Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T17:37:51.552Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

CONGRUENCE OF ULTRAFILTERS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 February 2021

BORIS ŠOBOT*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS AND INFORMATICS UNIVERSITY OF NOVI SAD, TRG DOSITEJA OBRADOVIĆA 4 21000 NOVI SAD, SERBIAE-mail:sobot@dmi.uns.ac.rs
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We continue the research of the relation $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}$ on the set $\beta \mathbb {N}$ of ultrafilters on $\mathbb {N}$ , defined as an extension of the divisibility relation. It is a quasiorder, so we see it as an order on the set of $=_{\sim }$ -equivalence classes, where $\mathcal {F}=_{\sim }\mathcal {G}$ means that $\mathcal {F}$ and $\mathcal {G}$ are mutually $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ -divisible. Here we introduce a new tool: a relation of congruence modulo an ultrafilter. We first recall the congruence of ultrafilters modulo an integer and show that $=_{\sim }$ -equivalent ultrafilters do not necessarily have the same residue modulo $m\in \mathbb {N}$ . Then we generalize this relation to congruence modulo an ultrafilter in a natural way. After that, using iterated nonstandard extensions, we introduce a stronger relation, which has nicer properties with respect to addition and multiplication of ultrafilters. Finally, we introduce a strengthening of $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}$ and show that it also behaves well with respect to the congruence relation.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

1 Introduction

Let $\mathbb {N}$ be the set of natural numbers. The relation $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ , an extension of the divisibility relation $\mid $ on $\mathbb {N}$ to the set $\beta \mathbb {N}$ of ultrafilters on $\mathbb {N}$ , was introduced in [Reference Šobot11] and further investigated in [12–15]. The main idea was to understand the impact of various properties of $\mid $ to $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}$ and possibly, learning about the $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ -hierarchy, to acquire better understanding of $\mid $ . In this paper we will make another step in that direction, considering possible extensions of the congruence relation to $\beta \mathbb {N}$ and their relation to $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ , as well as to the operations of addition and multiplication on $\beta \mathbb {N}$ .

When working with the set of ultrafilters $\beta S$ on a set S it is common to identify each element $s\in S$ with the principal ultrafilter $\{A\subseteq S:s\in A\}$ . Having that in mind, any binary operation $\star $ on S can be extended to $\beta S$ as follows: for $A\subseteq S$ ,

(1) $$ \begin{align} A\in\mathcal{F}\star\mathcal{G}\Leftrightarrow\{s\in S:s^{-1}A\in\mathcal{G}\}\in\mathcal{F}, \end{align} $$

where $s^{-1}A=\{t\in S:s\star t\in A\}$ . If $(S,\star )$ is a semigroup equiped with the discrete topology, $(\beta S,\star )$ becomes a compact Hausdorff right-topological semigroup. The base sets for the topology are (clopen) sets $\overline {A}=\{\mathcal {F}\in \beta S:A\in \mathcal {F}\}$ . Many aspects of structures obtained in this way were examined in [Reference Hindman and Strauss6].

Every function $f:\mathbb {N}\rightarrow \mathbb {N}$ can be extended uniquely to a continuous $\widetilde {f}:\beta \mathbb {N}\rightarrow \beta \mathbb {N}$ : the ultrafilter $\widetilde {f}(\mathcal {F})$ is generated by $\{f[A]:A\in \mathcal {F}\}$ . This was used in [Reference Šobot11] to define analogously an extension of a binary relation $\rho $ on $\mathbb {N}$ to a relation $\widetilde {\rho }$ on $\beta \mathbb {N}$ : $\mathcal {F}\widetilde {\rho }\mathcal {G}$ if and only if for every $A\in \mathcal {F}$ the set $\rho [A]:=\{n\in \mathbb {N}:(\exists a\in A)a\rho n\}$ is in $\mathcal {G}$ . This coincides with the so-called canonical way of extending relations from $\mathbb {N}$ to $\beta \mathbb {N}$ described in [Reference Goranko5]. It turned out that the extension $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}$ of the divisibility relation $\mid $ has a simple equivalent definition, more convenient for practical use:

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{F}\hspace{1mm}\widetilde{\mid}\hspace{1mm}\mathcal{G}\Leftrightarrow\mathcal{F}\cap\mathcal{U}\subseteq\mathcal{G},\end{align*} $$

where $\mathcal {U}=\{A\in P(\mathbb {N})\setminus \{\emptyset \}:A\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow =A\}$ is the family of sets upward closed for $\mid $ . $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ is a quasiorder, so we think of it as an order on the set of $=_{\sim }$ -equivalence classes, where $\mathcal {F}=_{\sim }\mathcal {G}$ if and only if $\mathcal {F}\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}\mathcal {G}$ and $\mathcal {G}\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}\mathcal {F}$ . We say that $C\subseteq \mathbb {N}$ is convex if for all $x,y\in C$ and all z such that $x\mid z$ and $z\mid y$ holds $z\in C$ . All ultrafilters from the same $=_{\sim }$ -equivalence class $\mathcal {C}$ have the same convex sets. Clearly, each equivalence class $\mathcal {C}$ is determined by $\mathcal {F}\cap \mathcal {U}$ (for any $\mathcal {F}\in \mathcal {C}$ ), or by the family of convex sets belonging to any $\mathcal {F}\in \mathcal {C}$ .

An ultrafilter $\mathcal {F}$ is divisible by some $n\in \mathbb {N}$ if and only if $n\mathbb {N}:=\{nk:k\in \mathbb {N}\}\in \mathcal {F}$ . If $\mathcal {F}\in \mathbb {N}$ as well, $n\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}\mathcal {F}$ holds if and only if $n\mid \mathcal {F}$ . Hence, we can write just $n\mid \mathcal {F}$ in case $n\in \mathbb {N}$ .

Especially useful are prime ultrafilters $\mathcal {P}$ : those $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ -divisible only by 1 and themselves. This is equivalent to $P\in \mathcal {P}$ , where P is the set of prime numbers.

The $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ -hierarchy can be naturally divided into two parts. The “lower” part, L, can be divided into levels: $L=\bigcup _{l<\omega }\overline {L_{l}}$ , where

$$ \begin{align*}L_{l}=\{p_{1}p_{2}\dots p_{l}:p_{1},p_{2},\dots,p_{l}\mbox{ are prime}\}\end{align*} $$

is the set of natural numbers having exactly l (not necessarily distinct) prime factors. Some nice properties of L were established in [Reference Šobot15]; for example every ultrafilter in $\overline {L_{l}}$ has exactly l prime ingredients (but being divisible by the n-th power of a prime $\mathcal {P}$ is not the same as being divisible by $\mathcal {P}\, n$ times). The “upper” part, however, is much more complicated. It contains the maximal $=_{\sim }$ -class, $MAX$ , consisting of ultrafilters divisible by all $n\in \mathbb {N}$ , and consequently by all $\mathcal {F}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ ([Reference Šobot12], Lemma 4.6). Another interesting class is $NMAX$ , maximal among $\mathbb {N}$ -free ultrafiters (those that are not divisible by any $n\in \mathbb {N}$ ), see [Reference Šobot14], Theorem 5.4. A set belonging to an $\mathbb {N}$ -free ultrafilter is called an $\mathbb {N}$ -free set.

The paper is organized as follows. In §2 several well-known results of elementary number theory are employed to obtain results about the congruence of ultrafilters modulo an integer in connection with the divisibility relation $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ . In §3 we recapitulate basic definitions about $\omega $ -hyperextensions, obtained by iterating nonstandard extensions of the set $\mathbb {Z}$ . Tensor pairs play an important role here. They were first considered by Puritz in [Reference Puritz10]; Di Nasso proved several useful characterizations and coined the term (see [Reference Di Nasso3]). Most of the results in §3 are taken from Luperi Baglini’s thesis [Reference Luperi Baglini7], where the concept of a tensor pair is implemented in the surrounding of $\omega $ -hyperextensions. In §4 we define congruence modulo an ultrafilter and find several conditions equivalent to this definition. The next section deals with a stronger relation, and we prove some results connecting it to $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}$ and operations of addition and multiplication of ultrafilters. In §6 we define another version of divisibility, obtained in a natural way from the strong congruence relation, and get some basic results about it. The last section contains several remarks and open questions.

Notation. $\mathbb {N}$ is the set of natural numbers (without zero), $\omega =\mathbb {N}\cup \{0\}$ , P is the set of prime numbers and $\mathbb {Z}$ the set of integers. The calligraphic letters $\mathcal {F},\mathcal {G},\mathcal {H},\dots $ are mostly reserved for ultrafilters, and small letters $x,y,z,\dots $ for integers (both standard and nonstandard). For $A\subseteq \mathbb {N}$ , $A\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow =\{n\in \mathbb {N}:(\exists a\in A)a\mid n\}$ and $A\hspace {-0.1cm}\downarrow =\{n\in \mathbb {N}:(\exists a\in A)n\mid a\}$ . If $m,r\in \mathbb {N}$ , then $\mathbb {Z}_{m}=\{0,1,\dots ,m-1\}$ and $mA+r=\{mn+r:n\in A\}$ . Finally, $\mathcal {U}=\{A\in P(\mathbb {N})\setminus \{\emptyset \}:A\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow =A\}$ and $\mathcal {V}=\{A\in P(\mathbb {N})\setminus \{\mathbb {N}\}:A\hspace {-0.1cm}\downarrow =A\}$ .

Because we use ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {N}}$ for a nonstandard extension of $\mathbb {N}$ , to avoid confusion we will not denote $\beta \mathbb {N}\setminus \mathbb {N}$ with $\mathbb {N}^{*}$ . Likewise, we will avoid writing $A^{2}$ for $A\times A$ , since this notation had another meaning in papers preceding this one.

