In colonies … violence almost inevitably breaks out. Hence that kind of bloody foolhardiness that seizes the explorer in connection with races he deems inferior. The superiority that he arrogates tends, as though independently, to assert itself brutally, without object or reason, for the mere pleasure of asserting itself. It produces a veritable intoxication, an excessive exaltation of self, a sort of megalomania, which goes to the worst extremes … nothing restrains him; he overflows in violence, quite like the tyrant.
Émile Durkheim, Moral EducationTexts that are inertly of their time stay there: those which brush up unstintingly against historical constraints are the ones we keep with us, generation after generation.
Edward Said, Freud and the Non-EuropeanThose who nowadays set themselves up as judges and distribute praise and blame among the sociologists and ethnologists of the colonial past would be better occupied in trying to understand what it was that prevented the most lucid and best intentioned of those they condemn from understanding things which are now self-evident for even the least lucid and sometimes the least well intentioned observers.
Pierre Bourdieu, The Logic of PracticeIntroduction
Émile Durkheim's Elementary Forms of the Religious Life is a foundational text in the sociology of knowledge.Footnote 1 Determining Durkheim's views of colonialism and empire is therefore as important for intellectual historians as it is for sociologists. If Durkheim's work “bore the mark of empire,” as Raewyn Connell claims, we need to then ask, what exactly are these “marks”?Footnote 2 Do such “marks” undermine any argument that we should keep Durkheim's texts with us, generation after generation? Conversely, are Durkheim's ideas about colonialism more ambiguous and even more useful for ongoing work on colonial and imperial history? Do marks of empire coexist in his writing with ideas that that discomfit political verities, unsettle social-scientific doxa, and gesture toward new understandings of colonialism and empire?
In fact, Durkheim was critical of the forms of colonialism and continental empire that existed during his lifetime. He rejected the hierarchical, civilizational, and racist discourses that accompanied modern European colonial conquest and rule. Durkheim's critique of colonialism and empire is related to his general theory of social morality and moral deregulation. He was adamantly opposed to despotic empires that exist “without internal acquiescence from their subjects.” Against militarism and empire, he advocated an international system of states based on morality.Footnote 3
This article proceeds as follows. The first section presents some of the leading interpretations of Durkheim. The second section examines Durkheim's explicit discussions of colonial and imperial phenomena, before discussing several additional relevant themes: his sociology of morality; his views of race, racism, and civilizational hierarchy; and his theory of pathological and anomic social conditions.
The third section compares Durkheim's views of colonialism to leading figures in nineteenth-century French sociology and neighboring disciplines, concluding that his views located him on the critical edge of French anticolonialism before World War I. The fourth section examines Durkheim's influence on French sociological writing on colonialism and empire between his death in 1917 and the early 1960s, when the French empire wound down.Footnote 4 This discussion finds that Durkheim's legacy occupied a central position in French sociological writing that explicitly thematized and theorized colonialism during the middle decades of the twentieth century. The conclusion turns to the current “postcolonial” criticism of Durkheim and asks how his ideas might contribute to further research on colonialism and empire.
I: some leading interpretations of Durkheim
There are at least five interpretations of Durkheim's thought that are worth considering here, because they shed specific light on the question of his views of colonialism and social organization more generally.Footnote 5
Some of the oldest readings of Durkheim describe him as a conservative theorist of social order, social reproduction, and consensus.Footnote 6 A few even argued that Durkheimian sociology was proto-fascist.Footnote 7 I will contribute to the literature that puts these older theories to rest by marshaling evidence about Durkheim's anticolonialism, which situated him closer to the socialists and the political left at the time.
A second reading calls attention to Durkheim's interest in politics and power and his writings on the state, democracy and despotism, socialism, and political theory.Footnote 8 Several writers emphasize that Durkheim “never lost his fascination for the ‘social question’,” and supported “a more equitable distributive justice,” “welfare as a social responsibility,” “some level of planning,” and the abolition of inherited wealth.Footnote 9 During his lifetime Durkheim was closest politically to French liberals and socialists, particularly to his lifelong friend the socialist Jean Jaurès (see below). Durkheim rejected violent revolution, empires, militarism, bellicose foreign policy, and colonialism, favoring republicanism, democracy, the rule of law, expansive political and individual liberties, and an international order based on human rights.Footnote 10
A third interpretation sees Durkheim as being driven by a profound sense of societal destabilization and multifaceted crisis.Footnote 11 This is expressed most forcefully in his concept of “anomie,” which he first presented in the third section of The Division of Labor.Footnote 12 Here, Durkheim discusses “abnormal” or “pathological” forms of the division of labor, including commercial crisis and labor strife, which reflect, in his words, a “state of anomie.”Footnote 13 Durkheim's second book, Suicide (1897), “hinges on the chapter on anomic suicide.”Footnote 14 Here, anomie is defined as a “condition of rulelessness in which individuals lose their moorings.”Footnote 15 For Durkheim, anomie became chronic and institutionalized in contemporary societies.Footnote 16 Besnard argues that Durkheim's anomie concept therefore amounts to “a vigorous and almost vehement condemnation of the ideology of industrial society.”Footnote 17 As we will see, Durkheim characterizes both colonialism and noncolonial empires as anomic.
