Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T09:28:38.928Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Gender Transition: The Moral Meaning of Bodily and Social Presentation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Helen Watt*
Affiliation:
Anscombe Bioethics Centre, 17 Beaumont Street, Oxford, OX1 2NA, United Kingdom
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Medical and/or social gender transition need not involve denial of one's biological sex, but raises other taxing ethical issues. These range from sexual ethics issues narrowly understood to consideration of the claims of any spouse or children and indeed, of gender-discordant younger people who may follow one's example. As with intersex conditions, not all crossdressing or use of cross-sex hormones is excluded absolutely. Detransition, for example, could be rightly deferred for various reasons. However, as illustrated by the analogy of an infertile woman wanting to present as the pregnant mother of a child she plans to adopt, there is a significant social value in accurate bodily and other outward communication of one's actual/predominant sex (and occupancy of key allied roles).

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2019 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

‘Transgender’ is an umbrella term (one might say, a labelFootnote 1) describing a mismatch between one's personal sense of being male or female,Footnote 2 and one's birth sex and associated social gender which feel alien, at least to some degree. ‘Gender dysphoria’ refers to unease or distress at one's sexed body and/or social genderFootnote 3 and the discordance between this body/social gender and how one identifies internally.

It should be stressed that those who have transitioned medically will often not believe they are now, or have ever been, full biological members of the ‘target’ sex – as opposed to believing they now function for some/many purposes like members of that sex (and the associated gender). Transitioned people who may believe they have a form of intersex condition (the ‘brain sex’ model) may still accept that, like the vast majority of intersex people, they were born with a predominant biological sex which medical transition cannot change. That biological sex may indeed be acknowledged by the person as a persisting source of pain or unease. While the moral significance of a person's biological sex is something on which there is, of course, widespread disagreement, the fact of the biological sex – no less than the fact that the person feels alienated from that sex and/or the associated gender – need not be a matter of dispute.

Adoption analogy

The question then is: assuming that the person has a certain biological sex, and experiences a strong tendency to identify with the opposite sex and gender, what is the best way forward morally, in the first place for the person, but also for those around him or her?

In approaching the question whether medical and/or social transition might be morally right for oneself or another adult, the analogy has been given of adoption as something based on a biological reality – the relationship of genetic-cum-social parenthood – but which does not require any deception or illusion on the part of the adoptive parent. An adoptive mother, for example, while she is not the biological mother of her child – a fact she may have no wish to deny – is indeed a genuine mother of the child, and should not be otherwise described. It would be incorrect, as well as ill-mannered, to call her a ‘non-parent’, since for most practical purposes she is no less a parent than a genetic and/or gestational mother. In the same way (it is claimed) while there is a conceptual connection between the gender with which one identifies and the biological sex associated with that gender, for most or many purposes one can truthfully identify with the gender even in the absence of the associated biological sex.

This analogy, which has been made recently in this journal,Footnote 4 is ingenious but not, I believe, sufficiently close to the case of gender transition to be ultimately convincing. I will adapt the analogy below in a way I believe helps illustrate what I see as a strong moral onus against social transition, let alone transition via surgery and/or hormones.

Moral absolute or moral onus?

I should say at the outset that in making this case, I have absolutely no wish to deny the painful and debilitating nature of gender dysphoria for the real-world people who experience it through no choice of their own. The intense politicisation of this area and growing marginalisation of responses other than transition only make more acute the need to address carefully the individual situations of those affected by dysphoria. Nor do I wish to suggest – however troubling the powerful social forces favouring transition – that it is intrinsically wrong in all cases for someone, including someone with dysphoria, to dress in the clothes of the gender associated with the opposite sex, or even indeed to take cross-sex hormones.

After all, in considering these questions, we need to remember the situation of ‘intersex’ people as the term is normally understood ie those born with a disorder of sex development (DSD)Footnote 5 who, if raised in the opposite gender, may find it very difficult, at least in the short term, to transition to the gender associated with their true (predominant) biological sex. That biological sex may, after all, be a recent surprise for them: perhaps something only revealed when they go through a kind of puberty which they were not at all expecting. Intersex people are not the main subject of this paper, but do share some of the same dilemmas regarding identification or non-identification with one's biological sex and the associated social gender, including the choice to use or not use cross-sex hormones. While people with DSDs often have no desire to transition from the social gender in which they were raised, their own situation also raises questions regarding gender presentation, including to potential sexual/romantic partners, if such presentation does not accord with their predominant biological sex.

Returning to the main subject of this article: it is also helpful in exploring these issues to consider the case of a person who has already transitioned away from the gender associated with their biological sex as a means of dealing with dysphoria. Such a person, like the person with a DSD, may or may not be in a position immediately to transition (in this case, back) to the relevant gender, and away from a current gender not associated with their biological sex. Inspired perhaps by the growing numbers of detransitioned people sharing their experiences, some transitioned people may be seriously drawn to detransition but may nonetheless need to delay beginning or at least, slow down the pace of detransition for one or other practical reason. Clothes may need to be bought first, cross-sex hormones may need to be stepped down gradually to make this a better experience and/or detransitioning may need to be deferred until the person feels sufficiently confident and mentally prepared. Even if the person is in fairly good health mentally, and is confident about the general decision to detransition, a recent traumatic life event such as a bereavement might reasonably cause the person to delay detransitioning until a more opportune time.

Admittedly, for some, there may be specific sexual ethical reasons in favour of more urgent detransition: we might think of those wanting to avoid sexual involvement with (or fantasies concerning) same-sex partners or to avoid crossdressing with a self-directed sexual/romantic motive of the kind to which, controversially, some trans-identifying people testify.Footnote 6 In many other cases, however, it does not seem that, morally speaking, even if the person should eventually detransition, this absolutely needs to happen now. Even less does it seem that someone who is detransitioning gradually as regards dress and/or use of hormones is doing wrong by doing this in stages.

Nonetheless, I will argue that there is, at very least, a moral onus against continued crossdressing and use of cross-sex hormones even for motives apart from sexual/romantic motives of any kind. A person who has transitioned has, I believe, at least a prima facie responsibility to consider whether detransition in the short- or longer- term might perhaps be feasible for them. I will also argue that the choice to transition in the first place is rather more of an issue morally than is sometimes suggested – and not just because the dysphoria might in any case subside and/or be managed in less radical ways.