2 Congruence modulo integer

Let $m\in \mathbb {N}$ and let $\mathbb {Z}_{m}$ be given the discrete topology. The homomorphism $h_{m}:\mathbb {N}\rightarrow \mathbb {Z}_{m}$ is defined as follows: $h_{m}(n)$ is the residue of n modulo m. $h_{m}$ extends uniquely to a continuous function $\widetilde {h_{m}}:\beta \mathbb {N}\rightarrow \mathbb {Z}_{m}$ . The next results follows directly from [Reference Hindman and Strauss6], Corollary 4.22.

Proposition 2.1. $\widetilde {h_{m}}$ is a homomorphism, both for addition and multiplication of ultrafilters.

As described in §1, the relation $\equiv _{m}$ of congruence modulo m can be extended to a relation $\widetilde {\equiv _{m}}$ on $\beta \mathbb {N}$ : $\mathcal {F}\widetilde {\equiv _{m}}\mathcal {G}$ if and only if, for every $A\in \mathcal {F}$ , $\{n\in \mathbb {N}:(\exists a\in A)n\equiv _{m}a\}\in \mathcal {G}$ . Recall that the kernel of a function $h:X\rightarrow Y$ is the relation $\text {ker}h=\{(x,y)\in X\times X:h(x)=h(y)\}$ .

Proposition 2.2 ([Reference Šobot11], Theorem 2.13)

If $h:\mathbb {N}\rightarrow \mathbb {N}$ and $\rho =\ker h$ , then $\widetilde {\rho }=\ker \widetilde {h}$ .

Thus, for $m\in \mathbb {N}$ the extension of $\equiv _{m}$ to $\beta \mathbb {N}$ coincides with the definition found in [Reference Hindman and Strauss6]: $\mathcal {F}\widetilde {\equiv _{m}}\mathcal {G}$ if and only if $\widetilde {h_{m}}(\mathcal {F})=\widetilde {h_{m}}(\mathcal {G})$ . In particular, $r<m$ is the residue of $\mathcal {F}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ modulo m ( $\mathcal {F}\widetilde {\equiv _{m}}r$ ) if and only if $m\mathbb {N}+r\in \mathcal {F}$ . For practical reasons, we will denote the extension of $\equiv _{m}$ to $\beta \mathbb {N}$ also by $\equiv _{m}$ from now on.

The congruence of ultrafilters modulo integer is not new, but it was mostly marginally mentioned; for example the following interesting result has only the status of a comment in [Reference Hindman and Strauss6].

Proposition 2.3 ([Reference Hindman and Strauss6], Comment 11.20)

For every $\mathcal {F}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ and every $U\in \mathcal {F}$ there is a neighborhood $\overline{A}$ of $\mathcal {F}$ such that $A\subseteq U$ and for all $\mathcal {G}\in {\overline{A}}\setminus A$ and all $m\in \mathbb {N}$ holds $\mathcal {G}\equiv _{m}\mathcal {F}$ .

We begin with a simple result about the solvability of a system of congruences in $\beta \mathbb {N}$ . A system such that its every finite subsystem has a solution in $\beta \mathbb {N}$ will be called feasible.

Lemma 2.4.

  1. (a) Let $x\equiv _{m_{i}}a_{i}$ (for $i=0,1,\dots ,k$ , $a_{i}\in \mathbb {Z}$ and $m_{i}\in \mathbb {N}$ ) be a finite system of congruences. It has a solution in $\beta \mathbb {N}\setminus \mathbb {N}$ if and only if it has a solution in $\mathbb {N}$ .

  2. (b) The system $x\equiv _{m_{i}}a_{i}$ (for $i\in \omega $ , $a_{i}\in \mathbb {Z}$ and $m_{i}\in \mathbb {N}$ ) of congruences has a solution in $\beta \mathbb {N}$ if and only if it is feasible.

Proof

  1. (a) Let $\mathcal {F}\in \beta \mathbb {N}\setminus \mathbb {N}$ be a solution of the given system. Then $A_{i}:=\{x\in \mathbb {N}:x\equiv _{m_{i}}a_{i}\}\in \mathcal {F}$ for each $i=0,1,\dots ,k$ . Hence $A:=\bigcap _{i=0}^{k}A_{i}\in \mathcal {F}$ , and any $x\in A$ is a solution of the given system.

    On the other hand, if $s\in \mathbb {N}$ is a solution and $u=lcm(m_{0},m_{1},\dots ,m_{k})$ (the least common multiplier of $m_{0},m_{1},\dots ,m_{k}$ ), then all the elements of the set $B=\{x\in \mathbb {N}:x\equiv _{u}s\}$ are also solutions. Thus every $\mathcal {F}\in \overline {B}\setminus B$ is a solution of the system in $\beta \mathbb {N}\setminus \mathbb {N}$ .

  2. (b) One direction is trivial, so assume the given system to be feasible. Let $A_{i}=\{x\in \mathbb {N}:x\equiv _{m_{i}}a_{i}\}$ . By the assumption, every finite subsystem of the given system has a solution, so the family $\{\overline {A_{i}}:i<\omega \}$ has the finite intersection property. Since all the sets $\overline {A_{i}}$ are closed, it follows that $A=\bigcap _{i<\omega }\overline {A_{i}}$ is nonempty, and any $\mathcal {F}\in A$ is a solution of the given system.⊣

Since $=_{\sim }$ -equivalence classes within L are singletons ([Reference Šobot15], Corollary 5.10), each class in L trivially contains ultrafilters congruent only to one residue modulo m. We want to investigate for which systems of congruences there is a $=_{\sim }$ -class such that all its ultrafilters satisfy it. Clearly, such a system must be feasible. On the other hand, by Lemma 2.4 a feasible system S has a solution $\mathcal {G}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ so we can assume that it is a system of all congruences satisfied by $\mathcal {G}$ (we will call such a system maximal). Also, every congruence $x\equiv _{m_{i}}r_{i}$ is equivalent to a system of congruences modulo mutually prime factors of $m_{i}$ , so we can assume that all $m_{i}$ are powers of primes themselves. Let $Q_{S}=\{p\in P:\mathcal {G}\equiv _{p^{n}}0\mbox { for all }n\in \mathbb {N}\}$ and $T_{S}=P\setminus Q_{S}$ . As a special case, if $T_{S}=\emptyset $ , all ultrafilters from the class $MAX$ satisfy S.

$A\subset \mathbb {N}$ is an antichain if there are no distinct $a,b\in A$ such that $a\mid b$ .

Theorem 2.5. For every maximal feasible system S of congruences $x\equiv _{p^{n}}r_{p,n}$ (for $n\in \omega $ , $p\in P$ and $r_{p,n}<p^{n}$ ) such that $T_{S}$ is infinite there is an $=_{\sim }$ -equivalence class $\mathcal {C}\not \subseteq L$ such that $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{p^{n}}r_{p,n}$ for all $\mathcal {F}\in \mathcal {C}$ .

Proof We consider two cases.

$1^{\circ } Q_{S}$ is infinite. Let $\{q_{i}:i\in \omega \}$ and $\{t_{i}:i\in \omega \}$ be enumerations of $Q_{S}$ and $T_{S}$ respectively. For $i\in \omega $ let $s_{i}=\min \{n\in \mathbb {N}:\mathcal {G}\not \equiv _{t_{i}^{n}}0\}$ . We construct, by recursion on n, a set $A=\{a_{n}:n\in \omega \}$ such that $a_{n}<a_{n+1}$ and:

  1. (1) $a_{n}\in t_{i}^{s_{i}+n}\mathbb {N}+r_{t_{i},s_{i}+n}$ for $i<n$ ;

  2. (2) $t_{n}^{s_{n}}\mid a_{n}$ ; and

  3. (3) $q_{j}^{n}\mid a_{n}$ for every $j<n$ .

Start with choosing any $a_{0}\in t_{0}^{s_{0}}\mathbb {N}$ . Assume that $a_{n}$ is constructed. We want to choose $a_{n+1}$ satisfying the system $x\equiv _{t_{i}^{s_{i}+n+1}}r_{t_{i},s_{i}+n+1}$ for $i\leq n$ , $x\equiv _{t_{n+1}^{s_{n+1}}}0$ and $x\equiv_{q_j^{n+1}}0$ for $j\leq n$ . By the Chinese remainder theorem this system has a solution in $\mathbb {N}$ such that $a_{n+1}>a_{n}$ . Clearly, obtained $a_{n+1}$ satisfies conditions (1)–(3).

A is an antichain: for all $m<n$ , $a_{m}<a_{n}$ implies that $a_{n}\nmid a_{m}$ , and $t_{m}^{s_{m}}\mid a_{m}$ and (1) imply that $a_{m}\nmid a_{n}$ . Let $\mathcal {C}$ be the $=_{\sim }$ -equivalence class of any ultrafilter containing A. Every ultrafilter $\mathcal {F}\in \mathcal {C}$ contains $A\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow $ and $A\hspace {-0.1cm}\downarrow $ , so it contains $A=A\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow \cap A\hspace {-0.1cm}\downarrow $ as well. Condition (3) clearly implies that A intersects each level $L_{l}$ only in finitely many elements, so $\mathcal {F}\notin L$ , and in particular $\mathcal {F}$ is nonprincipal. By (1), $A\setminus (t_{i}^{m}\mathbb {N}+r_{t_{i},m})$ is finite for all i and all m, hence $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{t_{i}^{m}}r_{t_{i},m}$ . By (3), $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{q_{i}^{n}}0$ for all $i\in \omega $ and $n\in \mathbb {N}$ . Thus $\mathcal {F}$ satisfies all congruences of the given system.

$2^{\circ } Q_{S}$ is finite. We repeat the construction from case $1^{\circ }$ , but for $j\geq |Q_{S}|$ (when we “run out” of elements from $Q_{S}$ ) instead of $q_{j}$ in condition (3) we use some elements $t_{i}\in T$ for $i>n$ . (This condition is needed here only to ensure that $\mathcal {F}\notin L$ .)⊣

Proposition 2.6 ([Reference Šobot14], Lemma 5.2)

If A is an $\mathbb {N}$ -free set, then $A\not \subseteq n_{1}\mathbb {N}\cup n_{2}\mathbb {N}\cup \dots \cup n_{k}\mathbb {N}$ for any $n_{1},n_{2},\dots ,n_{k}\in \mathbb {N}\setminus \{1\}$ .

