Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T05:42:13.595Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Parmenides the Late Archaic Poet

from Part I - Prooimia

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 June 2022

Benjamin Folit-Weinberg
Affiliation:
University of Bristol

Summary

The previous chapter locates Parmenides in his physical and linguistic contexts; this chapter locates him in his poetic, intellectual, and cultural milieux. It argues that we need to understand Parmenides’ poem in light of the late archaic revolution in the way that Homer was conceptualized. This chapter examines the epistemological framework Parmenides inherits from Hesiod and Xenophanes in considering the nature of human enquiry; the way that other poets in the late archaic period make use of the newly emergent figure of Homer and the corpus of Homeric poetry, especially with respect to their claims to knowledge and their relationship to the Muses; and the ways that scholars have characterized developments between Homeric poetry and the poetry of the late archaic period. I show how Parmenides uses the resources this Homeric tradition offers to launch a multipronged response to the challenges set down by Hesiod and Xenophanes. These include: reinitiating contact with a Muse-like figure in the proem; the use of crossroads imagery to articulate fundamental distinctions; ceding the voice of the poem to the unnamed goddess; the use of argument; and the return to the privileged poetic form of epic dactylic hexameter.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

The mid- to late sixth century into which Parmenides was born was a time of profound changes that touched nearly every aspect of society, from poetry to politics, architecture to astronomy, economics to epistemology.Footnote 1 During this period and in the decades before it, new settlements, including Parmenides’ own Elea, continued to spring up all around the Mediterranean and Black Sea;Footnote 2 Persian encroachments across the Greek east scattered westward Ionian refugees and their cultural and intellectual traditions; the monumental Greek temple as we know it was coming into its own.Footnote 3 Prose was born;Footnote 4 so was the map; so, too, was (non-alloyed) money.Footnote 5 For the purposes of this chapter, however, one of the most important developments was the series of fundamental shifts that were playing out in the world of archaic poetry during this era, particularly concerning the social status and conceptualization of Homer. If sections 1.1 and 1.2 of the previous chapter located Parmenides in his physical environment and linguistic milieu, respectively, this chapter will in turn locate him in the world of late archaic poetry in which he worked.

Doing so yields three benefits. The first concerns Homer’s position of unparalleled cultural prominence and social prestige in Parmenides’ era. In recent decades, scholars have begun assembling a mosaic of evidence that suggests important changes during this time in how Homer and the poems attributed to him were conceptualized and how poets of the day interacted with him. By the late archaic period, thinking one’s social and aesthetic values, one’s views on the nature of knowledge and poetic craft through, against, or otherwise alongside Homer had become a widespread phenomenon. Moreover, when Parmenides was composing his poem, creative reappropriation of the Homeric poems was becoming an established habit. Just as we would miss something of deep importance were we to fail to appreciate the physical nature of the actual roads with which Parmenides and his audience would have been familiar, or were we to elide the semantic nuances of the road vocabulary that Parmenides makes central to his poem, so must we also grapple with how Parmenides fits into the dynamics that defined the relationship between late archaic poets and the epic poems they used and abused, adapted and critiqued. What, generally speaking, were other poets in Parmenides’ era doing?

Working and reworking Homer, and reworking Homer yet again. In this and subsequent chapters of this book, I unquestionably privilege Homer in my reading of Parmenides – perhaps, as scholars with other interpretative perspectives on Parmenides may argue, excessively so. But as scholars of late archaic poetry have recently demonstrated, and as I shall emphasize in this chapter, poets in the late archaic period accorded Homer a place of unusually exalted privliege. Accordingly, our understanding of Parmenides’ poem will benefit from incorporating the insights gained by recent scholarship on late archaic poetry generally, and the early reception of Homer more specifically. Put differently, my emphasis on reading Parmenides against Homer is simply a reflection of, and commensurate with, the level of cultural influence Homer had earned in Parmenides’ own time.Footnote 6

Second, resituating Parmenides in his time and place will open up new perspectives on the precise nature of Parmenides’ engagements with Homer. As so often when discussing both archaic Greek poetry and ‘the Presocratics’, what appears normal or exceptional often depends on how we narrativize and periodize the development of individual thinkers and patterns of thought, poets and poetic traditions, and alongside whom we do, or do not, place the poet or thinker in question. When Parmenides is viewed not as a successor to Thales, Anaximander, Anaximenes, or Xenophanes, nor as a predecessor to Zeno, Melissus, Empedocles, or Plato (and, eventually, Aristotle, the Stoics, the Cynics, and, ultimately, as is not uncommon, Russell and Wittgenstein, or Heidegger and Derrida), but rather alongside his late archaic companions in verse such as Ibycus, Simonides, and Pindar, we get a different picture of important features of his poem. This is particularly true concerning his use of dactylic hexameter, the dramatic scenario of his proem, his epistemological orientations and aims, and key words, phrases, and lines in his proem and the ‘Route to Truth’.