Modified adoption analogy

Let me propose a modification to the adoption analogy which I believe creates a closer analogy for medical and/or social gender transition as a treatment for dysphoria. Imagine a woman who wants to adopt a baby, but finds her infertility so painful psychologically that she wants to be treated in every possible way as if she were the baby's biological mother. She does not deny (at least to close friends and familyFootnote 7) that she is not in fact the biological mother, but both before and after she adopts she wants to give a very strong social impression that this is what she is. After all, she already feels like a biological mother – perhaps more so than does the real biological mother, she may say – as she waits for the child to be born, then ‘experiences’ the birth and takes the child home as her own.

Leading up to the adoption, the adoptive mother talks about her ‘due date’, wears maternity clothes and perhaps even takes medication to make her body more closely resemble that of a pregnant/labouring woman. After or just before the birth, following which (let's imagine) adoption papers will be signed immediately, she announces that she is in labour, leaves home with her overnight bag and checks as a patient into the relevant maternity ward. She then announces the birth when the adoption papers are signed, giving the time of the adoption as the time her child was born.

Note that this way of acting is not intrinsically morally objectionable – or not, at least, in every aspect. For example, it might be done – minus any lies – to protect the real biological mother and/or the baby in a society where ‘unauthorised’ pregnancies can result in serious harm to one or both. Yet although not intrinsically immoral, there would seem to be a fairly strong onus against this way of acting: it is not merely likely to lead to outright verbal falsehoods but itself ‘falsifies’ what should be a reliable social signFootnote 8 of something important: the gestation by, and birth of a child to, the woman who, as biological mother, has first responsibility for the child. Childbearing is too important, in regard to society's need to protect mothers and their role, and children and their well-being and sense of identity, for people to simulate childbearing without a sufficiently serious reason. Nor is this just a matter of deceiving people as to biological facts: even if the adoptive mother told everyone what was happening in reality – while continuing to look like a pregnant woman and speak of ‘my pregnancy’ – her language and behaviour would still involve a morally suspect ‘appropriation’ of words and appearances that do not belong to her.Footnote 9

Gender transition and social meaning

While pregnancy is, of course, in some ways sui generis, there are some obvious parallels here. Indeed, there is even some potential overlap, in that we can imagine such a scenario in the case of a male-to-female transsexual adoptive parent,Footnote 10 as well as an adoptive parent who is a biological female. But more generally: just as the appearance of a genuinely pregnant woman, and the social act of giving birth, are valuable in connecting biological children publicly to their mothers and (one hopes) their publicly-committed fathers,Footnote 11 so too, one's presentation as a gender concordant with one's biological sex has a valuable social meaning: the onus is against merely appearing to communicate the full meaning normally associated with that presentation.

There are some things it is important we know in interacting socially with each other. These include any close biological relationships in which we may stand to others, and the biological sex of potential marital/reproductive partners. Further, we need to identify potential maternal or paternal surrogates or role models: ‘grandmother’ or ‘grandfather’ or ‘uncle’ or ‘aunt’ figures or specific male or female supports such as female doulas. Note that these role-holders may not be sought for oneself, but for another in whose welfare we take a special interest: we may identify our child, for example, as needing a role model of his or her own sex and gender (perhaps due to the absence of a parent of that sex and gender who is able to take that role).

We do not, of course, identify these actual or potential role-holders by looking at their genitals – much less their internal gonads which are arguably most determinative of their biological sex.Footnote 12 Rather, it is normally through secondary sexual characteristics, plus clothes and behaviour, that people communicate, intentionally or otherwise, their biological sex to the world. Breasts, for example, do not merely have a nurturing function, but a communicative function: the reproductive-cum-social function of identifying the person who has them as a female. Just as a male peacock communicates through his tail, and a female peacock through her more discreet plumage, so human beings communicate what biological sex they are with their bodies, but also standardly their dress, hairstyle, jewellery and/or makeup. All that said, it is hard to stress too strongly the vast gulf between the primitive communications of peacocks and the rich and complex human communications (via bodily traits or social presentation) concerning actual or potential male or female biological and social roles.

Sexual stereotyping

Of course, there is, at the same time, a danger of putting too much stress on outward communication of biological sex: this can be positively harmful to those who are gender-atypical in some way. The person's very ability to accept his or her birth sex and gender may be threatened by too-rigid expectations of dress and behaviour in the playground and beyond. Although this paper is concerned with the situation of adults, it is worth noting that expectations of children that they be very ‘feminine’ or very ‘masculine’ are unfair to (among others) tomboys, or boys averse to rough and tumble play. Messages that such children are not ‘real’ girls or ‘real’ boys may be not only hurtful but damaging to their ability to identify fully with their own sexed bodies and the gender associated with them. A world in which such messages are suggested either maliciously in the playground, or by adults anxious to confirm a suspected transgender identity,Footnote 13 is not a world in which gender-atypical girls and boys have their interests truly respected.

All that said, it is hard to deny that there is a real value in dress, body shape and voice giving some kind of cue – if only a subtle cue – as to the biological sex to which the person belongs. After all, from the perspective of traditional sexual ethics, marriage and marital acts are founded on complementarity in reproductive terms, even if many marital acts, and some entire marriages, are infertile and result in no conceptions. Those who believe in the polarity or complementarity of marriage and marital sex, and want to date only those they see as morally available potential partners, will recognise that it is important to know with whom one is socialising and may become sexually interested.Footnote 14 Sexual attraction is often the result of social presentation: it is about how the person looks, sounds and acts, as opposed to being simply an immediate chemical effect of pheromones. Whatever the cue or cues, sexual attraction is biologically oriented at some level towards reproductive-type behaviour – of a kind that is, however, unavailable (in principle and not just in practice) if the person in focus is of the same biological sex. Moreover, even those who see no moral issue with same-sex marriage or same-sex relationships for other people may be averse themselves to dating those of the same sex, nor is it obvious that (as is sometimes suggested) this is sheer prejudice in the person concerned.

Turning to the area of role models, many will want role models of their own biological sex as well as social gender, whose experience of growing up and living as a male or female is not too diverse from their own. And many will want this for their children: perhaps especially parents of children who are struggling to accept their birth sex and gender may be looking for someone who can model for their child ways of living out that sex and gender which may not perhaps be typical but are nonetheless happy and successful. Again, such models may be sought even by those who do not object to transition for adults but are trying to circumvent for their children a lifelong rejection of their sexed bodies and reliance on hormones:Footnote 15 surely not an ‘equally good’ outcome for the child as the acceptance of birth sex and gender which so often follows childhood dysphoria.