Example 2.7.

  1. (1) Let us show that the condition of $T_{S}$ being infinite in the theorem above is necessary. Consider a system S consisting of $x\equiv _{t_{i}}r_{i}$ (for some primes $t_{0},t_{1},\dots ,t_{l-1}$ and some nonzero $r_{i}<t_{i}$ ) and $x\equiv _{p^{n}}0$ for all $p\in P\setminus \{t_{0},t_{1},\dots ,t_{l-1}\}$ and all $n\in \mathbb {N}$ . Let us show that there can be no $=_{\sim }$ -class $\mathcal {C}$ such that all $\mathcal {F}\in \mathcal {C}$ satisfy S. Assume the opposite. Then every such $\mathcal {F}$ contains all sets in $\mathcal {U}_{N}:=\{A\in \mathcal {U}:A\mbox { is }\mathbb {N}\mbox {-free}\}$ : by Proposition 2.6 each $A\in \mathcal {U}_{N}$ must contain an element a mutually prime to all $t_{0},t_{1},\dots ,t_{l-1}$ ; hence $a\mid \mathcal {F}$ implies $a\mathbb {N}\in \mathcal {F}$ , and therefore $A\in \mathcal {F}$ . This means that $\mathcal {F}\cap \mathcal {U}=\mathcal {U}_{N}\cup \{A\in \mathcal {U}:n\mathbb {N}\subseteq A\mbox { for some }n\in \mathbb {N}\mbox { such that }t_{i}\nmid n\mbox { for all }i=0,1,\dots ,l-1\}$ . But now, if we change any of the $r_{i}$ s into another nonzero value we stay inside the same class $\mathcal {C}$ .

  2. (2) In the class $NMAX$ of $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ -maximal $\mathbb {N}$ -free ultrafilters one can find an ultrafilter congruent to r modulo m for any $0<r<m$ such that $gcd(m,r)=1$ . Namely, the family $\mathcal {U}_{N}\cup \{\mathbb {N}\setminus n\mathbb {N}:n>1\}\cup \{m\mathbb {N}+r\}$ has the finite intersection property: for any given $A\in \mathcal {U}_{N}$ and $n_{0},n_{1},\dots ,n_{k}\in \mathbb {N}\setminus \{1\}$ , since A is $\mathbb {N}$ -free, Proposition 2.6 says that there is $a\in A$ mutually prime to all of $m,n_{0},\dots ,n_{k}$ . By the Chinese remainder theorem the system $x\equiv _{m}r$ , $x\not \equiv _{n_{i}}0$ , $x\equiv _{a}0$ has a solution, and it belongs to $A\cap (m\mathbb {N}+r)\cap \bigcap _{0\leq i\leq k}(\mathbb {N}\setminus n_{i}\mathbb {N})$ .

Now we will prove a result describing which residues modulo a given prime can appear in the same $=_{\sim }$ -class; first we need the following definition. A set S of residues modulo $p\in P$ is a geometric set of residues if there are s and r such that $0\leq s<p$ , $0<r<p$ and $S=\{rest(sr^{k},p):k\in \omega \}$ , where $rest(x,p)$ is the residue of x modulo p.

Theorem 2.8. Let $p\in P$ and let $S\subseteq \{0,1,\dots ,p-1\}$ . There is an $=_{\sim }$ -equivalence class $\mathcal {C}$ such that the set of residues of ultrafilters $\mathcal {F}\in \mathcal {C}$ modulo p is exactly S if and only if S is a geometric set of residues.

Proof ( $\Leftarrow $ ) First assume that $S=\{s_{0},\dots ,s_{l-1}\}$ is a geometric set of residues, where $s_{i}=rest(s_{0}r^{i},p)$ (for $i=0,1,\dots ,l-1$ ) are exactly all distinct residues of numbers $s_{0}r^{k}$ modulo p. If $S=\{0\}$ , which happens for $s_{0}=0$ , any $=_{\sim }$ -class of ultrafilters divisible by p (i.e., containg the set $p\mathbb {N}$ ) will do. Otherwise, by Dirichlet’s prime number theorem, there are primes $s\equiv _{p}s_{0}$ and $b\equiv _{p}r$ . Let $B=\{sb^{k}:k\in \omega \}$ , $\mathcal {U}^{\prime }=\{U\in \mathcal {U}:U\cap B\neq \emptyset \}$ and $\mathcal {V}^{\prime }=\{V\in \mathcal {V}:\mathbb {N}\setminus V\notin \mathcal {U}^{\prime }\}$ . Then the family $\mathcal {U}^{\prime \prime }=\mathcal {U}^{\prime }\cup \mathcal {V}^{\prime }$ has the finite intersection property: $\mathcal {U}^{\prime }$ is closed for finite intersections, and every $V\in \mathcal {V}^{\prime }$ contains B. Let $\mathcal {C}$ be the $=_{\sim }$ -equivalence class determined by $\mathcal {U}^{\prime \prime }$ . For every $\mathcal {F}\in \mathcal {C}$ we have $B\in \mathcal {F}$ (since $B\cup \{b^{k}:k\in \omega \}\in \mathcal {V}^{\prime }$ and $\mathbb {N}\setminus \{b^{k}:k\in \omega \}\in \mathcal {U}^{\prime }$ ) and $B\subseteq \bigcup _{i=0}^{l-1}(p\mathbb {N}+s_{i})$ , so every such $\mathcal {F}$ is congruent to some $s_{i}$ modulo p. On the other hand, for each $i\in \{0,1,\dots ,l-1\}$ the family $\mathcal {U}^{\prime \prime }\cup \{p\mathbb {N}+s_{i}\}$ has the finite intersection property: B contains infinitely many elements from each of the sets $p\mathbb {N}+s_{i}$ , and finite intersections of sets from $\mathcal {U}^{\prime \prime }$ contain all but finitely many elements from B, so they also intersect $p\mathbb {N}+s_{i}$ . Hence there is an ultrafilter $\mathcal {F}\in \mathcal {C}$ such that $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{p} s_{i}$ .

( $\Rightarrow $ ) Now assume S is the set of residues modulo p of ultrafilters $\mathcal {F}\in \mathcal {C}$ for some $=_{\sim }$ -equivalence class $\mathcal {C}$ . Every singleton is clearly a geometric set of residues (obtained by choosing the quotient $r=1$ ), so we will assume $|S|>1$ . Let $\mathcal {W}$ be the family of all convex sets belonging to all $\mathcal {F}\in \mathcal {C}$ . Since the elements of S are all possible residues of ultrafilters $\mathcal {F}\in \mathcal {C}$ , there is $C\in \mathcal {W}$ (a finite intersection of sets from $(\mathcal {U}\cup \mathcal {V})\cap \mathcal {F}$ ) such that $C\subseteq \bigcup _{k=0}^{l-1}(p\mathbb {N}+s_{k})$ (otherwise $\mathcal {W}\cup \{\mathbb {N}\setminus \bigcup _{k=0}^{l-1}(p\mathbb {N}+s_{k})\}$ would have the finite intersection property).

Let q be a primitive root modulo p (this means that for every $0<r<p$ there is $k\in \mathbb {N}$ such that $q^{k}\equiv _{p}r$ ; see [Reference Burton2] for more details). Let $S=\{s_{0},\dots ,s_{l-1}\}$ , where $s_{i}=rest(q^{k_{i}},p)$ , $k_{0}<k_{1}<\dots <k_{l-1}$ and for each $s_{i}$ the smallest $k_{i}$ is chosen. If we denote $r_{i}=k_{i}-k_{0}$ for $0<i<l$ , then $s_{i}=rest(s_{0}q^{r_{i}},p)$ .

Claim 1. The set $R:=\{r_{i}:0<i<l\}$ is closed for the $gcd$ (greatest common divisor) operation.

Proof of Claim 1 Let $0<i<j<l$ . Take $A_{0}$ to be the set of $\mid $ -minimal elements of $C\cap (p\mathbb {N}+s_{0})$ . By recursion on k, let $A_{3k+1}$ be the set of $\mid $ -minimal elements of $C\cap A_{3k}\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow \cap (p\mathbb {N}+s_{i})$ , $A_{3k+2}$ the set of $\mid $ -minimal elements of $C\cap A_{3k+1}\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow \cap (p\mathbb {N}+s_{j})$ and $A_{3k+3}$ the set of $\mid $ -minimal elements of $C\cap A_{3k+2}\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow \cap (p\mathbb {N}+s_{0})$ . Each of the sets $A_{m}$ (for $m\in \omega $ ) must be nonempty, since otherwise

$$ \begin{align*}C\subseteq (C\setminus A_{0}\hspace{-0.1cm}\uparrow)\cup(C\cap A_{0}\hspace{-0.1cm}\uparrow\setminus A_{1}\hspace{-0.1cm}\uparrow)\cup\dots\cup(C\cap A_{m-1}\hspace{-0.1cm}\uparrow),\end{align*} $$

and each of the (convex) sets on the right would miss one of the sets $p\mathbb {N}+s_{0}$ , $p\mathbb {N}+s_{i}$ or $p\mathbb {N}+s_{j}$ , so it could not belong to all ultrafilters in $\mathcal {C}$ .