A fourth reading frames Durkheim, or the mature Durkheim of the Elementary Forms, as a theorist of “dogmata”; that is, of collective ideation, discourse, culture.Footnote 18 This approach draws particularly on Elementary Forms, where Durkheim traces the origins of modern scientific categories of understanding, including time, space, cause, force, and number, to religion, and indeed to the religions of the structurally simplest human societies. In the process of tracing modern classification schemes to “primitive” religions, Durkheim elaborates a theory of collective conscience as the source of social solidarity, of the reawakening of solidarity through collective ritual, and of religion as an originary moral and epistemological framework. Working from this “culturalist” turn, interwar Durkheimian sociology examined collective representations and classification schemes, social epistemologies, and practices such as sacrifice and ritual within contemporary “Western” societies.Footnote 19 Durkheim's text had a decisive influence on twentieth-century British social anthropology, from Alfred Radcliffe-Brown, Victor Turner, and Mary DouglasFootnote 20 to Claude Lévi-Strauss and French structuralism. Durkheimian sociology still resonates, directly or indirectly, within cultural sociology.Footnote 21
A final set of interpretations frames Durkheim as a sociologist of morality.Footnote 22 As Isambert notes, the “importance of morality for Durkheim can perhaps be measured by the extent of his writing on the subject”: the “first article he published concerns moral science in Germany,” and the last of his texts sought to create a new moral theory.Footnote 23 The original Introduction to Durkheim's Division of Labor framed the book as a sociology of morality.Footnote 24 Pickering observes that while Elementary Forms “stands as [Durkheim's] masterpiece, his ambition was to crown it with something greater, something closer to his heart, a sociological study of moral behaviour.”Footnote 25 Durkheim comes to analyze “moral facts” as compulsory rules of behavior that create social order and solidarity. In more differentiated societies, morality is also promoted by the state, the legal and educational systems, and professional and occupational groups.Footnote 26 Each society develops—or should develop—a system of morality specific to its social structure, which is itself historical and historically changing. As we will see below, Durkheim rejected the categorization of non-European mores as uncivilized, countering that European empires and colonies were themselves amoral.
Each of these interpretations is useful for making sense of the thematic cluster Durkheim/colonialism/empire. I focus in the pages that follow on Durkheim's comments on colonialism, empire, the state, and politics; his theory of crisis and anomie; his rejection of race as a category for social explanation and his increasing refusal to distinguish between societies in terms of their putative civilizational levels; and his sociology of morality—particularly his relativism about ethics, law, religion, and all of the other social practices that were referred to by European powers in justifying their conquests and their arrogations to themselves of sovereignty from African and Asian societies.
II: colonialism and empire in Durkheim's writings
Durkheim was not entirely silent about colonialism, contrary to most commentators, and when he did discuss it he was unerringly critical.Footnote 27 In The Division of Labor Durkheim suggests that “colonization” was one response to the disorganizing, anomic pressures of the modern division of labor, along with emigration and suicide.Footnote 28 It is revealing that Durkheim distinguishes between colonization and emigration; his translators have sometimes failed to do so.Footnote 29
One of Durkheim's most sustained discussions of colonialism appears in Moral Education. This text is based on “the most important of the lecture courses” that Durkheim “delivered fairly regularly between 1889 and 1912, both at Bordeaux and Paris.”Footnote 30 Durkheim was interested in developing educational practices that could inculcate morality and autonomous capacities for moral judgment among youths in societies like his own that seemed to lack universal moral codes. The passage in question appears in a chapter on corporal punishment, an educational practice that, according to Durkheim, culminated in an “orgy of violence … in the schools of the fourteenth, fifteenth, and sixteenth centuries.”Footnote 31 There was, however, “a force that is … in a position to check this kind of thinking: the prevailing climate of moral opinion.”Footnote 32 Durkheim then turns to the behavior of a hypothetical European in the colonies who encounters “moral forces” that are “depreciated in his eyes” because they are associated with “races he deems inferior.” This European does not recognize any moral force or “authority requiring his deference”; at the same time, he is unrestrained by the moral rules of his home society.Footnote 33 Nothing restrains the colonizer, Durkheim writes: “he overflows in violence, quite like the tyrant.”Footnote 34
This passage is fascinating in several respects. The first is that Durkheim introduces colonialism in a discussion of corporal punishment in schools. His text has already associated corporal punishment with earlier, despotic political systems.Footnote 35 Through a chain of associations, Durkheim links colonialism to continental empires, which are elsewhere described as despotic (see below), and as asynchronic or outdated. Second, by including a discussion of the relations between colonizer and colonized in lectures on the development of morality in children, Durkheim calls attention to the ways in which colonial rulers often impute childlike inferiority to the colonized. Third, Durkheim describes the colonial situation as completely lacking in moral regulation. Although he does not use the word “anomie” here, he had already introduced that term, defined as an absence of moral regulation, in The Division of Labor, which ended with a warning that morality was currently “in the throes of an appalling crisis” and that a form of justice corresponding to the new form of life had not yet appeared.Footnote 36 Situations were proliferating, Durkheim wrote, in which “the law of the strongest … decides any dispute, and a state of out and out warfare exists” between social groups.Footnote 37 As Frank Pearce notes, if we “follow Durkheim's reasoning, a likely feature of a colonial … society … will be an ever-present anomie.”Footnote 38
In the colonial setting, anomie escalates into something even more extreme than the scenarios in The Division of Labor and Suicide. It is important to pay attention to the rhetorical excess of Durkheim's texts, which often exceed the strictures and limits of his scientific categories.Footnote 39 Consider this passage in Moral Education which argues that the European's sense of superiority tends