Modesty and transparency

There is also the issue to consider of modesty and transparency: attitudes protecting respect for sexual matters generally. Other things being equal, one should know in front of whom one is discussing such issues as male or female puberty, menstruation, pregnancy, male or female sexual behaviour and so on.Footnote 16 Speech barriers can protect more important barriers, while in contrast, breaking speech and similar barriers can sexualise friendships, and in any case, seems presumptively unfair to those who have let their guard down under the impression that they are speaking to a biological peer.

Again, we need a caveat here: avoiding such social misperceptions is clearly not a moral absolute. After all, there have been many cases in history in which people have needed to dress as a member of the opposite sex for ‘external’ reasons – say, to avoid capture by enemies – where unavoidably, they have risked inappropriate confidences and perhaps even unwanted romantic overtures. So deception (which does not involve lying) as to sex and one's past history insofar as this reveals one's sex need not be absolutely avoided.Footnote 17

However, the onus is certainly against such deception – even if the transitioned person will often have felt deceptive, rightly or wrongly, when the dysphoria was initially concealed before transition.Footnote 18 And it is true that, rightly or wrongly, there are people, such as close friends and family, who may feel they should have been told sooner what their loved one was experiencing. However, a person's biological sex, as opposed to painful private feelings, concerns public roles and is something many of us expect to know about even casual friends, acquaintances and strangers - though there are certainly sometimes reasons why this expectation cannot be met. To give another maternal analogy: the fact one has a new baby is a public matter, concerning an important role, and the onus is against concealing it. It is far more a public matter than the fact that one has post-natal depression, and is perhaps struggling to see oneself in the role of mother at all.

When the transitioned person's biological sex is discovered, as it may be, relationships may be (not unnaturally) damaged – and this is not necessarily simply due to prejudice on others’ part. In the frank and insightful words of one detransitioned female to male commentator:

The simple, fair fact is that people become rightfully uncomfortable when another person tries to pass themselves off as something which they are not. Deception is a habit we learn well to identify as we live together in society.Footnote 19

Masking versus bodily miss-signaling

Real as are the moral questions raised by ‘masking’ sex with external aids like clothes and makeup, there is, I believe, significantly more of an onus against coopting the body itself to signal opposite-sex type characteristics via use of cross-sex hormones. The body, unlike clothes, is of course one's very self and it seems particularly unfortunate when the very thing that has the function of sending out a signal (a flat chest for a man, for example) is altered to send out exactly the opposite signal in order for one to ‘pass’ as a member of the other sex.Footnote 20 Those who value ‘reproductive’ functions in the sense concerned immediately with sex and pregnancy should also value the social function of such secondary sexual characteristics which is also ‘reproductive’ in the sense that it is the normal way of communicating one's sex to potential sexual partners. While rejection of the sexed body involved in using cross-sex hormones may not be as radical as that involved in sterilising surgery, communication of sex is still blocked here deliberately at the level of one's very bodily self.

Cross-sex hormones go beyond the ‘mere’ suppression of functions found in use of contraceptive drugs or even puberty blockersFootnote 21 (which is not to deny the serious ethical problems such suppressions normally raise). The aim with cross-sex hormones is to coopt one's very body to give out what is in reproductive terms a false message to others, as well as helping one avoid the painful experience of dysphoria by achieving a pleasing or reassuring effect. Body parts oriented to identifying the person as male or female, such as breasts or a male chest, are coopted and made to communicate something that, biologically, is not the case – however faithfully the change may express the person's psychological identification with the relevant sex and gender.Footnote 22 Returning to the analogy of the adoptive parent simulating pregnancy: there is even more of an onus against taking drugs to simulate pregnancy and labour than there is against simulating pregnancy and labour (in the context of real life, not theatre) by one's dress, gait and so on.

Dating and sexual/marital behaviour

Returning to sexual matters in the central sense of the word: on a traditional understanding, sexual union is of course very much a matter of reproductive-type behaviour. Unlike raising a child which does not always have a strong reproductive reference (children can be adopted and raised by two sisters, a brother and a sister and so on) heterosexual intercourse is biological in a highly sex-specific way. It is (or can be) a matter of forming a ‘reproductive-type’ bodily union with another person, hopefully within a ‘reproductive-type’ marital commitment which protects both any child conceived and the spouses themselves. This approach to sex and marriage has an explanation for the general feeling that marriages should be life-long and exclusive, and that sex, unlike non-sexual expressions of affection, should involve a reasonably high level of consent. The approach sets sex apart from non-sexual activities, in a way that many feel intuitively is right, but which accounts more fully for the wrongness of such phenomena as polygamy and paedophilia, giving deeper reasons against these than do standard, more fragmentary approaches to sexual ethics.

Many people following the Sexual Revolution will reject, if not, thankfully, the ban on polygamy and paedophilia, some elements of the unified approach offered by traditional sexual ethics. That includes many same-sex attracted and/or trans-identifying people, many of whom – in a world so firmly shaped by post-Revolution sexual politics – would argue they are morally free to form relationships with those of the opposite gender, even if they are of the same biological sex. Alternatively, trans-identifying people may identify as gay or lesbian in relation to those who are of the same gender, but not the same sex – claiming again that such gay and lesbian relationships, as they see them, are no less valid than any other.Footnote 23

Gender dysphoria is about sexual and reproductive parts of one's body, and the social roles associated with these. Although not everyone will be interested in a sexual relationship specifically, when we think about cross-sex hormones and, in particular, genital and other surgery, it is worth remembering that many will have sexual relationships in mind (the neo-vagina, for example, will often be intended for possible sexual performance and not merely for allaying feelings of dysphoriaFootnote 24). If there is indeed a problem with any sexual union that is not a true reproductive union (ie a ‘reproductive striving’Footnote 25 of the two linked bodies, however infertile in practice) then seeking to facilitate such a non-reproductive-type union will inevitably be a moral problem too. This is important to stress as it is easy just to focus on damage to the person's existing sex organs caused by sex reassignment surgery and/or long-time use of hormones: while such damage is certainly a serious moral issue (not dealt with in this paper) the construction of alternative sex organs is a serious moral issue also.