This brings us to the third, and most consequential, point. Relocating Parmenides in his poetic context will help us understand more precisely both the intellectual challenges he faced and the set of cultural and poetic resources he had at his disposal in facing them. Of central importance on this score is the extraordinary epistemological tumult of Parmenides’ era and the decades immediately preceding him. One key current in this epistemological fomentation is a poetic and intellectual tradition that runs from Hesiod by way of Xenophanes, two thinkers with whom scholars have often seen Parmenides engaging.Footnote 7 I shall thus begin this chapter by building on recent scholarship on this theme to outline the poetic and intellectual state of play that Parmenides would have inherited from these poet-thinkers, and the precise challenges their work would have presented him. Framing the discussion this way does not, however, mean we should understand this Hesiodic-Xenophanean line of thinking as disconnected from the conception of, and engagement with, Homer that seems to have played such an important role in the late archaic poetry of Parmenides’ peers and near-contemporaries; rather we must be prepared to see how these two stories intersect and are intertwined. Thus, having proceeded by way of other examples of late and mid- to late archaic engagements with Homer (especially in poems by Ibycus, Pindar, and Simonides) and the epistemological stakes at play in these engagements, I shall ultimately loop back to Parmenides’ place in the Hesiodic-Xenophanean tradition armed with fresh insights into Parmenides’ strategies for addressing the challenges this tradition presented.

To summarize: three strands of the backdrop to Parmenides must be examined. My argument in this chapter will be as follows. First, I shall set the stage by exploring the challenge to which Parmenides needed to respond and the larger epistemic framework within which he needed to work (in Section 2.1, ‘Hesiod’s Muses, Xenophanes’ Doubt’). Second, I shall look at the late archaic period’s interest in Homer, especially the Invocation of the Muses in Iliad 2, and the resources this provided Parmenides in meeting that challenge (in Section 2.2, ‘Archaic Receptions of Homer’). Third, I shall consider the larger epistemico-poetic milieu within which Parmenides would have been operating in order to appreciate more fully his response to the Hesiodic-Xenophanean tradition (in Section 2.3, ‘Poetics and Epistemology’). Finally, building on these three sections, I shall explore how Parmenides, finding himself in the situation described in the third section, deploys the resources explored in the second to overcome the challenge outlined in the first (in Section 2.4, ‘Parmenidean Strategies’).

2.1 Hesiod’s Muses, Xenophanes’ Doubt

The best way to establish the larger stakes at play in this chapter, then, is to consider Parmenides’ rather more well-established place in the poetic and intellectual tradition that begins with Hesiod and moves primarily by way of Xenophanes. Scholarship on this topic often centres on the infamous lines 27–28 of the Theogony. There the Olympian Muses, having withdrawn from their idyllic perch on ‘highest Helicon’ (Th. 25), quite literally condescend to address Hesiod while he tends his flocks in the human world below; underscoring his lowly status (Th. 26), they make the following declaration (Th. 27–28):

ἴδμεν ψεύδεα πολλὰ λέγειν ἐτύμοισιν ὁμοῖα,
ἴδμεν δ᾽, εὖτ᾽ ἐθέλωμεν, ἀληθέα γηρύσασθαι.
We know how to compose many lies indistinguishable from things that are real,
And we know, when we wish, to pronounce things that are true.

Shaul Tor’s recent study Mortal and Divine in Early Greek Epistemology can help us make sense of the bewildering implications of these lines and the reams of scholarship that they have justifiably provoked.Footnote 8 One of the virtues of Tor’s analysis is that it transcends the usual impasses – do Hesiod’s Muses lie to others but tell the truth to him, and, if so, does he gain knowledge from them? Do Hesiod’s Muses lie to him? Is there any way of knowing? – by reassessing the place of these lines in the Hesiodic corpus more generally. Seen from this perspective, Hesiod’s Muses are not staking out an epistemological position (that Hesiod’s Muses reject Homeric epic, for example, and authorize his own) but rather constructing an epistemological framework.Footnote 9 This framework is premised on the idea that only by interacting with the divine is Hesiod’s poetry possible, and can be broken down into three parts.Footnote 10 First (i) is the need to assess ‘what mortals and gods are like’, especially by attaining insight into the nature of ‘the epistemic capacities and limitations of mortals’; second (ii), as follows from the limitations of mortals established in the first point, ‘it is only through a special and privileged interaction with the divine that the mortal poet can produce potentially true (since divinely disclosed) accounts of matters that lie beyond human cognition’; finally (iii), ‘the mortal cannot know the truth-value of these accounts’.Footnote 11

There are two fundamental benefits to framing matters this way. First, of use both immediately and later in the chapter, this analysis allows for a concise comparison between the views of Hesiod, Xenophanes, and Parmenides.Footnote 12 Following Hesiod, both Xenophanes and Parmenides agree on the importance of point (i). Xenophanes, however, rejects the possibility of point (ii), denying that mortals (poets or otherwise) ‘can produce potentially true (since divinely disclosed) accounts of matters that lie beyond human cognition’; Xenophanes also develops a particularly strong and explicit version of point (iii).Footnote 13 This is an excellent starting point for discussing the intellectual state of play Parmenides would have inherited.