as though independently, to assert itself brutally, without object or reason, for the mere pleasure of asserting itself. It produces a veritable intoxication, an excessive exaltation of self, a sort of megalomania, which goes to the worst extremes. This violence is a game with him, a spectacle in which he indulges himself, a way of demonstrating the superiority he sees in himself.Footnote 40
This description of a form of pleasure existing without object or reason recalls at first glance Durkheim's description of anomic suicide as a form of unlimited, insatiable desire that is “over-excited” and unregulated by the “check-rein” of a moral code.Footnote 41 Yet the description of the colonizer's acute pleasure in engaging in a spectacle without an object exceeds even the discussion of anomic suicide. Durkheim describes the colonizer as being gripped by a kind of Tropenkoller or colonial madness, an individual effervescence. For readers of Elementary Forms, this recasts the European as the primitive, reversing the imperial gaze. Such reversals had been commonplace in European anticolonial discourse, from Montaigne through to the Enlightenment, in the writings of Diderot, Voltaire, Le Vaillant, Chamisso, and others, but it had faded by Durkheim's era. Durkheim reintroduced this reversal of the colonial optic, which became a mainstay of the neo-Durkheimian surrealist discourse produced by the interwar Collège de sociologie. In this respect, Durkheim's vision is the very opposite of an “imperial gaze,” pace Connell.Footnote 42
Durkheim's second extended critique of colonialism appears in his 1915 pamphlet “Germany above All”.Footnote 43 As Bernard Lacroix notes, this text allowed Durkheim to return to his earlier preoccupation, during his Bordeaux years (1887–1902), with “the exegesis of great political texts,” including Montesquieu, Rousseau, and Saint-Simon.Footnote 44 “Germany above All” was written primarily for propagandistic purposes, but it hews to the general theoretical lines Durkheim had been working out since the 1890s. It can be read as an essay in political sociology and a critique of the ideas of Heinrich von Treitschke, who had been at the peak of his influence and popularity when Durkheim was in Berlin in 1886. I will return to Durkheim's specific analysis of political forms of empire below. The key point here is that Durkheim also discusses colonialism per se in this text. By including discussions of colonial phenomena in “Germany above All”—a text ostensibly focused on continental imperialism—Durkheim connected the two forms of morally deregulated geopolitics which Europeans usually considered separately.
Durkheim's working hypothesis is that Treitschke's ideas epitomize a dominant German ideology in which domestic despotism is combined with aggressive continental imperialism and overseas colonialism.Footnote 45 According to Durkheim, Treitschke insisted that the state's duty was to obtain “as large a place in the sun as possible, trampling its rivals under foot in the process.”Footnote 46 This phrase refers directly to the German colonial empire, which was identified at the time as a colonial latecomer seeking its own Platz an der Sonne (place in the sun)—in the tropics. Durkheim then criticizes Treitschke, and by extension Germany, for practicing a particularly brutal form of colonialism.Footnote 47 According to Durkheim, Treitschke believes that, “in dealing with people who are still in an inferior stage of civilisation, it is evident that policy must adapt the means to their mentality. It would be folly for an historian to judge European policy in Africa or the East by the principles applied in Europe. In those countries, he who knows not how to terrorise is lost.”Footnote 48 Durkheim clearly implies here that European policy in Africa or the East should be judged by the principles applied in Europe, or, as he writes elsewhere, by international norms (see below).
Durkheim then quotes Treitschke's remark about the English colonizers who, “over half a century ago, bound the rebel Sepoys to the mouths of the guns and blew their bodies into fragments that were scattered to the heavens.” Durkheim remarks that these “terrible measures of repression” were “tolerated” by “the manners of the time” but are condemned by the manners “of today,” and “would certainly be condemned by contemporary England.” Yet these same measures, he continues, “are pronounced natural by Treitschke.”Footnote 49 These comments make sense in terms of Durkheim's moral sociology, according to which “the normal type is the average type within a given stage of the development of the organism under consideration.”Footnote 50 Durkheim is arguing that these forms of colonialist savagery are out of alignment with contemporary manners and international morals. Once again, German morals are described as being objectively pathological in a comparative sociological sense.Footnote 51
Durkheim argued further that Germany's lust for “universal hegemony” was based on categories such as “race” and “legend,” and that these ideas were “sometimes bordering on delirium.”Footnote 52 He argues that German practice could not be understood at all without linking it to the myth (pan-Germanism) that it expresses and on which it depends. These connections to delirium and myth recall Durkheim's discussion of the anomic colonizer in Moral Education. It is significant that Durkheim here adds race thinking as a further marker of political pathology. As we will see below, Durkheim had taken a clear stand at this point against militarism, race, and racism, and against the idea of a hierarchy of stages of civilization. If the reader accepts Treitschke as the voice of a dominant strand of German ideology, then German morality can be diagnosed as lagging with respect to its own internal societal structures.Footnote 53
Finally, Durkheim reversed the “imperial gaze” once again here by describing the German military as applying colonialist practices to European warfare. Specifically, he describes Germany as entering Belgium in World War I as if it were annexing a res nullius. This phrase refers to the doctrine of terra nullius (“territory without a master”) that was used by colonial conquerors to justify the occupation of non-European lands. Durkheim is therefore suggesting that Germany is behaving like an aggressive colonial power inside Europe. He is describing the abandonment of any distinction between the inside and outside of the jus publicum Europaeum.Footnote 54 Durkheim is suggesting that colonialism and continental empire are kindred formations—a century before this became a topos among historians.Footnote 55 Both forms, for Durkheim, are despotic, undemocratic, unregulated, amoral, militaristic, and pathological.