Gender-transition and parental/other modelling

It remains the case that some trans-identifying people will be sincerely uninterested, whether for moral or for other reasons, in enabling future sexual relationships following gender reassignment, being concerned merely with managing feelings of dysphoria in their everyday life. Even so, however, they will normally be attempting to communicate via their appearance something to others as well as perhaps to themselves, and the question still arises for the individual person whether they have enough justification for tacitly communicating a message that is not accurate, at least as regards their biological sex (bearing in mind that the person will often want to ‘pass’ as a member of that sex, not just the associated social gender).

Still, someone who accepts a traditional view of sexual ethics in regard to sexual behaviour, including same-sex behaviour, could nonetheless experience dysphoria to an extent that leads the person to transition, or at least to consider this very seriously. Such a person may consider that since they are not/will not be a member of the opposite sex following transition, they should not date members of their own sex: they may see biological sex as morally determinative for all romantic and sexual purposes. If the person is currently unmarried, they may plan not to marry at all, perhaps because they do not believe they fulfil the criteria for a valid marriage; irrespective of this, they may believe that (for example) cross-sex hormones and crossdressing are the only things likely to help significantly with their long-standing dysphoria. The question for them, as they try to discern the best way forward, may be whether there is a moral objection to transitioning (or staying transitioned) medically and/or socially, simply as a palliative measure.

What should someone in that situation do? As mentioned earlier, I am leaving aside very serious questions raised by surgery and indeed, the sterilising effects of long-term hormone use (bearing in mind that sterility may well be intended by those for whom fertility is itself a source of distressFootnote 26). These matters raise concerns regarding legitimate and illegitimate applications of the ‘principle of totality’ which will not be pursued in this paper. My concern here is more with the social implications of the use of surgery and/or hormones and/or social transitioning, those other important issues aside.

Transition: responsibilities of the person

When contemplating a possible transition in the future, one thing that needs to be seriously considered is the effect on others, beginning with the person's family. Some of those wishing to transition may be married (even if questions of validity may arise depending on when their strong dysphoria developed) and the rights and feelings of spouses must of course be taken very seriously indeed. Nor is it only a matter of spouses’ rights and feelings: often there will be children involved. Young children, in particular, do not have the cognitive sophistication to hold in mind that this person, their father, really is male but only looks female and wants to be called by a female name and pronouns. Witnessing trusted adults calling one's father by a female name and pronouns is not conducive to children developing a healthy sense of realism. How are children supposed to engage with reality when the adults they look to to help them interpret reality say X is Y and Y is X? Footnote 27

Fathers wanting to cross-dress or transition will or should be concerned to act as good role models for their children – perhaps especially their male children. A crossdressing father, let alone a medically transitioned father,Footnote 28 does not model masculinity in a way that is helpful to his sons, as one former crossdresser has explicitly noted.Footnote 29 These issues are all the more pertinent as some studies have found that married autogynephilic crossdressers are more likely than others to respond to alternative therapeutic approachesFootnote 30 to identifying as a woman or even crossdressing part-time.Footnote 31

Another serious concern is the need to be a good role model to young people generally, who are growing up in a world where their sense of masculine or feminine identity may be fragile, due to a combination of innate vulnerability and social contagion. The latter is an all-too-real phenomenon: in the words of a recent paper on ‘rapid onset gender dysphoria’ (ROGD) seen through the eyes of parents:

The elevated number of friends per friendship group who became transgender-identified, the pattern of cluster outbreaks of transgender-identification in these friendship groups, the substantial percentage of friendship groups where the majority of the members became transgender-identified, and the peer group dynamics observed all serve to support the plausibility of social and peer contagion for ROGD.Footnote 32

Teenagers can be influenced not just by members of their friendship group but by adults whom they like or admire. When a popular female coach came out as transgender, the same paper reports, not just one but four teenage girls announced that they were transgender themselves. In considering transition, a gender-dysphoric adult who recognises that teenagers (or at least, the great majority of teenagers) should deal in other ways with gender anxieties should carefully consider the risk of influencing such vulnerable young people who can and should remain in their birth gender.Footnote 33

Transition: responsibilities of others

Turning to those around the gender-dysphoric person, they too should ask themselves about the effect of endorsing/seeming to endorse transition – effects both on the person and on others which may arise from using preferred pronouns, for example. True, it is not intrinsically wrong to use pronouns that do not belong to a person's biological sex and the associated social gender (for one thing, this is something potentially appropriate for intersex people who may also be currently living in a gender not associated with their true biological sex). But friends and family should be concerned, not just with what is wrong intrinsically (ie, in all conceivable situations) but with what is wrong in practice, here and now. Very often there will be a strong risk of giving the message, to the transitioned person but also to others, that the person is a male or female not just in presentation but in all important respects. That is a message family and friends should be very reluctant to give, whether intentionally or otherwise.

Quite generally, it is common and reasonable practice when relating to those with painful vulnerabilities to try to avoid causing unnecessary pain. Gender dysphoria is certainly no exception, nor need avoiding triggers involve deliberately or even recklessly helping the person and others believe that for all important purposes, the person is the sex and gender they identify with or want to be. For one thing, merely helping the person avoid painful reminders of something that distresses them may be compatible with the person's attention not being drawn to the issue particularly, as they will then focus more on other things. That might be the case if pronouns are avoided altogether – though such avoidance may itself become distressingly obvious, of course, as time goes on.Footnote 34

It is important to have honesty in families in particular: while use of an opposite-sex pronoun is not exactly a lie (the gender-dysphoric person may realise all too well that it does not betoken agreement that the person is ‘really’ ie for all important purposes the desired sex and genderFootnote 35) such use may nonetheless fail wrongly to witness to reality as regards the person's sex and its continuing moral and social importance.Footnote 36 Moreover, forms of compliance like using opposite-sex pronouns can lead to deeper questions of complicity, as when a brother then proceeds to ask his sister to introduce him to her friends as her sister or girlfriend.Footnote 37

Just as there is an onus against helping someone simulate pregnancy and labour – even if this could be done morally for a sufficiently serious reason – in a somewhat similar way, there is an onus against using non-birth sex pronouns, even without any actual lies, which also needs a sufficiently serious reason. (As regards use of language, to choose not to refer to the adoptive mother in our earlier analogy as a ‘birth mother’ or ‘woman going into labour’, despite her strongly wanting this, and even in a situation where everyone knows that these terms are not being used literally, seems presumptively, at least, the right thing to do. That is rather different from avoiding as too upsetting any reference to the child's actual ‘birth mother’ or ‘biological mother’ – avoidance which may be not only kind and courteous but quite possibly morally required.)