Now let $d=gcd(r_{i},r_{j})$ . By Bézout’s lemma there are $a^{\prime },b^{\prime }\in \mathbb {Z}$ such that $a^{\prime }r_{i}+b^{\prime }r_{j}=d$ . By replacing $a^{\prime },b^{\prime }$ with their residues modulo $p-1$ we get $a,b\in \mathbb {Z}_{p-1}$ such that $ar_{i}+br_{j}\equiv _{p-1}d$ . Let $m=3(a+b)$ and let $\langle c_{i}:0\leq i<m\rangle $ be a $\mid $ -chain in C of length m such that $c_{i}\in A_{i}$ (it exists since $A_{m-1}\neq \emptyset $ ). Let $c_{i+1}=c_{i}d_{i}$ ; then $d_{3k}\equiv _{p} q^{r_{i}}$ and $d_{3k}d_{3k+1}\equiv _{p} q^{r_{j}}$ for all k. Hence

$$ \begin{align*} e &:= d_{0}d_{3}\dots d_{3(a-1)}d_{3a}d_{3a+1}d_{3(a+1)}d_{3(a+1)+1}\dots d_{3(a+b-1)}d_{3(a+b-1)+1}\\ &\equiv_{p} (q^{r_{i}})^{a}(q^{r_{j}})^{b}=q^{ar_{i}+br_{j}}\equiv_{p} q^{d} \end{align*} $$

(in the last equality we used Fermat’s little theorem). But $c_{0}e$ is divisible by $c_{0}$ and divides $c_{m}$ ; since C is convex, $c_{0}e\in C$ and hence $d\in R$ .⊣

Claim 2. $rest(tr_{1},p-1)\in R$ for all $t\in \mathbb {N}$ .

Proof of Claim 2 is similar to (though simpler than) the proof of Claim 1. We construct a $\mid $ -chain $\langle c_{i}:0\leq i\leq 2t-2\rangle $ such that $c_{i}\in p\mathbb {N}+s_{0}$ for odd i and $c_{i}\in p\mathbb {N}+s_{1}$ for even i. If $c_{i+1}=c_{i}d_{i}$ , we get $c_{0}d_{1}d_{3}\dots d_{2t-3}\equiv _{p} q^{tr_{1}}$ , so $tr_{1}\equiv _{p-1}r_{j}$ for some $r_{j}\in R$ .⊣

Now, since $r_{1}<r_{2}<\dots <r_{l-1}$ , the two Claims show that R must have the form $R=\{ir_{1}:0<i<l\}$ . But then $s_{i}\equiv _{p} s_{0}(q^{r_{1}})^{i}$ , which is what we wanted to prove.⊣

3 $\omega $ -hyperextensions of $\mathbb {Z}$

In the previous two papers, [Reference Šobot12] and [Reference Šobot14], we employed nonstandard methods (more precisely, the superstructure approach) to get more information on the relation $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ . We will continue that practice here. However, now we turn to extensions of the set $\mathbb {Z}$ of all integers instead of $\mathbb {N}$ . The reason is, of course, that we want to use the operation of subtraction. Let X be a set containing a copy of $\mathbb {Z}$ consisting of atoms: none of the elements of X contains as an element any of the other relevant sets. Let $V_{0}(X)=X$ , $V_{n+1}(X)=V_{n}(X)\cup P(V_{n}(X))$ for $n\in \omega $ and $V(X)=\bigcup _{n<\omega }V_{n}(X)$ . $V(X)$ is then called a superstructure. The rank of an element $x\in V(X)$ is the smallest $n\in \omega $ such that $x\in V_{n}(X)$ .

If $V(X)$ is a superstructure, its nonstandard extension is a pair $(V(Y),*)$ , where $V(Y)$ is a superstructure with the set of atoms Y and $*:V(X)\rightarrow V(Y)$ is a rank-preserving function such that $A\subseteq {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}A}$ for $A\subseteq X$ , $\mathbb {Z}\subset {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ , ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}X}=Y$ and satisfying the Transfer principle (we delay the formulation of Transfer until later, since we will need a more general version).

A nonstandard extension $(V(Y),*)$ of $V(X)$ is a $\kappa $ - enlargement if for every family F of subsets of some set in $V(X)$ with the finite intersection property such that $|F|<\kappa $ there is an element in $\bigcap _{A\in F}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}A}$ . $\kappa $ -enlargements are known to exist in ZFC.

For an excellent introduction to nonstandard methods we refer the reader to [Reference Goldblatt4].

The connection between a nonstandard extension and $\beta \mathbb {Z}$ is given by the function $v:{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}\rightarrow \beta \mathbb {Z}$ , defined by $v(x)=\{A\subseteq \mathbb {Z}:x\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}A}\}$ . v is onto whenever $(V(Y),*)$ is a $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement.

Proposition 3.1 ([Reference Ng and Render8], Lemma 1)

For every $x\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb{Z}}$ and every $f:\mathbb {Z}\rightarrow \mathbb {Z}$ , $v({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}f}(x))=\widetilde {f}(v(x))$ .

More information about v can be found in [Reference Ng and Render8] and [Reference Luperi Baglini7]. The following proposition is Theorem 3.1 of [Reference Šobot12], adjusted for extensions of $\mathbb {Z}$ (instead of $\mathbb {N}$ ).

Proposition 3.2. The following conditions are equivalent for every two ultrafilters $\mathcal {F},\mathcal {G}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ :

  1. (i) $\mathcal {F}\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}\mathcal {G}$ ;

  2. (ii) in every $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement $V(Y)$ , there are $x,y\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ such that $v(x)=\mathcal {F}$ , $v(y)=\mathcal {G}$ and $x{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-1mm}\mid } y$ ; and

  3. (iii) in some $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement $V(Y)$ , there are $x,y\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ such that $v(x)=\mathcal {F}$ , $v(y)=\mathcal {G}$ and $x{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-1mm}\mid } y$ .

First, let us establish that we can use all previously obtained results about ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {N}}$ while working with ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ . In every extension $V(Y)$ the nonstandard set ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ consists of ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {N}}$ , another (“inverted”) copy of ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {N}}$ (containing negative nonstandard numbers) and zero. For $x,y\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ , $x{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-1mm}\mid } y$ holds if and only if $|x|\;{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-1mm}\mid }\;|y|$ .

The situation with $\beta \mathbb {Z}$ is similar. Let, for $A\subseteq \mathbb {Z}$ , $-A:=\{-a:a\in A\}$ ; likewise, for $\mathcal {F}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ let $-\mathcal {F}:=\{-A:A\in \mathcal {F}\}$ . Then every ultrafilter in $\beta \mathbb {Z}$ (except the principal ultrafilter identified with zero) contains either $\mathbb {N}$ or $-\mathbb {N}$ , so $\beta \mathbb {Z}=\beta \mathbb {N}\cup \{-\mathcal {F}:\mathcal {F}\in \beta \mathbb {N}\}\cup \{0\}$ . The family $\mathcal {U}_{Z}:=\{U\in P(\mathbb {Z})\setminus \{\emptyset \}:U\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow =U\}$ of upward closed subsets of $\mathbb {Z}$ consists of sets $V\cup -V\cup \{0\}$ for $V\in \mathcal {U}$ , and divisibility in $\beta \mathbb {Z}$ is naturally defined as: $\mathcal {F}\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}\mathcal {G}$ if and only if $\mathcal {F}\cap \mathcal {U}_{Z}\subseteq \mathcal {G}$ . Thus, $\mathcal {F}\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}\mathcal {G}$ if and only if $|\mathcal {F}|\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}|\mathcal {G}|$ (for absolute values of ultrafilters defined in the obvious way).

We will write $\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}$ instead of $\mathcal {F}+(-\mathcal {G})$ . So $A\in \mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}$ if and only if $\{n\in \mathbb {Z}:n-A\in \mathcal {G}\}\in \mathcal {F}$ , where $n-A=\{n-a:a\in A\}$ . Note that there can be no confusion with this notation, since $\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}$ is exactly the ultrafilter obtained by extending the subtraction operation from $\mathbb {Z}$ to $\beta \mathbb {Z}$ , as defined in (1).

A nonstandard extension $(V(Y),*)$ of $V(X)$ is called a single superstructure model if $Y=X$ . The existence of such a model was proved in [Reference Benci1]. In a single superstructure model it is possible to iterate the star-function, since it is defined for all elements in the range of $*$ .

Definition 3.3. Let $(V(X),*)$ be a single superstructure model with $\mathbb {Z}\subseteq X$ . Define recursively, for $x\in V(X)$ , $S_{0}(x)=x$ and $S_{k+1}(x)={{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}(}S_{k}(x))$ for all $k\in \omega $ . For $A\subseteq X$ the set ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}A}=\bigcup _{k<\omega }S_{k}(A)$ is called an $\omega $ -hyperextension of A.

Now, any $(V(X),S_{k})$ is a nonstandard extension. Moreover, we have the following.

Proposition 3.4 ([Reference Luperi Baglini7], Proposition 2.5.7)

If $(V(X),*)$ is a single superstructure model which is a $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement, then $(V(X),S_{k})$ for every $k\in \omega $ are also $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargements.

We will call a single superstructure model $(V(X),*)$ which is a $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement an $\omega $ -hyperenlargement.

Now we can use the Transfer principle within any of the mentioned extensions. Recall that a first-order formula $\varphi (x_{1},x_{2},\dots ,x_{n})$ is bounded if all its quantifiers are bounded, i.e., of the form $(\forall x\in y)$ or $(\exists x\in y)$ . In the Transfer principle the free variables $x_{1},x_{2},\dots ,x_{n}$ that appear in $\varphi (x_{1},x_{2},\dots ,x_{n})$ can take values of elements $a_{1},a_{2},\dots ,a_{n}\in V(X)$ and in $\varphi ({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}a}_{1},{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}a}_{2},\dots ,{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}a}_{n})$ they are replaced with their star-counterparts. Any k-ary relation $A\in V(X)$ appearing as an atomic subformula in $\varphi $ is also considered like a free variable and gets replaced with ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}A}$ .