Durkheim and his nephew, coauthor, and “alter ego” Marcel Mauss discussed colonialism in their book reviews in Année sociologique.Footnote 56 Postcolonial critics of Durkheim tend to ignore his reviews, but this is where Durkheim wrote some of his “most profound and seminal articles.”Footnote 57 His review of Célestin Bouglé's Essais sur les castes discusses the effects of the British administration on the Indian caste system.Footnote 58 His review of Louis Millot's La femme musulmane au Maghreb in 1913 does not ignore colonial administration but emphasizes “the attempts made by the French administration to ‘improve the lot of women'.”Footnote 59 Durkheim reviewed a number of books by Joseph Kohler on colonial law and ethnography.Footnote 60 He summarizes Kohler's studies as focusing on “the social organization of peoples subjected to German protectorate on different continents.”Footnote 61 In a review of Kohler's “Bantu Law in [German] East Africa,” Durkheim reminds his readers that the populations discussed by Kohler were all colonial subjects and that there was a German “administrator at the head of each district,” which meant that that “the autonomy of local groups had disappeared.”Footnote 62 According to Durkheim's sociology of law and morality, legal codes should correspond to the social structure and conscience collective of the population they regulate. This means that British policy in India, French interventions in the Maghreb, and German codifications of “Bantu law” were generating social pathology by disrupting the natural adjustment between social structures and moral and legal codes.
To better understand this aspect of Durkheim's views of colonialism and empire we need to consider his sociology of morality more closely.
Durkheim's sociology of morality, religion, and social pathology
In contrast to Kant, Durkheim argued that morals could not be derived deductively. And in contrast to the utilitarians, he insisted that individuals do not arrive at moral values via individual rational calculation.Footnote 63 Instead, Durkheim argued that individuals receive morality from society via primary socialization, formal education, and ongoing social interaction. “Moral facts,” for Durkheim, include rules of conduct; feelings of love, sympathy, loyalty, devotion, and remorse; and the pursuit of order, solidarity, and well-being.Footnote 64 Moral facts are compulsory rules of behavior that exist either at the level of entire societies or, in more complex societies, within smaller professional subgroupings.Footnote 65 Like social facts, moral facts “exist outside the individual consciousness and are endowed with a power of coercion by reason of which they control him.”Footnote 66 Each society or subgroup develops systems of moral rules and laws specific to their social structure. The healthy or normal form of morality in each society is therefore “the average type within a given stage of the development of the organism under consideration.”Footnote 67 Criticism of morality therefore involves comparing a society's moral ideals with its actual social practices. This empirical approach to grounding morality, Durkheim argues, is preferable to basing moral criticism on deductive, universal, or arbitrary definitions of right and wrong, good and evil.Footnote 68
Durkheim did not, however, restrict the efficacy of morality to submission to external coercion. He also emphasized the inculcation of a “habitus of moral being” and conscious reflection through deliberate “moral education.” This would allow morality to become a desirable end rather than simply a matter of duty: “The good is morality insofar as it seems to us a desirable thing … [to] which we aspire through a spontaneous impulse of the will.”Footnote 69 This meant that it was essential to develop a sociology of morality in order to guide the efforts by teachers and officials to inculcate moral values in the citizenry that are appropriate to the society in question.
This theory's relevance to the critique of colonialism stems, first, from its inherent relativism about morality, law, and religion. “Every social type has the morality necessary to it.” The Romans “should not have had any other” morality than the one they had.Footnote 70 Moreover, even simpler societies without a complex division of labor have highly elaborate moral systems. And just as “there are no religions that are false,”Footnote 71 there are no moral systems that are inferior or false. Durkheim's theory was in this respect completely at odds with European colonial practice. Claims of moral failure were used by great powers to bolster their right to conquer and colonize; arguments about moral “repugnancy” were used to outlaw native practices that offended European morals. Durkheim's theory rejects these legitimations of conquest and the imposition of foreign legal codes on colonized populations.
Durkheim's theory of the state, empire, and international orders
To understand Durkheim's theory of empire we also need to examine his theory of the state. Durkheim discussed the state in The Division of Labor and in his lectures on professional ethics and civic morals.Footnote 72 In The Division of Labor, he argues that the state “embodies the collectivity” and becomes society's “brain,” a “symbol of … [collective] consciousness” whose function is to protect beliefs, traditions, and collective practices.Footnote 73 In Professional Ethics and Civic Morals he argues that the modern state is not defined by religion, traditions, or a dynastic cult; instead, it is a “political society” containing a large number of secondary social groups.Footnote 74 It is based in a territory that is subject to “the same one authority, which is itself not subject to any other superior authority.”Footnote 75
Durkheim's overarching theme in Professional Ethics is once again the problem of identifying a system of moral rules that can generate solidarity within highly complex societies. As the division of labor increases, morality changes more rapidly and becomes increasingly fragmented. Yet Durkheim argues that there are substitutes for the “mechanical” solidarity that prevails in simpler societies. Moral codes develop within professional and occupational groups and are also promoted by the liberal state and its educational system—as the state's representations are common to all members of society (a theme echoed by Pierre Bourdieu in his theory of the state).Footnote 76
In more differentiated societies, over time, Durkheim argues, the individual becomes the sacred object par excellence.Footnote 77 The scope of individual life expands and the human being becomes the most “exalted object of moral respect.”Footnote 78 Contrary to libertarian and anarchist theories, the state is not antithetical to the flourishing of individuality but promotes it. Rather than creating tyranny, the (liberal) state alleviates various forms of tyranny or despotism, keeping in check secondary groups such as the family, church, and firm, such that they do not “draw the individual within their exclusive domination.”Footnote 79 As a result, “people began to have a far loftier idea of the human person and the smallest attempt on his freedom [becomes] more intolerable.”Footnote 80 The stronger the democratic state, the more the individual is respected. The most general political implication of the sacredness of the individual is “universal human rights for all.”Footnote 81 A form of universal morality does, therefore, emerge, but it is a product of historical changes in social complexity, the emergence of the modern state, and the state's democratization.