Second, of value at the end of this chapter, this perspective helps liberate us from the old dichotomy between rationality and irrationality, between reasoning and divine disclosure. More specifically, we would no longer need to see an incompatibility between the terms that form these traditional dichotomies: the reasoning in Parmenides’ poem may be intimately related to, and indeed perhaps made possible by, the fact that it is divinely disclosed.Footnote 14

Xenophanes’ rejection of point (ii) and development of point (iii) are particularly apparent in Fragment 34:Footnote 15

καὶ τὸ μὲν οὖν σαφὲς οὔτις ἀνὴρ ἴδεν ούδέ τις ἔσται
εἰδὼς ἀμφὶ θεῶν τε καὶ ἅσσα λέγω περὶ πάντων·
εἰ γὰρ καὶ τὰ μάλιστα τύχοι τετελεσμένον εἰπών,
αὐτὸς ὅμως οὐκ οἶδε· δόκος δ’ ἐπὶ πᾶσι τέτυκται.
And indeed that which is clear and certain truth no man has seen
Nor will there be anyone who knows about the gods and what I say about all things;
For even if, in the best case, someone happened to speak just of what has been fulfilled [someone chanced to say the complete truth],
Still he himself would not know; but opinion/belief is allotted to all.

As has often been remarked, it is precisely the kind of poetic inspiration described in Homer’s famous Invocation of the Muses in Iliad 2 that must be at least one of the main targets of Xenophanes’ critique;Footnote 16 whatever the ambiguity embedded in Hesiod’s own poetic or theological epistemology, Xenophanes declares the hotline (or, no less importantly, the perceived and socially accredited hotline) to the Muses definitively severed. Dokos, ‘opinion’ or ‘belief’, is the best that mortals ever get.Footnote 17

Considering matters from this perspective helps us more clearly take stock of the challenges facing Parmenides and the strategies he deploys to negotiate and overcome them, a question to which I shall return in the final movement of this chapter (‘Parmenidean Strategies’). We can now summarize Parmenides’ position vis-à-vis this strand of Hesiodic-Xenophanean thinking as follows. In the background stand two Hesiodic premises. Owing to the nature of god and man, truth (because divinely disclosed) can come only via an epistemically significant interaction with the divine; nevertheless, owing to the nature of mortals’ own limitations, they cannot be certain of the truth-value of the information they receive in this transaction with divinity. The view Parmenides would oppose is expressed by Xenophanes, who flatly denies the possibility of any unmediated disclosure from divinity, and forcefully underscores the inability of mortals to know the truth (as opposed to merely believing the claims at which they arrive in the course of their inquiries).Footnote 18

In short, and setting the stage for this chapter’s final section, meeting the challenge that Xenophanes set down thus involves (a) effecting an encounter with a Muse-like divinity, that she may disclose truth, and (b) finding a way to abolish any doubt as to whether what has been disclosed actually is the truth. I shall return below to Parmenides’ strategies for meeting these challenges; in order to understand these strategies, however, it will first be necessary to examine aspects of the archaic reception of Homer (in the next section, ‘Archaic Receptions of Homer’) and the larger epistemic and poetic context in which Parmenides was working (Section 2.3, ‘Poetics and Epistemology’).

2.2 Archaic Receptions of Homer

As discussed above, with the exception of Havelock and Mourelatos, scholars have often been reluctant to read Parmenides alongside Homer. It is precisely, however, in Parmenides’ time that a revolution occurs in the way that Homer is conceptualized and, more pertinently here, that Homer ascends to the dominant cultural position with which we now associate him; one might even say that it is in this time that Homer first becomes inescapable.Footnote 19 It is during this period that the name ‘Homeros’ first appears – not incidentally, in the mouths of critics like Xenophanes, who could proclaim that ἐξ ἀρχῆς καθ᾽ Ὅμηρον ἐπεὶ μεμαθήκασι πάντες (‘from the beginning, all have learned from Homer’, B10),Footnote 20 or Heraclitus, for whom τόν τε Ὅμηρον … ἄξιον ἐκ τῶν ἀγώνων ἐκβάλλεσθαι καὶ ῥαπίζεσθαι (‘Homer deserves to be kicked out of the agōnes and beaten with a stick’, B42).Footnote 21 They would in due course be followed by, among others, Simonides, Pindar, and Bacchylides, though these often took a less acerbic tone.Footnote 22 In the fragments of Stesichorus (like Parmenides, a western Greek),Footnote 23 scholars now detect a level of detailed interaction with the Iliad and the Odyssey qualitatively different from anything that had come before, and recherché enough in nature to suggest an intertextual engagement.Footnote 24 In the Hymn to Apollo, speculated by some to have been performed on Delos in 523/22 BCE,Footnote 25 we see in the notorious boast concerning ‘a blind man, living in rocky Chios, all of whose songs are the best among posterity’ (H.Ap. 172–73) the first surviving allusion to Homer as the ‘absolute classic’ he has been ever since.Footnote 26 The establishment of the Great Panathenaea and the institution of regular recitations of the Iliad and the Odyssey (also possibly in 522 BCE) has long been advanced as another seminal moment reflecting (or announcing) the canonicity of Homer, the stabilization of the Homeric text, or both.Footnote 27 Perhaps his first out-and-out literary critic, the allegorist Theagenes of Rhegium (a polis not far from Elea)Footnote 28 seems to date from around this time as well.Footnote 29