The Transfer principle. For every bounded formula $\varphi $ and every $a_{1},a_{2},\dots $ , $a_{n}\in V(X)$ , in $V(X)\, \varphi (a_{1},a_{2},\dots ,a_{n})$ holds if and only if $\varphi (S_{k}(a_{1}),S_{k}(a_{2}),\dots $ , $S_{k}(a_{n}))$ holds (for any $k\in \mathbb {N}$ ).

As a simple application of Transfer notice that ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}(}x+y)={{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}+{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}$ for $x,y\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}Z}$ , a fact that we will need later: if $z=x+y$ , Transfer implies that ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}z}={{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}+{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}$ . Likewise, ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}(}x\cdot y)={{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}\cdot {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}$ .

Proposition 3.5 ([Reference Luperi Baglini7], Proposition 2.5.3)

  1. (a) For $k\leq l$ and $A\subseteq \mathbb {Z}$ , $S_{k}(A)=S_{l}(A)\cap S_{k}(\mathbb {Z})$ . Consequently, $S_{k}(A)={{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}A}\cap S_{k}(\mathbb {Z})$ .

  2. (b) For $k\leq l$ , $h:\mathbb {Z}\rightarrow \mathbb {Z}$ and $x\in S_{k}(\mathbb {Z})$ , $S_l(h)(x)=S_k(h)(x)$ .

Therefore we can write ${}^\bullet h:{}^\bullet\mathbb{N}\rightarrow{}^\bullet\mathbb{N}$ for the function defined by ${}^\bullet h(x)=S_k(h)$ for $x\in S_k(\mathbb{Z})$ .

Let us comment on the iterated version of the divisibility relation. It is common to omit $*$ (or, more generally, $S_{k}$ ) in formulas in front of the relations $=$ and $\in $ and arithmetical operations, in order to simplify notation. Let us show that it is justified to do the same with the divisibility relation, even when working in an $\omega $ -hyperextension. Firstly, $(x,y)\in S_{k}(\mid )$ can hold only if $x,y\in S_{k}(\mathbb {Z})$ . On the other hand, for $x\in S_{k}(\mathbb {N})$ , $y\in S_{k}(\mathbb {Z})$ and $l>k$ , we will show that $(x,y)\in S_{k}(\mid )$ if and only if $(x,y)\in S_{l}(\mid )$ .

$(x,y)\in S_{k}(\mid )$ means that there is $z\in S_{k}(\mathbb {Z})$ such that $y=xz$ . But $S_{k}(\mathbb {Z})\subseteq S_{l}(\mathbb {Z})$ , so $(x,y)\in S_{l}(\mid )$ follows. In the other direction, if $(x,y)\in S_{l}(\mid )$ for some $l>k$ , and $y=xz$ , then $z\in S_{k}(\mathbb {Z})$ so $(x,y)\in S_{k}(\mid )$ as well. Thus, there will be no ambiguity if we drop the stars and write simply $x\mid y$ instead of $(x,y)\in S_{k}(\mid )$ .

Definition 3.6. For $\mathcal {F}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ , $\mu _{n}(\mathcal {F})=\{x\in S_{n}(\mathbb {Z}):(\forall A\in \mathcal {F})x\in S_{n}(A)\}$ .

The monad of $\mathcal {F}$ is $\mu (\mathcal {F})=\bigcup _{n<\omega }\mu _{n}(\mathcal {F})=\{x\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}:(\forall A\in \mathcal {F})x\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}A}\}$ .

For $x\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ , $v(x)$ is the unique $\mathcal {F}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ such that $x\in \mu (\mathcal {F})$ .

Note that this definition of $v(x)$ agrees with the previous one (for $x\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ ).

Proposition 3.7 ([Reference Luperi Baglini7], Proposition 2.5.11)

For every $x\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ and every $n\in \omega $ , $v(S_{n}(x))=v(x)$ .

Let us recall the tensor (or Fubini) product of ultrafilters: for $\mathcal {F},\mathcal {G}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ , $\mathcal {F}\otimes \mathcal {G}$ is the ultrafilter on $\mathbb {Z}\times \mathbb {Z}$ defined by

$$ \begin{align*}S\in\mathcal{F}\otimes\mathcal{G}\Leftrightarrow\{x\in \mathbb{Z}:\{y\in \mathbb{Z}:(x,y)\in S\}\in\mathcal{G}\}\in\mathcal{F}.\end{align*} $$

The definitions of monads of ultrafilters of the form $\mathcal {F}\otimes \mathcal {G}$ and the corresponding function v are analogous as above. For ultrafilters $\mathcal {F}$ and $\mathcal {G}$ and nonstandard numbers $x\in \mu (\mathcal {F})$ and $y\in \mu (\mathcal {G})$ , $(x,y)$ is a tensor pair if $(x,y)\in \mu (\mathcal {F}\otimes \mathcal {G})$ .

Lemma 3.8. If $(x,y)\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}\times {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ is a tensor pair, then so are $(x,-y)$ and $(-x,y)$ .

Proof Let $\mathcal {F}=v(x)$ and $\mathcal {G}=v(y)$ ; then $v(-y)=-\mathcal {G}$ and $v((x,y))=\mathcal {F}\otimes \mathcal {G}$ . We need to prove that $v((x,-y))=\mathcal {F}\otimes (-\mathcal {G})$ . But whenever $(x,-y)\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}S}$ for some $S\subseteq \mathbb {Z}\times \mathbb {Z}$ , we have $(x,y)\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}S}^{\prime }$ , where $S^{\prime }:=\{(m,-n):(m,n)\in S\}$ . By the assumptions $S^{\prime }\in \mathcal {F}\otimes \mathcal {G}$ , so $\{x\in \mathbb {Z}:\{y\in \mathbb {Z}:(x,y)\in S\}\in (-\mathcal {G})\}=\{x\in \mathbb {Z}:-\{y\in \mathbb {Z}:(x,y)\in S\}\in \mathcal {G}\}=\{x\in \mathbb {Z}:\{y\in \mathbb {Z}:(x,y)\in S^{\prime }\}\in \mathcal {G}\}\in \mathcal {F}$ , and $S\in \mathcal {F}\otimes (-\mathcal {G})$ .

The proof for $(-x,y)$ is analogous. ⊣

By [Reference Di Nasso3], Proposition 11.7.2, for any tensor pair $(x,y)$ we have $x+y\in \mu (\mathcal {F}+\mathcal {G})$ and $x\cdot y\in \mu (\mathcal {F}\cdot \mathcal {G})$ . An important feature of $\omega $ -hyperextensions is that they provide a canonical way to obtain tensor pairs.

Proposition 3.9 ([Reference Luperi Baglini7], Theorem 2.5.27)

If $x\in \mu (\mathcal {F})$ and $y\in \mu (\mathcal {G})$ , then the pair $(x,{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y})$ is a tensor pair. Hence, $x+{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}\in \mu (\mathcal {F}+\mathcal {G})$ and $x\cdot {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}\in \mu (\mathcal {F}\cdot \mathcal {G})$ .

4 Congruence modulo ultrafilter

A natural way to define the congruence relation modulo an ultrafilter would be to imitate again the construction of an extension $\widetilde {\rho }$ , as described in §1.

Definition 4.1. For $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ and $\mathcal {F},\mathcal {G}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ , $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}\mathcal {G}$ if and only if for every $A\in \mathcal {M}$ the set $\{(x,y)\in \mathbb {Z}\times \mathbb {Z}:(\exists m\in A)x\equiv _{m}y\}$ belongs to the ultrafilter $\mathcal {F}\otimes \mathcal {G}$ .

This definition has a nice equivalent formulation via divisibility of ultrafilters.

Lemma 4.2. For $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ and $\mathcal {F},\mathcal {G}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ , $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}\mathcal {G}$ if and only if $\mathcal {M}\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}$ .

Proof

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{F}\equiv_{\mathcal{M}}\mathcal{G} &\Leftrightarrow (\forall A\in\mathcal{M})\{x\in \mathbb{Z}:\{y\in \mathbb{Z}:(\exists m\in A)x\equiv_{m}y\}\in\mathcal{G}\}\in\mathcal{F}\\ &\Leftrightarrow (\forall A\in\mathcal{M})\{x\in \mathbb{Z}:\{y\in \mathbb{Z}:x-y\in A\hspace{-0.1cm}\uparrow\}\in\mathcal{G}\}\in\mathcal{F}\\ &\Leftrightarrow (\forall A\in\mathcal{M}\cap\mathcal{U})\{x\in \mathbb{Z}:\{y\in \mathbb{Z}:x-y\in A\}\in\mathcal{G}\}\in\mathcal{F}\\ &\Leftrightarrow (\forall A\in\mathcal{M}\cap\mathcal{U})\{x\in \mathbb{Z}:x-A\in\mathcal{G}\}\in\mathcal{F}\\ &\Leftrightarrow (\forall A\in\mathcal{M}\cap\mathcal{U})A\in\mathcal{F}-\mathcal{G}, \end{align*} $$

which is equivalent to $\mathcal {M}\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}$ .⊣

The following lemma justifies our using the same notation as for the relation from §2.

Lemma 4.3. If $m\in \mathbb {N}$ and $\mathcal {F},\mathcal {G}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ , $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{m}\mathcal {G}$ as defined in §2 is equivalent to $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{m}\mathcal {G}$ from Definition 4.1.

Proof By Proposition 2.1 $\widetilde {h_{m}}$ is a homomorphism, so $\widetilde {h_{m}}(\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G})=\widetilde {h_{m}}(\mathcal {F})-\widetilde {h_{m}}(\mathcal {G})$ . It follows that $m\mid \mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}$ if and only if $\widetilde {h_{m}}(\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G})=0$ , if and only if $\widetilde {h_{m}}(\mathcal {F})=\widetilde {h_{m}}(\mathcal {G})$ . ⊣

$\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}$ also has a nonstandard characterization. First we recall Puritz’s result that $(x,y)\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {N}}\times {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {N}}$ is a tensor pair if and only if $x<{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}f}(y)$ for every $f:\mathbb {N}\rightarrow \mathbb {N}$ such that ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}f}(y)\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {N}}\setminus \mathbb {N}$ ([Reference Puritz10], Theorem 3.4). Taking into account Lemma 3.8, we get the following version of this result.