It is worth remembering in any case that the social and medical transition that friends, family and others are being asked to support will not necessarily even decrease the person's distress in the long term. As one therapist comments, in an open letter to a teenager considering transition:

Those who identify as transgender can suffer from pangs of cognitive dissonance. This can often make the dysphoria worse. I have heard many stories from desisters and detransitioners that identifying as transgender made them feel worse, because they then had to deal with a constant tension around the fact that their body looked and acted differently than how they thought it should. This can invite obsessive, perseverative thinking, which can be draining and cause increased distress and anxiety. Adopting a belief that contradicts material reality can be a recipe for unhappiness, as we will likely feel the need to strive to become the thing we are not. This is part of the reason many wisdom traditions and psychotherapy schools direct us to cultivate acceptance of those things we cannot change.Footnote 38

In the words of someone who has since detransitioned:

“I was not living in truth, regardless of surgery, legal declaration, and proclamations of diversity, and tolerance.”Footnote 39

Even if not all who have already transitioned are similarly called to detransition, we should not be surprised by the growing list of those detransitioning even after many years living in the new gender and after radical and perhaps irreversible interventions. Such individuals now oppose too-ready recourse to self-labelling and transition as ways of dealing with dysphoria; and call for alternative approaches, whether therapeuticFootnote 40 or in terms of self-careFootnote 41, which are sometimes given short shrift in common ‘trans-narratives’ where the message often given is: transition or die.

Acceptance and external expression of biological sex the ideal

Accepting and even gratefully accepting one's sexed body, and trying to conform one's perceptions to that body (to the extent one focuses on it at allFootnote 42), must remain the ideal, bearing in mind that in traditional sexual ethics, biological sex may not be dismissed as ‘merely’ biological but is already fraught with marital meaning. Nor does acceptance of the transitioned person as a loved and valued person like anyone else require ignoring their biological sex which, in traditional sexual ethics, is alone relevant to issues such as choice of dating and marital partners.

A person's social male or female role should ideally ‘track’ his or her biological sex, which is important for social interactions of various kinds. In particular, biological sex is crucial to roles such as husband or wife (or potential husband or wife) and mother or father (or potential mother or father). The gender-dysphoric person may already have a spouse and children, on whom the effect of transitioning will not be trivial, and may indeed be devastatingly painful. Transition can give a false impression concerning the interchangeability of the sexes for sexual and not just for social purposes, even if the person is in fact celibate. Those who do not marry and have children can also have important roles in terms of biological sex and gender: son or daughter, brother or sister, uncle or aunt, good/bad male or female role model for those around them.

To repeat: none of this is to say that those who are currently living in a gender discordant from their true biological sex must cease and desist immediately, whatever their state of health or personal circumstances. Crossdressing and even use of hormones simply as a palliative measure to stave off anxiety and/or depression and/or suicidality is not an absolute moral wrong. Even those who may indeed be called to move (back) to the gender associated with their true biological sex are not necessarily called to do so immediately. If one is an intersex person who has only just learnt that one's biological sex is divergent from one's gender of rearing, one may surely be allowed some time to process this before reversing one's wardrobe and changing one's pronouns – even assuming that this is the best way forward.

Nonetheless, those who are mentally and physically able should, I would argue, make social expression of their biological sex an ultimate goal if they can, recognising the value in terms of key social roles of harmony between biological sex and social expression. And as regards initial medical and/or social transition, again, the effects on others will clearly need to be considered, including effects on young people who are not currently strongly dysphoric but are vulnerable to influence and example.

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Anthony McCarthy, David Jones, Gwen McCourt, John Berry, Norella Broderick, Andrew Sodergren and Ted Watt for their helpful comments on this paper.

References

1 Yarhouse, Mark A., Understanding Gender Dysphoria (Downer's Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 2015)Google Scholar. Yarhouse highlights different degrees of possible identification with feelings of dysphoria (“I am someone who experiences dysphoria”, “I am a transgender person”, “I am transgender”) and draws a distinction between seeing transgender experiences as “who” I am versus “how” I am. He also explores situations in which feelings of dysphoria are able to be minimised by the person, using the example of an icon on a computer which can take up the entire screen or can be reduced to a corner of the screen.

2 Or neither male nor female (this article does not address other identifications falling under the generic term transgender).

3 Sometimes a distinction is made between ‘sex dysphoria’ very much focussed on body parts and ‘gender dysphoria’ where the person may be content simply to transition socially, while continuing to have all the body parts associated with their biological sex.

4 David Jones, ‘Truth in transition? Gender identity and Catholic anthropology’, New Blackfriars, May 29, 2018, DOI:10.1111/nbfr.12380. See also Sophie Grace Chappell, ‘Transwomen and adoptive parents: an analogy’, Conscience and Consciousness, July 2018, https://conscienceandconsciousness.com/2018/07/ (and comment box below).

5 It is often clear to what sex the person with a DSD biologically belongs: real ambiguity is very rare. Moreover, in the words of John Di Camillo, “Biologically, sex is determined by reproductive role, which is understood most essentially in terms of the two gametes: sperm and ova. No intersex condition introduces a new type of gamete; in fact, most people with serious intersex conditions are infertile. There is no third biological sex.” Di Camillo, John A., ‘Gender Transitioning and Catholic Health Care’, National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 17.2 (2017), p. 215CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Lawrence, Anne A., ‘Becoming What We Love: autogynephilic transsexualism conceptualized as an expression of romantic love’, Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 50.4 (2007), pp. 506-520CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

7 If a woman considering adoption was experiencing an overwhelming desire to present herself as a pregnant/labouring woman, then this is something those close to her would even perhaps have a right to know (and they should respond sympathetically if she does confide in them).

