We thank all authors for the six commentaries on ‘Depression: Why Drugs and Electricity are not the Answer’ (Read & Moncrieff, Reference Read and Moncrieff2022). We are sorry we cannot address all their points in the space available.
Pariante quotes from Hippocrates: ‘from the brain and from the brain only arise our pleasures, joys, laughter and jests as well as our sorrows, pains, grieves and tears’ (Hippocrates goes on to suggest that madness arises from excessive ‘moistness’ of the brain). This biological reductionism is a contentious position that is central, with varying subtly, to the commentaries by Aftab et al., Meechan et al., Pariante, and Goldberg and Nasrallah, exemplified by the latter's description of depression as a ‘potentially fatal brain syndrome’.
Depression and antidepressants
We all share the natural inclination to try to help someone who is suffering, but messing about with the brain, using interventions whose effects we do not fully understand, and that have unproven benefits and well-established harms, is not consistent with the Hippocratic oath (a more valuable contribution).
Aftab et al. do not like ‘binaries’ but the fact is we make distinctions in life. For most people, it is self-evident that using drugs to treat diseases of the body is quite different from using them to modify unwanted emotions or behaviour.
While a fuller rebuttal to the reductionist position has been given elsewhere (Moncrieff, Reference Moncrieff2020a, Reference Moncrieff2020b), we agree that depression is ‘not one thing’. Although we are biological organisms with a large brain providing the capacity for rational thought and complex feelings, this does not mean we can understand human thought, emotion and behaviour in terms of the brain.
In exceptional cases, low mood is a consequence of somatic factors – such as an illness like hypothyroidisim, or various drugs. Yet, contrary to Goldberg & Nasrallah's assertions, there is no good evidence that ‘regular’ depression, however severe, originates from biological deficiencies. Although Genome-Wide Association studies show associations between depressive phenotypes and some gene loci, they predict only a tiny proportion of the variance in liability to the disorder (Wray et al., Reference Wray, Ripke, Mattheisen, Trzaskowski, Byrne and Abdellaoui2018). How they relate to the suggested pathophysiology of depression also remains uncertain, and the largest study of previously proposed candidate genes showed none had any association with depression, nor interaction with adverse life events (Border et al., Reference Border, Johnson, Evans, Smolen, Berley, Sullivan and Keller2019).
A systematic review and meta-analysis found no evidence that any proposed biomarker, including neuroimaging findings, neurotrophic factors, neurotransmitters or hormones, reliably predicted the onset or maintenance of depression (Kennis et al., Reference Kennis, Gerritsen, van Dalen, Williams, Cuijpers and Bockting2020). We suggest, therefore, that depression, even when severe, is not correctly thought of as an unwanted biological state or disease, but as one of the emotional reactions that we humans manifest as a consequence of our sophisticated evaluation of our circumstances and history. It is important that we distinguish these situations (Moncrieff, Reference Moncrieff2020a). On the one hand there is an impersonal biological process or disease, that needs to be treated (if possible); on the other, a fellow human being who needs understanding and support.
It is true that most medical treatments do not address the ‘underlying biological dysfunctions,’ yet they still act on the physiological mechanisms that produce symptoms (e.g. painkillers acting on pain pathways). Since no such mechanisms have been established for depression, the ‘outcome-centred model’ Aftab et al. describe amounts to giving brain-modifying chemicals without knowing what they are doing, simply because they change depression rating scales by a couple of points more than placebo. The ever-changing conjectures about how these foreign chemicals might actually be benefiting the brain (rather than harming it as we might plausibly expect) are not reassuring.
Pariente cites others who, recognising the inconsequential differences between antidepressants and placebo, proclaim that the measures are inadequate. While measuring depression as if it was a piece of string is clearly absurd (as Timimi points out in his commentary on our article), using the single depression item of the Hamilton scale is no more valid. In the cited study, the difference between antidepressants and placebo on this item was between one point, the criteria for which is ‘These feeling states indicated only on questioning’, and two points, defined as ‘These feeling states spontaneously reported verbally’. It is not obvious that having to be asked if one feels sad indicates a less severe state than volunteering this information spontaneously. It is also subject to publication bias since it is not the primary outcome.