Proposition 4.4. $(x,y)\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}\times {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ is a tensor pair if and only if $|x|<|{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}f}(y)|$ for every $f:\mathbb {Z}\rightarrow \mathbb {Z}$ such that ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}f}(y)\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}\setminus \mathbb {Z}$ .

If we denote $\mathcal {G}=v(y)$ , the condition ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}f}(y)\notin \mathbb {Z}$ is equivalent to $f\upharpoonright B$ not being constant for any $B\in \mathcal {G}$ . Let us call $f:\mathbb {Z}\rightarrow \mathbb {Z}$ non- $\mathcal {G}$ -constant in that case.

Note that we are still working in any $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement (we do not need an $\omega $ -hyperextension), so $\mu (\mathcal {F})$ here actually means $\mu _{1}(\mathcal {F})$ .

Theorem 4.5. Let $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ and $\mathcal {F},\mathcal {G}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ . The following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (i) $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}\mathcal {G}$

  2. (ii) in some $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement holds

    (2) $$ \begin{align} (\forall m\in\mu(\mathcal{M}))(\exists x\in\mu(\mathcal{F}))(\exists y\in\mu(\mathcal{G}))((x,y)\mbox{ is a tensor pair }\land m\mid x-y) \end{align} $$
  3. (iii) in every $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement holds (2).

Proof (ii) $\Rightarrow $ (i) Let (2) hold in some $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement. If $y\in \mu (\mathcal {G})$ then $-y\in \mu (-\mathcal {G})$ . Since for a tensor pair $(x,y)$ we have, by Lemma 3.8, $x-y=x+ (-y)\in \mu (\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G})$ , the result follows directly from Proposition 3.2 and Lemma 4.2.

(i) $\Rightarrow $ (iii) Assume $\mathcal {M}\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}$ ; we work in arbitrary $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement. We define, for $A,B\subseteq \mathbb {Z}$ , $M\subseteq \mathbb {N}$ and $f:\mathbb {Z}\rightarrow \mathbb {Z}$ :

$$ \begin{align*} & E_{A,B,M}=\{(m,a,b)\in\mathbb{N}\times\mathbb{Z}\times\mathbb{Z}:a\in A\land b\in B\land m\in M\land m\mid a-b\}\\ & F_{f}=\{(m,a,b)\in\mathbb{N}\times\mathbb{Z}\times\mathbb{Z}:|a|<|f(b)|\}. \end{align*} $$

We prove that the family $\{E_{A,B,M}:A\in \mathcal {F},B\in \mathcal {G},M\in \mathcal {M}\}\cup \{F_{f}:f:\mathbb {Z}\rightarrow \mathbb {Z}\mbox { is non-}\mathcal {G}\mbox {-constant}\}$ has the finite intersection property. $\{E_{A,B,M}:A\in \mathcal {F},B\in \mathcal {G},M\in \mathcal {M}\}$ is closed for finite intersections. So let $A\in \mathcal {F}$ , $B\in \mathcal {G}$ , $M\in \mathcal {M}$ and let $f_{1},f_{2},\dots ,f_{k}:\mathbb {Z}\rightarrow \mathbb {Z}$ be non- $\mathcal {G}$ -constant. Since $M\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow \in \mathcal {M}\cap \mathcal {U}$ , $\mathcal {M}\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}$ implies $M\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow \in \mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}$ . Hence $\{n\in \mathbb {Z}:n-M\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow \in \mathcal {G}\}\in \mathcal {F}$ . Let $a\in A\cap \{n\in \mathbb {Z}:n-M\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow \in \mathcal {G}\}$ . This means that $B_{1}:=B\cap (a-M\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow )\in \mathcal {G}$ . Hence there is $b\in B_{1}$ such that $|f_{i}(b)|>|a|$ for all $i\leq k$ (otherwise $\{b\in B_{1}:f_{i}(b)=j\}\in \mathcal {G}$ for some $i\leq k$ and some $-a\leq j\leq a$ , a contradiction with the assumption that $f_{i}$ is non- $\mathcal {G}$ -constant). Since $b\in a-M\hspace {-0.1cm}\uparrow $ , there is $m\in M$ such that $m\mid a-b$ , so $(m,a,b)\in E_{A,B,M}\cap F_{f_{1}}\cap F_{f_{2}}\cap \dots \cap F_{f_{k}}$ .

Now, since we are working with a $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement, there is

$$ \begin{align*}(m,x,y)\in\bigcap_{A\in\mathcal{F},B\in\mathcal{G},M\in\mathcal{M}}{{{\hspace{-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace{-0.5mm}E}_{A,B,M}\;\;\cap\bigcap_{f\mbox{ non-}\mathcal{G}\mbox{-constant}}{{{\hspace{-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace{-0.5mm}F}_{f}.\end{align*} $$

This means that $m\in \mu (\mathcal {M})$ , $x\in \mu (\mathcal {F})$ , $y\in \mu (\mathcal {G})$ and $m\mid x-y$ . Also, for every non- $\mathcal {G}$ -constant $f:\mathbb {Z}\rightarrow \mathbb {Z}$ , $|{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}f}(y)|>|x|$ , so $(x,y)$ is a tensor pair. ⊣

Unfortunately, we do not even know whether $\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}$ is an equivalence relation on $\beta \mathbb {Z}$ , which makes it unconvenient to work with. Therefore in the next section we introduce a stronger relation with much nicer properties.

5 Strong congruence

To better explain the forthcoming definition of congruence, we begin with a few simple lemmas. Recall that $MAX$ is the class of ultrafilters $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ -divisible by all others.

Lemma 5.1. Let $x,y\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ and $v(x)=v(y)$ . Then $m\mid x-y$ for all $m\in \mathbb {N}$ and $x-y\in \mu (MAX)$ .

Proof For each $m\in \mathbb {N}$ , let $h_{m}$ be the function defined in §2. Then ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}h}_{m}(x)\in \mathbb {Z}_{m}$ for all $x\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ . By Proposition 3.1, $v({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}h}_{m}(x))=\widetilde {h_{m}}(v(x))=\widetilde {h_{m}}(v(y))=v({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}h}_{m}(y))$ , so x and y have the same residue modulo m.

Ultrafilters from $MAX$ are those divisible by all $m\in \mathbb {N}$ . Hence $\mu (MAX)$ consists exactly of nonstandard numbers divisible by all $m\in \mathbb {N}$ , so the second statement follows directly from the first. ⊣

By Theorem 2.8, the assumption of Lemma 5.1 can not be relaxed to $v(x)=_{\sim } v(y)$ : there are $=_{\sim }$ -equivalent ultrafilters giving different residues modulo some $m\in \mathbb {N}$ .

Lemma 5.2. Let $x,y\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}$ , $v(x)=v(y)$ and $m\in S_{k}(\mathbb {N})$ . Then $m\mid S_{k}(x)-S_{k}(y)$ .

Proof By Lemma 5.1, $(\forall m\in \mathbb {N})m\mid x-y$ . By Transfer, $(\forall m\in S_{k}(\mathbb {N}))m\mid S_{k}(x)-S_{k}(y)$ . ⊣

Thus, for every $m\in S_{k}(\mathbb {N})$ , all the numbers from $\mu (\mathcal {F})\cap S_{k}[{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {Z}}]$ have the same residue modulo m. We will use this to establish a strengthening of congruence modulo $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ .

Definition 5.3. Ultrafilters $\mathcal {F},\mathcal {G}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ are strongly congruent modulo $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ if, in every $\omega $ -hyperenlargement,

(3) $$ \begin{align} (\forall m\in\mu_{1}(\mathcal{M}))(\exists x\in\mu(\mathcal{F}))(\exists y\in\mu(\mathcal{G}))m\mid{{{\hspace{-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace{-0.5mm}x}-{{{\hspace{-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace{-0.5mm}y}. \end{align} $$

We write $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {G}$ .

We easily get the following equivalent condition.

Lemma 5.4. $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {G}$ implies that in every $\omega $ -hyperenlargement

$$ \begin{align*}(\forall m\in\mu_{1}(\mathcal{M}))(\forall x\in\mu(\mathcal{F}))(\forall y\in\mu(\mathcal{G}))m\mid{{{\hspace{-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace{-0.5mm}x}-{{{\hspace{-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace{-0.5mm}y}.\end{align*} $$

Proof Let $x_{0}\in \mu (\mathcal {F})$ and $y_{0}\in \mu (\mathcal {G})$ be such that $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}_{0}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{0}$ , and let $x\in \mu (\mathcal {F})$ and $y\in \mu (\mathcal {G})$ be arbitrary. By Lemma 5.2, $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}_{0}$ and $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{0}$ , so $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}$ as well. ⊣

To avoid constant repetition, in each of the proofs in the rest of the paper it will be understood that we are working in an $\omega $ -hyperenlargement (a single superstructure extension which is a $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement).

It will follow from Lemmas 6.5, 6.3, and 4.2 that $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {G}$ implies $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}\mathcal {G}$ . For now we prove that $\equiv _{m}^{s}$ for $m\in \mathbb {N}$ also coincides with the congruence relation modulo integer (from §2).

Lemma 5.5. If $m\in \mathbb {N}$ and $\mathcal {F},\ \mathcal {G}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ , $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{m}^{s}\mathcal {G}$ holds if and only if $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{m}\mathcal {G}$ .