8 Note that this is a different form of social ‘mis-signalling’ from gestational surrogacy, where a genuine pregnancy gives a false signal as to the genetic parentage and future parenting of the child (in that case, a false signal so serious as to contribute to the absolute moral wrong of beginning such a pregnancy). See Watt, Helen, The Ethics of Pregnancy, Abortion and Childbirth: Exploring Moral Choices in Childbearing (New York: Routledge, 2016)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 One former crossdresser, ‘Kerry’, uses strong words to describe what he sees as his own form of appropriation, going so far as to describe it as delusional:

“I wanted to be something I could never be and experience things that were not mine to know… It is hard to give up things we know and are comfortable with, but for me it was much worse to base my life upon a lie or an illusion […] I hurt a lot of people that I claimed to love […] chasing after something I could never really have.” ‘What Do You Really Want’, in Understanding Gender Confusion, ed. Denise Shick

(CreateSpace Independent Publishing Platform, 2014).

10 Conversely, a female-to-male transsexual person may of course identify as a father throughout pregnancy – see the accounts in Mullin, Amy, Reconceiving Pregnancy and Childcare: Ethics, Experience, and Reproductive Labour (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005), pp. 41-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 Watt, The Ethics of Pregnancy, Abortion and Childbirth.

12 See Austriaco, Nicanor, ‘The Specification of Sex/Gender in the Human Species: A Thomistic Analysis’, New Blackfriars 94.1054 (November, 2013), pp. 701-715CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Sexual organs have the function of uniting a man and woman both physically and emotionally in a way that is procreative in tendency if not always in effect. For that reason, gonads (that is, naturally-produced gonads) would seem to be better evidence than genitals of one's biological sex: gonads do not merely mature sex characteristics generally but also produce the gametes that provide the most basic raison-d'etre for sexual complementarity.

13 Lisa Selin Davis, “My daughter is not transgender. She's a tomboy.”, New York Times, April 18, 2017, https://www.nytimes.com/2017/04/18/opinion/my-daughter-is-not-transgender-shes-a-tomboy.html.

14 Of course, there will be other things it is helpful to know in this context: both things that should normally be public (whether the person is already married or has taken a vow of celibacy) and things a casual acquaintance would not necessarily have a right to know (whether the person is impotent, for example, or same-sex attracted).

15 Without downplaying potential biological influences and vulnerabilities involved in experiences of dysphoria, to say that social influences have no bearing at all on dysphoria and its intensity would be seriously misleading. Detransitioned adults will often stress precisely the social influences, as well as their own internal reactions to these, which led them to take the step of transitioning (for some examples, see Callahan, Carey Maria Catt, ‘Unheard Voices of Detransitioners’, in Brunskell-Evans, Heather and Moore, Michele, eds., Transgender Children and Young People: Born in Your Own Body (Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars, 2018), pp. 166-180Google Scholar, and the accounts on the website Detransition Info. Such influences are certainly noted by some parents of children with ‘rapid onset gender dysphoria’ – see Littman, Lisa, ‘Rapid-onset gender dysphoria in adolescents and young adults: A study of parental reports’, PLoS ONE 13(8) (2018)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0202330

16 Even when one does know, one may be inhibited in frankness in front of someone who is not the biological sex he or she appears, nor should one necessarily have to resolve one's own feelings of discomfort in favour of the feelings of the transitioned person, real as these feelings also are. The latter also applies to single sex spaces such as bathrooms where, besides psychological comfort more generally, the traditional rationale for such spaces partly relates to a wish to avoid ‘peeping Toms’ and more aggressive sexual predators. The vast majority of biological males are not sexual predators, but that does leave a small minority who are indeed a threat, including a small minority of biological males who identify as transgender, whether sincerely or to gain access to a target group. See Saunders, Kate, Bass, Christopher, ‘Gender reassignment: 5 years of referrals in Oxfordshire’, The Psychiatrist 35 (2011), pp. 325-327CrossRefGoogle Scholar, https://doi.org/10.1192/pb.bp.110.032664; Amanda Prestigiacomo, ‘Trans-Age: Pedophile Charged With Abusing 3 Girls Says He's A 9-Year-Old Trapped in Man's Body’, Daily Wire (January 26, 2018), https://www.dailywire.com/news/26380/trans-age-pedophile-charged-abusing-3-girls-says-amanda-prestigiacomo#; Jonathan van Maren ‘Male pedophile identifies as trans woman and victimizes children’, The Bridgehead, October 8, 2018, https://thebridgehead.ca/2018/10/08/male-pedophile-identifies-as-trans-woman-and-victimizes-children/.

17 By analogy, a person's attraction to his or her own sex need not of course be announced to every stranger or acquaintance – despite the fact that, if known, this might affect the willingness of interlocutors to make confidences in what they wrongly assume to be a reliably non-sexual same-sex environment.

18 “Hiding the fact that you're transgender is hard, in lots of ways. I hid it from absolutely everybody (often including myself) for 50 years, and from nearly everybody for 33 years. This gave me more or less permanent imposter syndrome; I was just waiting to be found out and disgraced. And, I felt, when it happened, it would serve me right.

This waiting-to-be-exposed mindset still comes naturally today. Almost always I felt that I was being dishonest, two-faced and deceptive with everybody around me. (Sometimes I was. But not as often as my brain was telling me.) I had to work full time to keep such a big thing hidden. Such work was both exhausting and profoundly dispiriting.” Sophie Grace Chappell, ‘Being Transgender and Transgender Being’, Therapy Today, April 2016, https://counsellingfoundation.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/11/Sophie-Grace-Chappell-Being-Transgengder-and-Transgender-Being.-Therapy-Today-p10.-April-2016-Vol.27-Issue-3..pdf, p. 12.

19 Violet Irene, combox comment at 7: 27 am, March 12, 2013, https://gendertrender.wordpress.com/2012/04/25/ftm-detransitioning-experience-quitting-t-and-getting-back-to-life-as-a-woman/

The same author comments at 12:10 am:

“The fantasy of “hangin with the bros” is just a fantasy, it can never really be real. Trust me when I say that I do completely understand what you mean and the appeal. Even if they think you are 100% bro (and this is HARD to achieve, often, they will suspect something is off with you but be too awkward/polite to say something, just saying) you will always know the truth, and no matter how hard you run and how far you travel, you will never be able to escape that truth. You will always know that you have something to hide, and you will always–like a woman born and raised–fear rape and know that it's a possible consequence of being discovered and exposed.”

Another detransitioned person, who has suffered from dysphoria both before and after transitioning and detransitioning, comments starkly:

“… better to live a painful true reality than to continue soul sacrificing agonizing destructive lie.”

