Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T14:17:11.760Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Vaccines in the coronavirus disease 2019 (COVID-19) era: Game theory applications

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 April 2021

Marios Papadakis*
Affiliation:
University Witten-Herdecke, Germany
Nikolaos Spernovasilis
Affiliation:
School of Medicine, University of Crete, Heraklion, Greece
*
Author for correspondence: Marios Papadakis, E-mail: marios_papadakis@yahoo.gr
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Letter to the Editor
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Society for Healthcare Epidemiology of America

To the Editor—Vaccines are among the greatest inventions of science, preventing millions of deaths worldwide annually. Currently, the lack of a coronavirus disease 2019 (COVID-19) vaccine has led to a pandemic that has brought the whole world to a near standstill. Although international collaborations to guarantee equitable access have been established, as COVID-19 vaccines are approved, national egotism is expected. Reference Greer1 Game theory is the science of strategy and interactive decision making, where the outcome depends not only on one’s actions but also on the actions of others. Reference McFadden, Tsai, Kadry and Souba2 Herein, we present applications of game theory in vaccine allocation.

The well-known Prisoner’s Dilemma is the most common game theory paradigm. It proves that 2 individuals who act in their own self-interest do not produce the optimal outcome. As countries try to secure vaccine availability for their citizens, they may fail to slow the spread of the virus elsewhere, which harms human society overall. For example, if Germany concentrates on making the vaccine available only for all German citizens while the outbreak grows in Belgium, Switzerland, and other neighboring countries, a shortage of ICU beds could result in these countries. However, such a shortage led to critical care patients being transferred to Germany, where the ICU capacity was sufficient.

The Tragedy of the Commons refers to bad outcomes for the whole system, when individual self-interests conflict with the common good. It is based on a 200-year-old concept that originally described a group of shepherds who let their sheep graze on a shared field, resulting in the grass getting eaten down to the roots and, thus, all sheep dying. As more and more “wealthy” countries order large numbers of vaccines for their citizens, concerns arise that, if the manufacturing capacity limit is reached, low-income countries may have to wait 2–3 years to get vaccines. The COVAX initiative aims to prevent such vaccine hoarding by guaranteeing vaccines to 20% of each country’s most vulnerable population. Such an approach gives shepherds (in this case the pharmaindustry) time to plant new grass (in this case more vaccines) for the sheep (in this case the population). Moreover, approval of >1 effective vaccine means more grass for a given number of individuals.

The Free Rider Dilemma refers to an individual or a group who uses a resource or receives a benefit without having any contribution to it. In the COVID-19 era, free riders can be considered all persons that benefit from herd immunity without exposing themselves to the vaccine. At the country level, free riders can be considered countries that have not participated in the negotiations for the vaccine distribution (eg, countries that will receive vaccines just because they are EU members) or developing countries that do not participate in the COVAX facility but take advantage of its decisions.

In the Volunteer’s Dilemma, he who goes first loses, but if no one tries all lose. For example, University of Oxford/AstraZeneca (Oxford/AZ) partnership was the first to conclude a vaccine agreement with the European Commission. Reference Ng, Liu and Mahalingam3 Oxford/AZ promised vaccine at uniform price worldwide ($2.90) and was granted protection from future product liability claims. The Pfizer/BioNTech vaccine was approved for use in the United Kingdom, and although it is priced at $20.00, the UK government also granted the manufacturer protection from being sued. Reference Hafner, Yerushalmi, Fays, Dufresne and Van Stolk4 This example may also indicate reciprocity—a situation in which, after adopting a cooperative strategy on the first move, the player proceeds by copying the moves of the other players.

Finally, the Stag Hunt Dilemma describes a conflict between safety and cooperation. According to the scenario, a group of hunters go hunting. If all hunters work together and kill the stag, it will provide shared meat for all. If they work at their immediate self-interest, they may succeed killing a hare (which is worth less than a stag), providing adequate meat only for the individual. The problem is that there is no guarantee for a stag, so the hunter’s dilemma when he sees a hare is whether to kill it or to sacrifice his immediate self-interest for the risk of not eating anything. In the COVID-19 era, the stag is a highly effective vaccine, which, at the beginning, could not be guaranteed. Oxford/AZ reported an overall vaccine efficacy of 70%. To increase this efficacy, Oxford/AZ decided to work with the makers of Russia’s Sputnik-V vaccine to test a combined shot, based on 1 of 2 vectors of Sputnik-V. This could produce greater and longer-lasting immunity.

In conclusion, human cooperation is the only driving force that can minimize such dilemmas and provide a fair, uniform, and equitable COVID-19 vaccine allocation.

Acknowledgments

Financial support

No financial support was provided relevant to this article.

Conflicts of interest

All authors report no conflicts of interest relevant to this article.

References

Greer, SL. National, European, and global solidarity: COVID-19. Eurohealth 2020;26:104108.Google Scholar
McFadden, DW, Tsai, M, Kadry, B, Souba, WW. Game theory: applications for surgeons and the operating room environment. Surgery 2012;152:915922.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ng, WH, Liu, X, Mahalingam, S. Development of vaccines for SARS-CoV-2. F1000Res 2020. doi: 10.12688/f1000research.25998.1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hafner, M, Yerushalmi, E, Fays, C, Dufresne, E, Van Stolk, C. COVID-19 and the Cost of Vaccine Nationalism. Santa Monica, CA: RAND Corporation; 2020.CrossRefGoogle Scholar