Proof The only element of $\mu _{1}(m)$ is m itself. Let $x\in \mu (\mathcal {F})$ and $y\in \mu (\mathcal {G})$ be such that $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}$ ; then ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}$ and ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}$ have the same residue modulo m: ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}h}_{m}({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x})={{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}h}_{m}({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y})$ . Then, by Propositions 3.1 and 3.7, $\widetilde {h_{m}}(\mathcal {F})=v({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}h}_{m}({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}))=v({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{\bullet }\hspace {-0.5mm}h}_{m}({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}))=\widetilde {h_{m}}(\mathcal {G})$ , so $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{m}\mathcal {G}$ . The other implication is proved similarly, using Lemma 5.4. ⊣

Lemma 5.6. $\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}$ is an equivalence relation on the set $\beta \mathbb {Z}$ .

Proof Reflexivity and symmetry are obvious from the definition. So let $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {G}$ and $\mathcal {G}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {H}$ . By Lemma 5.4, for any $m\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {M})$ , $x\in \mu (\mathcal {F})$ , $y\in \mu (\mathcal {G})$ and $z\in \mu (\mathcal {H})$ holds $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}$ and $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}z}$ . Then $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}z}$ , so $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {H}$ . ⊣

Theorem 5.7. Let $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ . $\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}$ is compatible with operations $+$ and $\cdot $ in $\beta \mathbb {Z}$ :

  1. (a) $\mathcal {F}_{1}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {F}_{2}$ and $\mathcal {G}_{1}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {G}_{2}$ imply $\mathcal {F}_{1}+\mathcal {G}_{1}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {F}_{2}+\mathcal {G}_{2}$ and

  2. (b) $\mathcal {F}_{1}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {F}_{2}$ and $\mathcal {G}_{1}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {G}_{2}$ imply $\mathcal {F}_{1}\cdot \mathcal {G}_{1}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {F}_{2}\cdot \mathcal {G}_{2}$ .

Proof Let $m\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {M})$ , $x_{1}\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {F}_{1})$ , $x_{2}\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {F}_{2})$ , $y_{1}\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {G}_{1})$ and $y_{2}\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {G}_{2})$ . It follows from Proposition 3.7 that ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{1}\in \mu (\mathcal {G}_{1})$ and ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{2}\in \mu (\mathcal {G}_{2})$ . By the assumptions we have $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}_{1}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}_{2}$ and $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{1}}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{2}}$ .

  1. (a) By Proposition 3.9 $x_{1}+{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{1}\in \mu (\mathcal {F}_{1}+\mathcal {G}_{1})$ and $x_{2}+{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{2}\in \mu (\mathcal {F}_{2}+\mathcal {G}_{2})$ . From the above conclusions follows $m\mid ({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}_{1}+{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{1}})-({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}_{2}+{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{2}})$ , i.e., $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}(}x_{1}+{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{1})-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}(}x_{2}+{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{2})$ . Since we started with arbitrary $m\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {M})$ , this means that $\mathcal {F}_{1}+\mathcal {G}_{1}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {F}_{2}+\mathcal {G}_{2}$ .

  2. (b) By Proposition 3.9 $x_{1}\cdot {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{1}\in \mu (\mathcal {F}_{1}\cdot \mathcal {G}_{1})$ and $x_{2}\cdot {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{2}\in \mu (\mathcal {F}_{2}\cdot \mathcal {G}_{2})$ . We have $m\mid ({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}_{1}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}_{2}){{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{1}}$ and $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}_{2}({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{1}}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{2}})$ . Hence $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}_{1}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{1}}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}_{2}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{2}}$ , i.e., $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}(}x_{1}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{1})-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}(}x_{2}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}_{2})$ , so $\mathcal {F}_{1}\cdot \mathcal {G}_{1}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {F}_{2}\cdot \mathcal {G}_{2}$ .⊣

The following simple result is a version of a well-known fact ([Reference Puritz9], Corollary 8.3).

Lemma 5.8.

  1. (a) Every $\mathcal {F}\in MAX$ is strongly congruent to zero modulo any ultrafilter and

  2. (b) for every $\mathcal {F}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}\setminus \mathbb {Z}$ , $\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {F}\in MAX$ .

Proof

  1. (a) For any $\mathcal {F}\in MAX$ and any $x\in \mu (\mathcal {F})$ , $(\forall m\in \mathbb {N})m\mid x$ implies by Transfer $(\forall m\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {N}})m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}$ , which gives us $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}} 0$ for any $\mathcal {M}$ .

  2. (b) We will show that $A\in \mathcal {F}-\mathcal {F}$ for all $A\in \mathcal {U}_{Z}$ (see the two paragraphs following Proposition 3.2). Let $m\in A$ be arbitrary. Then there is $r\in \mathbb {Z}_{m}$ such that $m\mathbb {Z}+r\in \mathcal {F}$ , so since $m\mathbb {Z}\subseteq -A$ , it follows that $n-A\in \mathcal {F}$ for all $n\in m\mathbb {Z}+r$ . Thus $m\mathbb {Z}+r\subseteq \{n\in \mathbb {Z}:n-A\in \mathcal {F}\}$ , so $\{n\in \mathbb {Z}:n-A\in \mathcal {F}\}\in \mathcal {F}$ , which means that $A\in \mathcal {F}-\mathcal {F}$ .⊣

Let us also note, regarding the lemma above, that $\mathcal {F}=_{\sim }\mathcal {G}$ is not enough to conclude that $\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}\in MAX$ . By Theorem 2.8 there are $\mathcal {F},\ \mathcal {G}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ and $m\in \mathbb {N}$ such that $\mathcal {F}=_{\sim }\mathcal {G}$ but $\mathcal {F}\not \equiv _{m}\mathcal {G}$ , say $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{m}r_{1}$ and $\mathcal {G}\equiv _{m}r_{2}$ for some $r_{1}<m$ and $r_{2}<m$ . From Proposition 2.1 we get $\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}\equiv _{m} r_{1}-r_{2}\neq 0$ , so $m\nmid \mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}$ .

Definition 5.9. A family $\{\mathcal {F}_{i}:i\in I\}$ of ultrafilters is a complete residue system modulo $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ if it contains exactly one element of every equivalence class of strong congruence modulo $\mathcal {M}$ .

As an application of the above results, we have an ultrafilter version of a well-known theorem on complete residue systems in $\mathbb {Z}$ .

Theorem 5.10. If $\{\mathcal {F}_{i}:i\in I\}$ is a complete residue system modulo $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ then, for every $\mathcal {G}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ , $\{\mathcal {F}_{i}+\mathcal {G}:i\in I\}$ and $\{\mathcal {G}+\mathcal {F}_{i}:i\in I\}$ are complete residue systems modulo $\mathcal {M}$ .

Proof We need to show that in $\mathcal {R}=\{\mathcal {F}_{i}+\mathcal {G}:i\in I\}$ no two ultrafilters are congruent modulo $\mathcal {M}$ , and that each congruence class has a representative in $\mathcal {R}$ .

First assume $\mathcal {F}_{i}+\mathcal {G}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {F}_{j}+\mathcal {G}$ for some $i,j\in I$ , $i\neq j$ . By Theorem 5.7 $\mathcal {F}_{i}+\mathcal {G}-\mathcal {G}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {F}_{j}+\mathcal {G}-\mathcal {G}$ . By Lemma 5.8 $\mathcal {F}_{i}=\mathcal {F}_{i}+0\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {F}_{i}+\mathcal {G}-\mathcal {G}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {F}_{j}+\mathcal {G}-\mathcal {G}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {F}_{j}$ , a contradiction.

Now let $\mathcal {H}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ be arbitrary. There is $i\in I$ such that $\mathcal {F}_{i}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {H}-\mathcal {G}$ . Using Theorem 5.7 and Lemma 5.8 again we get $\mathcal {F}_{i}+\mathcal {G}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {H}-\mathcal {G}+\mathcal {G}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {H}$ .

The proof that $\{\mathcal {G}+\mathcal {F}_{i}:i\in I\}$ is a complete residue system modulo $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ is analogous. ⊣

6 Strong divisibility

It is natural to ask: which ultrafilters are strongly congruent to zero modulo some $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ ? Are those exactly the ultrafilters divisible by $\mathcal {M}$ ? For example, we saw in Lemma 5.8 that $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ -maximal ultrafilters are always strongly congruent to zero. In general, the above question leads us to the following definition.

Definition 6.1. Let $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ and $\mathcal {F}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ . $\mathcal {F}$ is strongly divisible by $\mathcal {M}$ if, in every $\omega $ -hyperenlargement,

$$ \begin{align*}(\forall m\in\mu_{1}(\mathcal{M}))(\exists x\in\mu(\mathcal{F}))m\mid{{{\hspace{-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace{-0.5mm}x}.\end{align*} $$

We write $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}$ .

In the same way as Lemma 5.4, we get a seemingly stronger condition.

Lemma 6.2. $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}$ implies that in every $\omega $ -hyperenlargement

$$ \begin{align*}(\forall m\in\mu_{1}(\mathcal{M}))(\forall x\in\mu(\mathcal{F}))m\mid{{{\hspace{-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace{-0.5mm}x}.\end{align*} $$

Proposition 3.2 easily implies the following.

Lemma 6.3. For all $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ and $\mathcal {F}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ , $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}$ implies $\mathcal {M}\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}\mathcal {F}$ .

It is tempting to try to prove the reverse implication; unfortunately this is not true, as we will now see.

Lemma 6.4. No $\mathbb {N}$ -free ultrafilter has any $\mid ^{s}$ -divisors.

Proof Assume the opposite, that an $\mathbb {N}$ -free ultrafilter $\mathcal {F}$ is $\mid ^{s}$ -divisible by some $\mathcal {G}$ . Then $\mathcal {G}$ is also $\mathbb {N}$ -free, and for any $x\in \mu (\mathcal {F})$ holds $(\forall m\in \mathbb {N})m\nmid x$ . By Transfer $(\forall m\in {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}\mathbb {N}})m\nmid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}$ , a contradiction with $\mathcal {G}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}$ . ⊣

Thus, this notion of divisibility is too strong to be our main divisibility relation, but it has some properties that are in good accordance with the strong congruence relation and operations on $\beta \mathbb {N}$ .