TheLumious01, combox comment at https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=9L2jyEDwpEw&t=5shttps://www.youtube.com/watch?v=9L2jyEDwpEw&t=5shttps://www.youtube.com/watch?v=9L2jyEDwpEw&t=5s accessed January 17, 2018.

20 Admittedly, some visibly male features such as beard growth are quite standardly adapted by shaving – but in most cases, this has neither the motive nor the effect of enabling the man to ‘pass’ as a biological female.

21 Puberty blockers themselves when initially used ‘merely’ produce appearances, whatever the medical risks, of a kind compatible with a natural slight delay of puberty (as opposed to an opposite-sex appearance which, however, crossdressing may convincingly create). Nonetheless, puberty blockers if continued close off an important opportunity of learning from one's changing body to identify with same-sex peers. Unsurprisingly, children who have been put on puberty blockers rarely transition back to their birth gender.

22 Note that even far more controversial identifications with a group to which one does not belong biologically eg identifications as a young child or a member of a different ethnic group still express something real, ie the reality of one's wish to belong to the relevant group or even belief that one is in some sense a member of that group. Feelings really do exist, but so does the world ‘outside’ those feelings, including our own bodies and some aspects of our mental lives of which we ourselves may not be entirely aware.

23 Like the person with gender dysphoria, the same-sex attracted person has an atypical perception of some aspects of the world that may be very deep-seated (even if more fluid for many than is often assumed – see Diamond, LM and Rosky, CJ, ‘Scrutinizing Immutability: Research on Sexual Orientation and U.S. Legal Advocacy for Sexual Minorities’, Journal of Sex Research 53 (May-Jun, 2016), pp. 363-91CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; on sexual attraction changes following gender transition which are still more common, see Auer, Matthias K. et al., “Transgender Transitioning and Change of Self-Reported Sexual Orientation”, PLOS One (October 9, 2014)CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0110016). Sexual perceptions of the same-sex attracted person may resemble in some ways, if not reproduce, sexual perceptions of a heterosexually-attracted person of the opposite biological sex, just as more general perceptions of the dysphoric person may resemble in some ways, if not reproduce, perceptions of someone of the opposite biological sex. Like dysphoria, same-sex attraction may have biological as well as potential social contributing causes – a possibility which in neither case resolves the moral debate about the best way forward for the person.

24 Even facial feminisation surgery may be undertaken partly, at least, as a means to entering into relationships which may be non-heterosexual in the context of the person's biological sex. Interestingly, one study found that quality of life was improved for those who simply had facial feminisation surgery, and that there was no statistical difference between this group and those who had gender reassignment surgery. Ainsvvorth, Tiffiny A. and Spiegel, Jeffrey H., ‘Quality of life of individuals with and without facial feminization surgery or gender reassignment surgery’, Quality of Life Research 19 (September, 2010), pp. 1019-1024CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 Pruss, Alexander, One Body: An Essay on Christian Sexual Ethics (Notre Dame, IL: Notre Dame Studies in Ethics and Culture, 2012)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also McCarthy, Anthony, Ethical Sex: Sexual Choices and their Nature and Meaning (Notre Dame, IN: Fidelity Press, 2016)Google Scholar.

26 Permanent cessation of reproductive functioning may be, not merely foreseen but actually intended: a girl or woman with severe dysphoria may have a pregnancy phobia and actively desire sterility for that reason, whether such sterility is caused by a hysterectomy or by prolonged use of hormones.

27 I owe this point to Andrew Sodergren whose comment I have reproduced here near-verbatim.

28 Note that, in particular, a father who has transitioned surgically has rejected – in a far more radical way than a man who has had a vasectomy – the very powers which resulted in his children's existence: something that may be both hurtful and harmful for those children to contemplate.

29 Anonymous, ‘Cross-dressing and Christianity’, in Shick, Understanding Gender Confusion.

30 Having claimed that most gender-dysphoric adults “cannot, or will not, completely accept their given gender through psychological treatment” (emphasis added), the author of one study (himself very willing to support transition) notes that:

“One population in which the acceptance of natal gender and the cessation of cross-gender behavior appears to be a possibility is a subgroup of male cross-dressers with gender dysphoria… The most common motivation for giving up cross-dressing is the fear of losing their marriages, families, or other valued parts of their lives. Some of these individuals have been able to abandon cross-dressing completely and experience a decrease in, or cessation of, gender dysphoria by approaching their transvestism from the perspective of a paraphilia or sexual compulsion and using standard behavioral and cognitive interventions (e.g., covert sensitization or stimulus control techniques), psychotherapy, and couple therapy.” Carroll, R., ‘Gender dysphoria and transgender experiences’, in Leiblum, S.R., ed., Principles and Practice of Sex Therapy, 4th edn (New York: Guilford, 2007), p. 490Google Scholar.

The author goes on to discuss two cases (‘Angela’ and ‘Charles’) which seem very similar but are resolved very differently by the married autogynephilic client in question (he explains that these cases are composites of several cases to highlight common patterns and protect the confidentiality of clients). He comments frankly:

“What remains striking is how similar Angela and Charles were, yet how they pursued different goals and ended up with different outcomes. It remains unclear as to why some individuals with autogynephilia choose to make a gender transition (Angela), while others attempt to eradicate their cross-dressing and impulse to become female (Charles), and still others are content with part-time crossdressing.”

The following claim is also worth noting: “Autogynephilic transsexuals are significantly more likely to regret reassignment surgery or experience poor outcomes than are androphilic transsexuals. The reasons for the differences between these two groups remain unknown.” Ibid, p. 496. On therapeutic issues, see also footnote 40 below.

31 Covert crossdressing may be less likely to cause social contagion or to distress family members, but can still affect the person profoundly – not least because crossdressing can have an addictive, obsessive quality about it of which some crossdressers have spoken – both those who have ceased crossdressing (see ‘Anonymous’ and ‘Kerry’ in Shick, Understanding Gender Confusion, and Robert Wenman, interviewed in Sophia Lee, ‘Transgenders Warn Others about Their Crazy Decisions to Live a Lie’, April 11, 2017, https://crtxnews.com/transgenders-warn-others-crazy-decisions-live-lie/), and also those who have transitioned and remain transitioned (see again Chappell, ‘Being Transgender and Transgender Being’). The trans-identifying therapist Anne Lawrence (‘Becoming what we love’) talks of a ‘love’ and not just a ‘sex’ element of autogynephilic crossdressing which – like other romantic love – can lead the person to sacrifice huge parts of their life in the pursuit of this love.

