demographic diversity in epistemic communities. (For a concise review, see Grim et al. Reference Grim, Singer, Bramson, Holman, McGeehan and Berger2019, 98–99.) For instance, Thompson (Reference Thompson2014, 1024) characterizes the paper as an “[attempt] to find a mathematical justification for ‘diversity’ as practiced in universities”; Anderson (Reference Anderson2006, 12) writes that it “supports the claim that democracy, which allows everyone to have a hand in collective problem solving, is epistemically superior to technocracy, or rule by experts”; and Grim et al. (Reference Grim, Singer, Bramson, Holman, McGeehan and Berger2019, 98) argue that the result “suggests that an organization is epistemically better off by recruiting a diverse set of candidates instead of just selecting the best individual performers.” Footnote 15 We might worry that these examples reflect these authors’ making use of the model for their own purposes or extending it beyond what Hong and Page (Reference Hong and Page2004) originally authorized. But, at a minimum, Hong and Page assert that their model has possible consequences for organizations and for educational policy. For instance, they write that the result of their model “has implications for organizational forms and management styles, especially for problem-solving firms and organizations” (16389). In addition to the firm example, they write that “even if we were to accept the claim that IQ tests, Scholastic Aptitude Test scores, and college grades predict individual problem-solving ability, they may not be as important in determining a person’s potential contribution as a problem solver as would be measures of how differently that person thinks” (16389). They conclude, “We should do more than just exploit our existing diversity. We may want to encourage even greater functional diversity, given its advantages” (16389, emphasis added).
Thus it is at least understandable that some listeners take Hong and Page to be arguing that their result justifies increasing diversity and that this justification rests on the epistemic advantage conferred by the diversity of the group of problem solvers. We can interpret this in at least two ways. On one interpretation, Hong and Page assert that this justification for increasing diversity plays a role in a conditional argument like the following:
-
(1) If you think exploitability is a good reason to increase the diversity of an epistemic community, then this model provides justification for doing so.
On another interpretation, Hong and Page assert that this justification for increasing diversity plays a role in an argument like the following:
-
(2) Because exploitability is a good reason to increase the diversity of an epistemic community, this model provides justification for doing so.
For listeners who are committed to the relative priority of various moral or exploitability-independent reasons for increasing the diversity (epistemic or otherwise) of epistemic communities, (2) may be inflammatory in a way that (1) is not. These conflicting interpretations of Hong and Page’s characterization of the purpose of their model stand in very different relationships to the affirmative action cases against which the paper is framed; whereas (1) is agnostic about the appropriateness of exploitability (as opposed to, say, considerations of justice or the intrinsic value of diversity) as a reason to support affirmative action, (2) instrumentalizes diversity.
6. Dogwhistles threaten the objectivity of science
In sections 4 and 5, I hope to have shown that we can (at least sometimes) diagnose models as dogwhistles. Now I’ll briefly argue that we should. One reason to diagnose dogwhistling seems obvious, especially because we began with the example of Ryan’s racist dogwhistle: dogwhistling can cause serious harm, and it might be the sort of thing for which we’d like to assign responsibility, sanctions, or blame, or at least take care to avoid. Given the tremendous epistemic authority and practical import of scientific communication, we might be particularly worried about the harms of dogwhistling in a scientific context when the stakes are high; in this sense, possible dogwhistling might be a source of epistemic risk or of more broadly pragmatic, as well as ethical, considerations (Biddle and Kukla Reference Biddle, Kukla, Elliott and Richards2017). Inflammatory characterizations of particular targets (i.e., populations) or the perception of untrustworthy purposes may contribute to public distrust of science. Our desire to avoid the harms of dogwhistling is an important potential avenue for so-called nonepistemic social and political values in science, and perhaps also for our thinking about the epistemic and testimonial responsibilities of scientific experts (Daukas Reference Daukas and Grasswick2011; Almassi Reference Almassi2012; Franco Reference Franco2017, Reference Franco2019; John Reference John2018, Reference John2019; Kelsall Reference Kelsall2020; Khalifa and Millson Reference Khalifa and Millson2020; Dang and Bright Reference Dang and Kofi Bright2021). Dogwhistling may jeopardize the trustworthiness or increase the epistemic risk of scientific communication, and it may purposefully or inadvertently perpetuate harmful speech. We can think of these as harms in a traditionally ethical sense of the word.
But diagnosing dogwhistles also has important consequences in a more restricted epistemic sense. This is because at least some dogwhistles, in some contexts, may be immune to criticism. As many feminist philosophers of science and social epistemologists have argued, criticism and dissent play important roles in the well-functioning social epistemology of science (e.g., Longino Reference Longino1990; Solomon Reference Solomon2001; Intemann Reference Intemann and Grasswick2011; and [small world] Anderson Reference Anderson2006). Perhaps most famously, Longino (Reference Longino1990) argues that the possibility of transformative criticism and the social structures that guarantee the possibility of sincere uptake of scientific criticism are so important that a scientific community cannot be said to be objective in any meaningful sense without them. If some dogwhistles escape criticism by avoiding detection, or, as Santana (Reference Santana2021) convincingly argues, if they are sometimes designed to be immune to criticism even when they are detected, then they pose a serious threat to the epistemic as well as the moral goods of science.