As in The Division of Labor, however, the “normal” or “healthy” social condition is not necessarily the empirical norm. This is evident in Durkheim's contrast between the forms of government in the French Third Republic state and the German Kaiserreich, discussed above. Durkheim discusses abnormal or pathological forms of polity in Professional Ethics in some detail, focusing on despotic states and “absolute governments,” which diminish individual rights and privilege war and imperialism. Indeed, some of Durkheim's earliest publications discussed the “bellicist” sociological writings of Ludwig Gumplowicz and Friedrich Ratzel. In 1885, Durkheim discussed Gumplowicz's argument that the “fundamental fact about all social life” is “the eternal struggle for dominance” (Der ewige Kampf um Herrschaft).Footnote 82 He summarized Ratzel as arguing that there was a “fundamental tendency of all societies to expand their geographical base”: the “hunger for space is, par excellence, the source of all political activity.”Footnote 83 Durkheim rejected this theory of the state from his earliest writings. But what he learned from this Central European political sociology was to blur the ideas of state and empire.
Durkheim's early rejection of the bellicist position was sharpened by his critique of French militarism, which crystallized in his response to the Dreyfus affair (1894–1906).Footnote 84 In that context, Durkheim participated in an “investigation of war and militarism” sponsored by the journal L'humanité nouvelle.Footnote 85 There, he deplored the fact that France was starting to worship its army as “something intangible and sacred.” This was a “truly superstitious cult,” a form of “fetishism,” one that removed the army from “rational criticism.” Here again, with this accusation of “fetishism,” we see Durkheim reversing the imperial gaze, just as Karl Marx had relocated “fetishism” to the heart of European capitalist subjectivity. In order for the army to lose its “transcendent” role, Durkheim reasoned, French youth would have to be educated in “worship of the law, respect for the law, love of freedom, concern for duties and responsibilities, whether of the individual or the community.”Footnote 86
According to Mauss, Durkheim “was profoundly opposed to all wars of class or nation.”Footnote 87 Durkheim's critique of bellicist theories and militarist politics was connected to his critique of states that were “solely preoccupied with expansion and self-aggrandizement to the detriment of similar entities.” Empires, Durkheim argued, had existed for centuries without ever obtaining “internal acquiescence from their subjects.”Footnote 88 Absolutist governments isolated themselves from society. Durkheim's ideal form of state, by contrast, was engaged in continuous, intensive communication with society, making it impossible to determine whether state or society was the original source of new practices and policies.
Durkheim and Mauss pushed their democratizing thought beyond the nation-state into the realm of international law and cosmopolitan culture. In their 1913 “Note on the Concept of Civilization,” they argued that there were “social phenomena that are not strictly attached” to a given state but that “extend over areas that go beyond a national territory.”Footnote 89 A system of states based on globalized morality and international law already existed, at least tendentially, Durkheim and Mauss suggested.Footnote 90 Only a subset of modern states was driven by the will to power and expansion. In contradistinction to these states there was an international order that was “no longer grounded on hatred, conflict, and war, but on reasoned construction, peaceful debate and cross-cultural exchange.”Footnote 91 Strands of this argument were already present in Durkheim's first publication on the liberal German sociologist Albert Schäffle. Here, Durkheim had supported “cosmopolitanism” against an exclusive “patriotism” and argued that there was “no doubt that international relations are destined to grow in importance and scope in the future.”Footnote 92 Just as the individual should desire to be encompassed by the social framework of moral rules, states should voluntarily subject themselves to international regulation. To withdraw from such control amounted to a form of “social pathology” within geopolitics.Footnote 93
Durkheim's views of “race” and “civilization”
There are two main reasons for discussing Durkheim's views of race, racism, and civilization in a treatment of his views of colonialism and empire. One is that racism and the category of race are closely connected to the history of European colonialism.Footnote 94 The other is that “decolonization,” for better or worse, has nowadays become a synonym for antiracism (see the conclusion below).