32 Littman, ‘Rapid-onset gender dysphoria in adolescents and young adults: A study of parental reports’.

33 It may be objected that the transitioning adult could be a good role model for some young people, such as a young person whose dysphoria was so exceptionally severe and so resistant to other approaches that some form of transition really was the only effective palliative option. Even if we accept that a rare individual might be positively affected by the older person's transition, it is far more likely that those affected in practice would be gender-discordant and/or same-sex attracted young people who do not currently experience dysphoria to any/a great degree but are nonetheless highly vulnerable to social contagion.

Similar concerns regarding young people and social contagion may seem to apply to an intersex person transitioning – but there, an explanation in terms of the person's predominant biology is available and could in principle be given where appropriate. Intersex people who have not yet transitioned may not be risking social contagion to the same extent by living as members of the opposite biological sex - but may need to reveal their intersex status to some people, particularly friends who may become romantically interested in them, or more generally, friends who are close enough to need/deserve to know more about their lives.

34 Without deliberate collusion with the overall project of transitioning, with which one may strongly disagree, it may still be possible to avoid pronouns in favour of (say) ‘Fred's’ rather than ‘his’ or ‘hers’; similarly a manager wishing to prevent workplace conflicts might intimate that the issue of pronouns will be left to the good sense of employees and that if they wish to avoid the chosen pronoun this may be done simply by using the chosen name. As the example of intersex people shows us, it is in any event not absolutely wrong in every case to use a pronoun which does not reflect the person's biological sex and the gender associated with that sex. As with terms such as ‘Father’, ‘Mrs’ or ‘Professor’, use of preferred names and pronouns by those who ideally would prefer not to use them is not a lie and may sometimes be necessary to avoid risk of harm – harm of triggering the person and/or harm to oneself, such as legal or employment repercussions.

35 We might think here of legal situations such as ‘show trials’ where everyone present knows that the ‘confessions’ of political prisoners do not reflect reality in any way. Leaving aside cases of perjury and apostasy, would it necessarily be wrong to save oneself by ‘confessing’ where (because no-one would believe the assertions) there was no issue of deliberate deception by statements purporting to be truthful (any more than in theatrical representations)?

36 In the words of one parent, commenting on an article on the gender-critical website 4th Wave Now:

“Whether clothes and hairstyles are masculine or feminine — who cares! These are fashion choices based on stereotypes. Pronouns are not. Pronouns have meaning. Think about how difficult it will be for your daughter if she changes her mind. So if you agree to a nickname, so much easier to use a variation of her birthname, or an initial. I was convinced by the gender therapist to agree to my daughter's chosen name. Such a big mistake. Now, when she hears her birth name she freaks out. So my husband and I call her nothing but “sweetie” and “honey.” FightingToGetHerBackon July 8, 2018 at 9:42 pm, at https://4thwavenow.com/2018/06/07/why-i-supported-my-autistic-daughters-social-transition-to-a-man/comment-page-1/

In an earlier comment in the chain (July 5, 2018 at 1:57 pm), the same commentator advises:

“I agree with allowing any kind of gender non-conforming expression as long as it is not harmful (eg., hair, clothes). For name change, I would encourage the use of a nickname related to the legal name. IMO, a dramatic name change is like rewriting your personal history. Also, if your child (hopefully) desists, this makes going back much, much easier.”

37 Denise Shick, ‘Family Complications’, in Shick, Understanding Transgender Confusion.

38 Lisa Marchiano, ‘The project of a lifetime: A therapist's letter to a trans-identified teen’, 4th Wave Now, May 10, 2018, https://4thwavenow.com/2018/05/10/the-project-of-a-lifetime-a-therapists-letter-to-a-trans-identified-teen//.

39 Anonymous, ‘Making Mountains Out of Molehills’, at http://docs.wixstatic.com/ugd/8960cb_cc81b74cb79b4bca952c087cb059e9b3.pdf.

40 See eg Sasha Ayad, ‘How I work with ROGD Teens’, November 12, 2018, http://gdworkinggroup.org/2018/11/. Hacsi Horváth (‘The Theatre of the Body: A detransitioned epidemiologist examines suicidality, affirmation, and transgender identity’, December 19, 2018, https://4thwavenow.com/2018/12/19/the-theatre-of-the-body-a-detransitioned-epidemiologist-examines-suicidality-affirmation-and-transgender-identity/) notes the paucity of literature on ‘non-affirmative’ treatment of people with dysphoria, and particularly, the lack of trials using newer ‘transdiagnostic’ approaches such as cognitive behavioural therapy, dialectical behavioural therapy and mindfulness therapy. He comments that “GD is not sui generis… it is well within the spectrum of conditions efficaciously treated with transdiagnostic approaches.”

41 Desisting or detransitioning people report the role of stress in exacerbating experiences of dysphoria: see for example Carey Maria Catt Callahan:

“At 32 I thought, “I have to investigate the chance there's another way to approach these feelings besides making them my identity because I'm so close to killing myself on this path.” At 34 I think “Wow, these feelings that used to run my life have receded into red flags that alert me to when my daily anxiety levels have been too high for too long.” Callaghan, ‘Unheard Voices of Detransitioners’, p. 175.

Commenting on alternative ways of managing dysphoria, another detransitioned person asks:

“How can someone give informed consent to transition when they believe the only alternative is a miserable life eventually cut short by suicide? People who transition believing it's absolutely the only way they can ever experience any relief are people whose community and healthcare professionals have failed them. ‘Max’, Ibid, p. 176.

For an account by one gay-identifying man of how non-sexual male friendships helped him resolve his gender dysphoria, see Chad Felix Greene, ‘Gender Identity: Embracing My Masculinity’, https://mensmovement.com/gender-identity-embracing-masculinity/

42 A humorous cartoon on the website Detransition Info

https://detransinfo.tumblr.com/post/171457500190/redressalert-tehbewilderness-naamahdarling points out that no-one expects us to love our consciousness and that our bodies similarly are ‘us’ – we don't need to form a ‘relationship’ with something that is us. In the comment box, tehbewilderness remarks:

“This is excellent advice. Do not dissociate from your mind and body. If you have done so, please try to find your way back to being whole. Attempting to develop a relationship with your body and mind as though they are separate from you exacerbates the dissociation”.