Lemma 6.4 also says that $\mid ^{s}$ is not reflexive: $\mathbb {N}$ -free ultrafilters are not divisible by themselves. It is, however, transitive: let $\mathcal {F}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {G}$ and $\mathcal {G}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {H}$ . Let $x\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {F})$ , $y\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {G})$ and $z\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {H})$ be arbitrary. Then $x\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}$ and $y\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}z}$ . Hence ${{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}z}}$ , so $x\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}z}}$ , which suffices for $\mathcal {F}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {H}$ .

Lemma 6.5. $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {G}$ if and only if $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}$ .

Proof ( $\Rightarrow $ ) Let $m\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {M})$ be arbitrary and let $x\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {F})$ and $y\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {G})$ be such that $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}$ . By Proposition 3.7, $v(y)=v({{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y})$ so, by Lemma 5.2, $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}}$ . It follows that $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}}$ , i.e., $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}(}x-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y})$ . On the other hand, since $-y\in \mu (-\mathcal {G})$ , by Lemma 3.8 and Proposition 3.9, $x-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}=x+{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}(}-y)\in \mu (\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G})$ , so $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G}$ .

( $\Leftarrow $ ) Let $m\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {M})$ , $x\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {F})$ and $y\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {G})$ be arbitrary. Then $x-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}\in \mu (\mathcal {F}-\mathcal {G})$ so, by Lemma 6.2, $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}(}x-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y})$ . By Lemma 5.2 again we have $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}}$ , so $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}-{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}$ , meaning that $\mathcal {F}\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}^{s}\mathcal {G}$ . ⊣

Theorem 6.6. Let $\mathcal {M}\in \beta \mathbb {N}$ and $\mathcal {F},\mathcal {G}\in \beta \mathbb {Z}$ .

  1. (a) $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}$ and $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {G}$ imply $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}+\mathcal {G}$ ;

  2. (b) $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}$ implies $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}\cdot \mathcal {G}$ ; and

  3. (c) $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {G}$ implies $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}\cdot \mathcal {G}$ .

Proof Let $m\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {M})$ , $x\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {F})$ and $y\in \mu _{1}(\mathcal {G})$ .

  1. (a) By assumptions $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}$ and $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}}$ . Hence $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}(}x+{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y})$ , and therefore $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}+\mathcal {G}$ .

  2. (b) Now we have $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}$ , which suffices for $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}}$ i.e. $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}(}x{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y})$ , so $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}\cdot \mathcal {G}$ .

  3. (c) By Lemma 6.2 $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {G}$ implies $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}}$ , so again $m\mid {{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}x}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-0.5mm}y}}$ and $\mathcal {M}\mid ^{s}\mathcal {F}\cdot \mathcal {G}$ .⊣

Let us remind ourselves of the definitions of other three divisibility relations from [Reference Šobot11]:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{G}\mid_{L}\mathcal{F} &\ \mbox{iff}\ (\exists\mathcal{H}\in\beta \mathbb{N})\mathcal{F}=\mathcal{H}\cdot\mathcal{G},\\ \mathcal{G}\mid_{R}\mathcal{F} &\ \mbox{iff}\ (\exists\mathcal{H}\in\beta \mathbb{N})\mathcal{F}=\mathcal{G}\cdot\mathcal{H},\\ \mathcal{G}\mid_{M}\mathcal{F} &\ \mbox{iff}\ (\exists\mathcal{H}_{1},\mathcal{H}_{2}\in\beta \mathbb{N})\mathcal{F}=\mathcal{H}_{1}\cdot\mathcal{G}\cdot\mathcal{H}_{2}. \end{align*} $$

What is the place of $\mid ^{s}$ (restricted to $\beta \mathbb {N}\times \beta \mathbb {N}$ ) among these relations? Like all the others, its restriction to $\mathbb {N}\times \mathbb {N}$ is just the usual divisibility relation (Lemma 5.5). We already saw that $\mid ^{s}\subset \hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ . We will show that this is the only inclusion that can be established:

First, why $\mid _{L}\not \subseteq \mid ^{s}$ ? Let $\mathcal {P},\mathcal {Q}\in \beta \mathbb {N}\setminus \mathbb {N}$ be $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }$ -prime and let $\mathcal {F}=\mathcal {P}\cdot \mathcal {Q}$ . Then $\mathcal {Q}\mid _{L}\mathcal {F}$ but, by Lemma 6.4, $\mathcal {Q}\nmid^{\hspace{1pt}s}\mathcal {F}$ . Analogously we conclude that $\mid _{R}\not \subseteq \mid ^{s}$ .

That $\mid ^{s}\subseteq \mid _{M}$ does not hold either can be seen by considering maximal classes of these two orders. By [Reference Šobot13], Theorem 4.1, the $\mid _{M}$ -maximal ultrafilters are exactly those in the smallest ideal $K(\beta \mathbb {N},\cdot )$ . On the other hand, the class of $\mid ^{s}$ -maximal ultrafilters is exactly $MAX$ by Lemmas 5.8 and 6.3. But $MAX$ is a proper superset of $K(\beta \mathbb {N},\cdot )$ ; we postpone the detailed examination of this and other aspects of maximal ultrafilters until a projected sequel to this paper.

7 Final remarks and questions

Even after finding, in §4, several equivalent conditions for $\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}$ , we were not able to answer the following.

Question 7.1. Is $\equiv _{\mathcal {M}}$ an equivalence relation?

Not being able to prove that it is presents a big drawback for using this relation, which seems to be the most natural extension of the congruence relation to $\beta \mathbb {N}$ .

Some more properties of our relations could be proved if we worked with $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -saturated nonstandard extensions. This is a stronger condition than being a $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement: $(V(Y),*)$ is $\kappa $ -saturated if every family F of internal sets in $V(Y)$ with the finite intersection property such that $|F|<\kappa $ has nonempty intersection. To Proposition 3.2 one can add two more equivalent conditions (see [Reference Šobot14], Theorem 3.4):

  1. (i) In every $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -saturated extension $V(Y)$ , for every $x\in \mu (\mathcal {F})$ there is $y\in \mu (\mathcal {G})$ such that $x{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-1mm}\mid } y$ ;

  2. (ii) In every $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -saturated extension $V(Y)$ , for every $y\in \mu (\mathcal {G})$ there is $x\in \mu (\mathcal {F})$ such that $x{{{\hspace {-0.0001pt}}}^{*}\hspace {-1mm}\mid } y$ .

However, Proposition 3.4 does not hold for $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -saturation in place of $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -enlargement: see [Reference Luperi Baglini7], page 74. So to use the equivalents (iv) and (v) we would have to answer the following question.

Question 7.2. Is it possible to construct a $\mathfrak{c}^+$ -saturated $\omega $ -hyperextension of $\mathbb {Z}$ ?

Acknowledgments

The author acknowledges financial support of the Science Fund of the Republic of Serbia (call PROMIS, project CLOUDS, grant no. 6062228) and Ministry of Education, Science and Technological Development of the Republic of Serbia (grant no. 451-03-68/2020-14/200125).

The author wishes to thank the referee for careful reading of the manuscript.

References

REFERENCES

Benci, V., A construction of a nonstandard universe , Advances in Dynamical Systems and Quantum Physics , World Scientific Publishing, River Edge, NJ, 1995, pp. 1121.Google Scholar
Burton, D. M., Elementary Number Theory , second ed., W. C. Brown Publishers, Dubuque, IA, 1989.Google Scholar
Di Nasso, M., Hypernatural numbers as ultrafilters , Nonstandard Analysis for the Working Mathematician , Springer, Dordrecht, 2015, pp. 443474.10.1007/978-94-017-7327-0_11CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldblatt, R., Lectures on the Hyperreals. An Introduction to Nonstandard Analysis , volume 188 Graduate Texts in Mathematics, vol. 188, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1998.Google Scholar
Goranko, V., Filter and ultrafilter extensions of structures: universal algebraic aspects, Technical report, School of Mathematics, University of the Witwatersrand, 2007.Google Scholar
Hindman, N. and Strauss, D., Algebra in the Stone-Čech Compactification, Theory and Applications. Second revised and extended edition, De Gruyter Textbook. Walter de Gruyter & Co., Berlin, 2012.Google Scholar
Luperi Baglini, L., Hyperintegers and nonstandard techniques in combinatorics of numbers, PhD thesis, University of Siena, 2012.Google Scholar
Ng, S. A. and Render, H., The Puritz order and its relationship to the Rudin-Keisler order, Reuniting the Antipodes—Constructive and Nonstandard Views of the Continuum, Synthese Lib. Kluwer Academic Publishers, vol. 306, Dordrecht, 2001, pp. 157166.10.1007/978-94-015-9757-9_14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Puritz, C., Ultrafilters and standard functions in non-standard arithmetic. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, vol. 3 (1971), no. 22, pp. 705733.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Puritz, C., Skies, constellations and monads, Contributions to Non-Standard Analysis (Sympos., Oberwolfach, 1970). Studies in Logic and Foundations of Math, vol. 69, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1972, pp. 215243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Šobot, B., Divisibility in the Stone-Čech compactification. Reports on Mathematical Logic (2015), no. 50, pp. 5366.Google Scholar
Šobot, B., Divisibility in $\,\beta N$ and *N . Reports on Mathematical Logic (2019), no. 54, pp. 6582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Šobot, B., Divisibility orders in $\ \beta \mathbb{N}$ . Publications de l'Institut Mathématique (Beograd) (N.S.) , vol. 107(2020), no. 121, pp. 3744.Google Scholar
Šobot, B., More about divisibility in $\ \beta N$ . Mathematical Logic Quarterly (2021).10.1002/malq.201900071CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Šobot, B., $\hspace {1mm}\widetilde {\mid }\hspace {1mm}$ divisibility of ultrafilters . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 172 (2021), no. 1.Google Scholar