Goldberg and Nasrallah consider that response rates provide evidence of the effects of antidepressants, but these derivative categorical measures have been shown to artificially inflate effects (Kirsch & Moncrieff, Reference Kirsch and Moncrieff2007).
Electroconvulsive therapy
Meechan et al., assert that ECT is highly effective, ignoring the fact that all 11 sham-ECT studies (average study size 37) were grossly flawed (Read & Bentall, Reference Read and Bentall2010; Read, Kirsch, & McGrath, Reference Read, Kirsch and McGrath2019). Five found no difference between ECT and ‘sham ECT’ during treatment. None found evidence that ECT outperforms placebo beyond the treatment period, or that it saves lives.
Most of the arguments of Meechan et al. were addressed in a paper (Read, Reference Read2022) identifying the many ‘errors, misrepresentations, omissions, inconsistencies and logical flaws’ in their previous attempt to dismiss these inconvenient truths, and to discredit the evidence that ECT causes memory loss, brain damage, cardiovascular events and, rarely, death. We have space here for only a few.
Repeatedly trying to undermine the two systematic reviews (Read & Bentall, Reference Read and Bentall2010; Read et al., Reference Read, Kirsch and McGrath2019) demonstrating the absence of robust evidence of efficacy, by wrongly calling them ‘narrative reviews’, is dishonest.
Meechan et al. attack these reviews because they ‘focus almost exclusively on older sham ECT (sECT) trials, going back to the 1980s’. Is it the reviewers' fault that ECT advocates have failed to conduct any such studies for 37 years? Meechan et al. repeat the old argument that this is because non placebo studies are more ‘ethical’. What other medical researchers argue that it is unethical to find out whether a treatment works because they can't withhold that treatment in a placebo study because they believe it works?
Meechan et al. again irresponsibly minimise mortality rates, memory loss and brain damage. For example, a crucial prospective study demonstrating significant memory loss after six months (Sackeim et al., Reference Sackeim, Prudic, Fuller, Keilp, Lavori and Olfson2007) is dismissed because it ‘included use of outmoded sine-wave ECT’ rather than the brief pulse method frequently used today. Meechan et al. conveniently omit, however, that Sackeim et al. compared sine wave and brief pulse and found no difference in the amount of damage to either anterograde and retrograde amnesia at six month follow up (although reaction time was more impaired by sine-wave). Meechan et al. wrongly describe the reduction in autobiographical memory after six months as ‘small’. Sackeim et al. however, reported the scores as ‘markedly below baseline values (t(251) = 21.1, p < 0.0001)’.
We are accused of ‘conflating cognitive test performance with brain damage’ when reporting the Sackeim study. What else should one call dysfunction of an organ caused by about ten electric shocks and convulsions, six months later?
Meechan et al.'s concerns about suicide studies and patient expectancy have been addressed elsewhere (Read, Reference Read2022; Read & Moncrieff, Reference Read and Moncrieff2022; Read et al., Reference Read, Kirsch and McGrath2019).
Pariante's critique rests solely on quoting a promotional piece from the Chair of the International Society for ECT, which, as usual, cites ECT response rates without acknowledging the necessity of placebo comparisons (Rasmussen, Reference Rasmussen2009; Read & Bentall, Reference Read and Bentall2010; Read et al., Reference Read, Kirsch and McGrath2019).
Goldberg and Nasrallah state only that ‘Meta-analyses of ECT for depression indicate large effect sizes’, with no mention of the poor quality and bias of those meta-analyses and the studies on which they relied (Read et al., Reference Read, Kirsch and McGrath2019). The meta-analysis they reference (UK ECT Review Group, 2003) actually found ‘limited randomised evidence on the efficacy of ECT in the specific subgroups of patients who are presently most likely to receive it’ and no evidence at all of efficacy beyond the end of treatment.
There is just not enough evidence of sustained, worthwhile benefit from ECT or antidepressants to justify exposing people to their many adverse effects. We mess with the brain at our peril.