Durkheim's entire sociological project was “directed against racialism.”Footnote 95 He stated bluntly in 1895, in Rules of Sociological Method, that race could not explain social facts. The “most diverse forms of organization are found in societies of the same race,” he reasoned, while there are “striking similarities between societies of different races.”Footnote 96 For Durkheim, “humanity is unitary in its thinking, not, as Lucien Lévy-Bruhl believed, divided between prelogical primitives and logical, science-based moderns.”Footnote 97 Durkheim attacked his contemporary, the sociologist Georges Vacher de Lapouge, who defended scientific racism and had reintroduced the ideas of Joseph Arthur de Gobineau, the French “inventor” of racist theory.Footnote 98 To deny the use of race in explanations of human behavior was to reject one of the main ideological foundations of modern colonialism. Durkheim further developed these arguments in his battle against anti-Semitism during the Dreyfus affair. Durkheim wrote that French anti-Semitism “reveals the serious moral disturbance from which we suffer,” using the same language as in his descriptions of colonialism and empire.Footnote 99
In another sharp break with colonial ideology, Durkheim refused to categorize societies as “savage” or “barbaric.” Instead, he used the adjective “primitive,” which for him did not signify inferiority but referred to societies that were smaller and structurally simpler, with a less thorough division of labor.Footnote 100 Durkheim agreed with Franz Boas that “there are no essential differences between primitive thought and the thought of civilized man.”Footnote 101 In 1912 the pro-colonial economist Charles Gide asked Durkheim to provide a criterion for “distinguishing between civilized and uncivilized” societies. Durkheim responded that such a criterion did not exist. He refused Gide's invitation to attend a discussion of “the right to colonize.”Footnote 102 Here again, Durkheim's views directly contradicted a central tenet of French colonialism, the so-called mission civilisatrice.Footnote 103 In the last volume of Année sociologique before World War I, Durkheim and Mauss published the above-mentioned essay that defined civilizations as complex, solidary systems of social facts that are not located within a single state or “political organism” but are “nonetheless localizable in time and space” and that have a shared “moral milieu.” There were “types of civilizations,” they argued, but not hierarchies, scales, or rankings of civilizations.Footnote 104 The notion of “uncivilized” societies was thus defined out of existence.Footnote 105
These systematic, logical rejections of the ideas of “race” and “uncivilized” societies were widely shared among Durkheim's prewar pleiad.Footnote 106 Célestin Bouglé, one of Durkheim's closest collaborators, wrote in 1908 that “the guiding thesis of the philosophy of races—so much used and abused in the nineteenth century—seems to have been decisively abandoned.”Footnote 107 Henri Hubert, another member of Durkheim's inner circle, rejected “anthroposociology” and argued that “sociology can only study societies, not races.”Footnote 108
III: Durkheim's contemporaries and colonialism
In order to understand Durkheim's views of colonialism it is also useful to situate them within his wider and more proximate intellectual and political contexts, including the views of his predecessors and contemporaries in French academia.Footnote 109 This allows us to identify blind spots in his thinking that might have been realistically avoided, since they were already being openly discussed by others at the time. It also permits us to identify moments in which Durkheim's thinking pushed up against historical constraints and pointed in new directions.Footnote 110
According to Steven Seidman, advocates of colonialism in the early Third Republic were extremely vocal “and often better organized” than their opponents. Seidman notes that “a loose network of scientists, geographers, explorers, public officials, and colonialists called the parti colonial” was one of the leading organizations advocating “imperial state policies” in the early Third Republic.Footnote 111 Indeed, most French social scientists supported colonialism before the 1930s.Footnote 112 French economists had shifted from widespread opposition to colonialism to almost universal support by the 1870s. French psychologists and psychiatrists became deeply engaged in the overseas colonies. Anthropologists were embedded in the colonial empire both for their fieldwork and as advisers to colonial governments.Footnote 113
According to Jonathan Derrick, there were three main strands of French anticolonialism between 1900 and 1940: (1) moral condemnation of oppression or ill-treatment of the colonized, (2) condemnation of the role of militarism and capitalism in driving colonialism and in the effects thereof on colonies and metropoles, and (3) utilitarian critiques of colonialism emphasizing its deleterious effects on metropolitan economies.Footnote 114 Several left-wing members of the socialist party—Jean Jaurès, Paul Louis, Jules Guesde, and Paul Lafargue—represented the main organized political opposition to colonialism within French politics. A larger group of socialists advocated “colonial socialism,” which led to the creation of socialist parties in Tunisia, Guadeloupe, Algeria, and Morocco.Footnote 115
How did Durkheim fit into this political landscape? The sociologists with the strongest influence on Durkheim, Saint-Simon and Auguste Comte, had commented extensively on colonial matters. Saint-Simon and his disciples were actively involved in the colonization of Algeria between 1830 and 1870, staffing the Bureaux arabes and directing the first grandes enquêtes of Arab society.Footnote 116 Comte was more critical, writing that “Catholicism, in its decay, not only sanctioned but even instigated the primitive extermination of entire races” while creating a system of colonial slavery, which was “a political monstrosity.” The European nations in which investors became “personally interested” in overseas colonies saw an increase in “retrograde thought and social immobility.”Footnote 117 Comte also argued that colonialism strengthened the “warrior spirit,” prolonging “the military and theological regime” and delaying “the time of the final reorganization.”Footnote 118 Durkheim drew more heavily on Saint-Simon in his doctoral thesis on socialism, but his views of colonialism were closer to Comte's.Footnote 119
The main contenders for leadership of French sociology alongside Durkheim were Frédéric Le Play, René Worms, and Gabriel Tarde. Le Play and Worms were favorable toward French colonialism. Durkheim was dismissive of both sociologists and of their views of colonialism. Durkheim had more respect for Tarde, who compared the French “colonial protectorates” to cases of “collective cannibalism,” “national anthropophagy,” and “vivisection.”Footnote 120 Durkheim also was invited to a discussion at the London School of Economics in 1904 with some of the anti-imperialist British sociologists, including John A. Hobson, author of Imperialism (1902), and Leonard Hobhouse.Footnote 121
Durkheim and his colleagues before World War I were not directly involved in colonialism or in advising colonial ministers or rulers, even if Mauss became more involved with colonial officials after 1925 in the Institute of Ethnology, whose teachers still “remained resolutely detached from the actual work of colonizing” and did not generally seek to place their students in colonial service.Footnote 122 Durkheim's friend Jaurès “centered his criticisms” of imperialism “on faulty administration rather than on the idea of colonialism” until the end of the 1880s, but in the 1890s he began to argue that colonialism “was the cause of Algeria's misery, and the answer to it was equality for the Arabs.”Footnote 123 Jaurès became “the great conscience of France during the conquest of Morocco” from 1907 to 1912.Footnote 124 Mauss belonged to the Socialist Party before World War I and wrote several articles in 1911 denouncing “the criminal or illegal acts of [French] diplomats and the military” in Morocco.Footnote 125
In sum, Durkheim was personally close to anticolonialists, and his writings went beyond “moral condemnation of oppression or ill-treatment of the colonized” insofar as they called into question the justification of colonialism tout court.