One way dogwhistling might escape criticism is, as we have seen, by allowing scientists plausible deniability about both their targets and the intended purposes of their work. This threatens the objectivity of science because it insulates dogwhistlers from criticism by allowing them to deny that norm-violating interpretations of their work were intended: if a critic points out that a model has, say, antiegalitarian representations or purposes, the modelers can point to the alternative interpretation to claim that they are being misunderstood. The intentions framework also helps dogwhistlers to make challenging dogwhistling a costly activity for would-be critics, as dogwhistlers can argue that critics are being uncharitable, inappropriately political, or dogmatically motivated in their assessment of speaker intentions when they “hear” a dogwhistle (Khoo Reference Khoo, Khoo and Sterken2021). Furthermore, successful dogwhistles also insulate dogwhistled content from scrutiny via what Howdle (Reference Howdle2023) calls “information balkanization.” In other words, if successful dogwhistles are not “heard” by would-be critics, they not only evade criticism but may not even be subject to it.
A second way that dogwhistles can escape criticism is when they are what Saul (Reference Saul, Fogal, Harris and Moss2018, 361) calls “covert dogwhistles.” On her account, whereas overt dogwhistles are those coded messages that the listener recognizes as such, covert dogwhistles are more slippery. In Saul’s historical example, a political advertisement that used the phrase “violent crime” while showing an image of a Black person functioned as a covert dogwhistle because, for some viewers, it appealed to racist stereotypes without doing so in a way that was consciously accessible to those viewers. Saul argues that undiagnosed covert dogwhistles escape certain sorts of criticism precisely because we do not see them at work. For Saul, a covert dogwhistle might “[allow] for people to be manipulated in ways that they would resist if the manipulation was carried out more openly—often drawing on racist attitudes that are consciously rejected” (361). This seems especially likely when listeners consciously hold, for example, egalitarian values but still maintain something like implicit bias. Importantly, for Saul, covert dogwhistles do not survive transparency: they do not have the same effect when they are made overt. When the more inflammatory potential of a speech act is made clear, dogwhistles can at least sometimes be challenged and even ameliorated. This suggests an important epistemological role for the dogwhistle diagnosis in science: it may enable certain kinds of resistance to, and criticism of, some models and claims about models that might otherwise persist in the shadowy realm of the covert. In this regard, the dogwhistle diagnosis may thus support the objectivity of scientific inquiry in the same way as so many other mechanisms that protect and encourage criticism.
In light of this, I’ll briefly propose three specific practical recommendations by which we might hope to avoid or ameliorate dogwhistling in science. First, it should be obvious by now that we ought to be on the lookout for dogwhistles in scientific communication. Specifically, because I’ve argued that dogwhistling may arise due to differences in listener background knowledge, we ought to be especially wary of unintentional dogwhistling in cases in which scientific communication might be expected to reach a broad audience who probably have such differences. For instance, Hong and Page’s 2004 paper appeared in the Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, a generalist journal with a broad readership that spans many academic disciplines, and Page’s (Reference Page2007a) book further popularized the model. Authors, editors, and reviewers for venues where such a broad audience is not only likely but expected might take special care to notice and ameliorate potentially inflammatory ambiguities before such papers go to press. Similarly, scientific communication that is intended or expected to reach a nonexpert or public audience might warrant special care. Second, journals and editors can allow longer articles, which give authors more space to clarify the scope of their models and to head off potentially inflammatory interpretations.Footnote 16 Third, in cases in which it is particularly important to avoid dogwhistling, editors might select additional reviewers precisely in virtue of their demographic differences or differences in expertise, because such differences might make it more likely that a reviewer will “hear” a dogwhistle before a paper is published (Wylie Reference Wylie2012). In light of our discussion of the diversity trumps ability theorem, it strikes me as particularly interesting to note that, if one is in the business of justifying the need for diversity of particular epistemic communities, this might be another (instrumental) reason to do so.
7. Conclusion
In this article, I have argued that we can and sometimes ought to diagnose models as dogwhistles. I’ve characterized two possible forms of dogwhistling with an eye toward modeling in scientific practice: representational and fit-for-purpose dogwhistling. We saw how these might work in the example of a mathematical model of diverse problem solvers. I strongly doubt that this is the only case of dogwhistling in the modeling literature. Because dogwhistling poses both a moral and an epistemic threat to science, I have argued that we ought to be on the lookout for potential dogwhistles and suggested a couple of places we might look. Because this account of dogwhistles is compatible with unintentional dogwhistling and charitable listeners, it is more amenable to challenging dogwhistle speech than it otherwise might be.
The dogwhistle diagnosis ought to be a fruitful one for scientists and for philosophers of science—but not only for philosophers of science: by extending the notion of dogwhistles to scientific practice in this particular way, we have learned some things about dogwhistling itself. I have tried to show how much ground we can cover with the notion of an unintentional dogwhistle and with a presumption of charitability. If this is right, then unintentional dogwhistling seems to be much more varied, interesting, and worthy of philosophical attention than it has so far been considered. Though I stop far short of a complete account of dogwhistling in science, these possibilities lead me to hope that future work might continue to be productive for scientists and for philosophers of language as well as for philosophers of science.
Acknowledgments
Thanks to Kevin Zollman, Carlos Santana, Mike Dietrich, Dasha Pruss, Alnica Visser, Taylor Koles, Will Conner, Greg Kehne, and audiences at the PSA 2020/2021 poster sessions for their generous suggestions, ideas, and expertise. Thanks also to the reviewers, who were very kind, constructive, and helpful in playing along with this article.