IV: Durkheimian sociology and colonialism between 1918 and the 1960s
Durkheim profoundly shaped the first French social-scientific studies of colonies qua colonies that appeared between the wars and in greater numbers after World War II. Mauss's students who conducted fieldwork in colonial settings between the wars understood themselves as standing on Durkheim's shoulders and pushing his ideas in new directions:
Charles Le Coeur was a student of Mauss who carried out fieldwork in the Moroccan city of Azemmour and among the Téda in northern Chad.Footnote 126 Le Coeur quoted Durkheim, rejecting “spontaneous sociology” in favor of “reflexive sociology.”Footnote 127 He published his doctoral thesis in the Année sociologique book series. Ethnographers associated with the mission scientifique in Morocco “self-consciously presented themselves as sociologists and asserted their intellectual connections to the Durkheim school.”Footnote 128
The North Africanist Jacques Berque left for his colonial administrative service in 1934 with the eleventh volume of the Année sociologique under his arm and read Durkheim during his years in Morocco.Footnote 129 Berque went on to align himself with the social history of the Annales school of Marc Bloch and Lucien Febvre, which he described as “perhaps the most authentic daughter of Durkheim.”Footnote 130
Joseph Chelhod, a sociologist born in French-controlled Aleppo in 1919, “received a French formation in the schools of Mandate Syria” and completed “his education in sociology at the Sorbonne.”Footnote 131 Chelhod's primary doctoral thesis in 1955 was Le sacrifice chez les Arabes, picking up on the core topos of ritual sacrifice in Durkheim's Elementary Forms. The title of Chelhod's secondary thesis posed the ur-Durkheimian question: “Are social facts things?”Footnote 132
Paul Henry Chombart de Lauwe began his career as an Africanist before 1940 and became an urban sociologist afterwards, leading the Groupe d'ethnologie sociale. Chombart de Lauwe traced the French study of urban geography to Durkheim's framework of “social morphology” and to its further development by the interwar Durkheimian Maurice Halbwachs.Footnote 133
Maurice Leenhardt, finally, was the first French sociologist to study the symbolic aspects of anticolonial struggle through firsthand ethnographic research. In his 1902 bachelor's thesis, Leenhardt interpreted the messianic “Ethiopian” church in Southern Africa as enacting resistance through the selective appropriation of colonial culture.Footnote 134 Leenhardt then began a long career focused on the French colony of New Caledonia. He was a member of Mauss's core circle, used Durkheimian concepts, and participated in the Année sociologique. After World War II, Leenhardt was also a founding member of the CNRS-sponsored Centre d’études sociologiques, where he carried out research on “the social structure of colonies.”Footnote 135 Michel Leiris, the famous anticolonial anthropologist, was Leenhardt's first student at the École pratique des hautes études. Most important in the present context was Leenhardt's criticism of colonialism. In the conclusion to the 1953 edition of his Gens de la Grande Terre, Leenhardt situated New Caledonian indigenous life within a critical narrative of the French invasion that entailed, in his account, expropriation, cultural decimation, and racism. Leenhardt suggested that the colony might become a kind of syncretic society, with acculturation moving in both directions in a jeu de transferts (a play of cultural transfers).Footnote 136
In other words, one development that stemmed from Durkheim was the analysis of colonialism's effects on native cultures. In 1934, Michel Leiris published L'Afrique fantôme, a proto-postcolonial critique of colonial social science. Leiris suggested that the Dakar-to-Djibouti ethnographic expedition led by anthropologist Marcel Griaule between 1931 and 1933 bracketed the effects of colonialism and avoided Africans whose culture had been clearly stamped by European influence. Ethnologists at the time showed a revulsion for “mixed” or métis cultures and a preference for “pure natives.”Footnote 137 This amplified an earlier theme among pre-1914 Durkheimians. Bouglé argued in 1908 and 1913 against race science, insofar as “the mixing of human races, operating over immense areas, is unlimited.”Footnote 138 Leiris focused on the dynamics of cultural mixing. As Fuyuki Kurosawa writes, together with Georges Bataille and other members of the Collège de sociologie, Leiris radicalized Durkheimian theory, finding in it “the raw materials out of which to forge … sweeping dismissals of a modern West.”Footnote 139
Colonial cultural mixité was also a central theme for sociologist Roger Bastide. Although Bastide had initially distanced himself from Durkheim, he embraced the Durkheimian legacy after 1945. Sociologists sympathetic to Durkheimian ideas contributed to the “third series” of Année sociologique, which recommenced publishing in 1949.Footnote 140 The emphasis on ethnological topics was retained from the journal's earlier series.Footnote 141 Colonialism was now explicitly covered in a section called “Contacts de civilizations; colonialisme” (Civilizational Contact and Colonialism). The contributions to Année sociologique no longer ignored the effects of colonialism on non-European cultures. According to the editors of the section on “Contacts de civilizations; colonialisme,” the word “sociology” now signaled an emphasis on historicity, crisis, and cultural “interpenetration.”Footnote 142
The Durkheimian legacy also resurfaced within French sociological research in some of the postcolonies. Durkheimian sociologist Jean Duvignaud argued in 1963 that the former French colonies were caught in a “movement of destructuration and structuration.”Footnote 143 Duvignaud conducted an ethnography of the Tunisian oasis village of Chebika, arguing that during the first years of his investigation the villagers were living in a “state of abandonment” that was so grave that it affected “not only their everyday practices and religious rites but also their conscience.” Colonialism, he wrote, had destroyed the forces of collective conscience and social solidarity.Footnote 144
Conclusion: for an alternative approach to “decolonizing sociology” and revising its “canon”
As calls increase for a “decolonization” of the social sciences and for a revision of theoretical canons, it becomes ever more urgent to clarify the stakes in this discussion and to carefully examine the works of “canonical” theorists. At one extreme in this debate is the position that Olúfẹ́mi Táíwò calls decolonisation2, defined as forswearing “any and every cultural, political, intellectual, social and linguistic artefact, idea, process, institution and practice that retains even the slightest whiff of the colonial past.”Footnote 145 At the opposite pole, perhaps surprisingly, is postcolonial theory, or at least certain foundational contributors to postcolonial theory, including Edward Said and Gayatri Spivak. Said argued in Freud and the Non-European that “[t]exts that are inertly of their time stay there: those which brush up unstintingly against historical constraints are the ones we keep with us, generation after generation.”Footnote 146 Spivak characterized her earlier interpretation of Charlotte Brontë's Jane Eyre as having been based on an overly “simple invocation of race and gender, with no bridle of auto-critique.” She recently argued that it is “useless” to “simply label great thinkers” like Immanuel Kant “racists” and to “learn nothing from them.”Footnote 147
Also located at the opposite pole from precipitous calls to decolonize the canon is Pierre Bourdieu, who was in many ways the most important inheritor of Durkheim's sociology.Footnote 148 Bourdieu was also the first sociologist to call explicitly for a “decolonization of sociology,” in a 1975 in a lecture entitled “For a Sociology of Sociologists: Colonial Sociology and the Decolonization of Sociology.”Footnote 149 Bourdieu's focus in this essay is the social scientists of the École d'Alger, the colonial-era specialists in Arab, Kabyle, and Islamic culture at the University of Algiers. Bourdieu argued for a careful reconstruction of the specific properties of the “relatively autonomous scientific field” in which “‘colonial’ ‘science’ was carried out” and of the relations between this knowledge field and “the colonial power”—the academic and scientific institutions within the colony—and the relations with “the central intellectual power, that's to say, the metropolitan science of the day.” The researcher would need to reconstruct the pertinent social properties of the field's participants and the polarizations and forms of habitus characterizing the scientific space.Footnote 150 Bourdieu also suggests, like Said, that a key question would be intellectual agency within structural constraints, and he pointed to several ways in which Europeans could partially transcend the limits of the colonial context.Footnote 151
Durkheim is a canonical sociological thinker who is often lambasted for being conservative, Eurocentric, and ignorant of—or even favorable to—colonialism. I have argued that he was nothing of the sort. And I have suggested that Durkheim's thought may be useful for ongoing research on colonialism and empire.Footnote 152 His theory points toward the possibility of a grounded critique of colonialism, while his theory of anomie allows us to thematize the morally unregulated character of modern colonies and their intrinsic instability. It guides us in criticizing colonialism for denying the conquered society's political autonomy and for treating its inhabitants as inherently inferior beings.Footnote 153 Durkheim's theory of anomic depravity intersects with discussions of colonies as sites of extreme violence and states of exception. Durkheim alerts us to seeing colonies as inherently unstable and crisis-ridden. Durkheim's moral theory suggests a method for grounding the critique of colonialism that avoids deductive, utilitarian, essentialist, or foundationalist conceptions of normativity (see above).Footnote 154
The French sociologists who engaged with colonialism after Durkheim, from Balandier and Berque to Bourdieu and beyond, engaged with the “Other of Europe” in ways that recognized difference without inscribing the other into a civilizational hierarchy. They analyzed the multiple ways in which colonialism was remixing cultures. They continued Durkheim's gesture of turning the imperial gaze against Europe itself. Although French sociology largely abandoned the project of theorizing empire and colonialism after the 1960s, the present-day sociology of colonies and empires might benefit from a renewed curiosity about Durkheimian ideas.
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank Steven Lukes, Mark Mizruchi, Loïc Wacquant, Andreas Wimmer, Geneviève Zubrzycki, and the participants in the UCLA Sociology Colloquium, especially Rogers Brubaker, Jason Ferguson, Kevan Harris, Ching Kwan Lee, Omar Lizardo, and Aliza Luft, for comments on earlier versions of this paper. I am also grateful to the students in the first semester of Graduate Sociological Theory on “classical” theory in Fall 2023 for inspiring me to explore Durkheim's relationship to colonialism in more detail.