The tremendous impact of this shift on late archaic cultural production has been carefully examined in the last several decades. One particularly rich vein of this scholarship explores the relationship between Odysseus’ preamble to the Phaeacians at Od. 9.2–11, the so-called ‘Golden Verses’, and different kinds of late archaic poetry and thought, particularly in relation to the symposium.Footnote 30 This is not the place to delve into this scholarship, but a few of its key findings, which encompass a range of late archaic poets and thinkers including Xenophanes, Heraclitus, Simonides, Bacchylides, and Pindar, may be listed here. One is that addressing the question of ‘what is finest’ that Odysseus broaches in Od. 9.2–11 became central to the process of self-fashioning in sympotic poetry and its associated cultural milieu.Footnote 31 Another, notable in the context of Parmenides’ relationship to Homer, is that one strategy for answering this question successfully involved quoting, troping, recontextualizing, and reworking bits of the Homeric text.Footnote 32 Finally, this in turn reveals the enormous cultural prestige attached to the lines of Homer; as Andrew Ford’s discussion of the citation of Il. 6.146 in Simonides 19 (IEG) makes clear, these lines ‘draw their authority from being accepted as words said by Homer himself and not by another’.Footnote 33 In sum, this strand of scholarship gives us a window onto a cultural milieu where chunks of Homeric text were a kind of precious metal that could be collected, beaten into new forms, recast with one’s own visage imprinted on the front, and put into circulation anew. Homerizing, that is, was rampant in the late archaic period.

These well-known points are worth recapitulating here for two reasons. First, my argument in subsequent chapters relies on Parmenides’ dealing with something like the Odyssey that we have now. I say ‘like’ because the core of the analysis I shall undertake below does not ultimately hinge on word-by-word intertextual readings.Footnote 34 Nevertheless, there are many features shared by Parmenides’ poem and Homer’s text (particularly Odyssey 12, my main point of comparison in chapters 3–6) that do take place at the level of language; and since Parmenides, if he engaged with Homer’s Odyssey 12 word by word, line by line,Footnote 35 would have had to have done so with some version of the Odyssey, I shall not shy away from presuming an intertextual relationship between the two poems at times to bolster my case. It is therefore very helpful – though again, in the last analysis, not absolutely necessary – to proceed on the basis that the Odyssey 12 that Parmenides would have encountered closely resembled the one we have at our disposal today.Footnote 36

Second, that Homer was ascending to a place of unparalleled prestige in the late archaic era is a point that, as we have seen, has been severely underappreciated by scholars of Parmenides. Exploring what this widespread ‘Homerizing’ during the late archaic era meant for Parmenides’ contemporaries, and especially his fellow poets, will provide a crucial context for my own interpretation of Parmenides. With this background in mind, my next goal in this chapter will be to examine a specific example that demonstrates these dynamics at work in the late archaic era. In particular, a brief look at a series of receptions of Homer’s Invocation of the Muses from Iliad 12, in Ibycus’ so-called ‘Polycrates Ode’, Pindar’s Paean 6 and Paean 7b, and Simonides’ ‘Plataea Elegy’, will provide powerful evidence of the kind of detailed engagement with a Homeric text very much resembling our own that I think we should see in Parmenides’ poem (Section 2.2.1, ‘Invoking the Muse(s)’).Footnote 37 On the other hand, juxtaposing the overlaps between Solon’s so-called ‘Eunomia’ (3 G.-P.= 4 W2) and Homer and between Parmenides’ poem and Homer (Section 2.2.2, ‘Far from the Beaten Track of Men’), a brief digression from my larger argument, will also bring into sharp focus aspects of Parmenides’ poem that have often been acknowledged but are not always discussed at the length they deserve.

2.2.1 Invoking the Muse(s)

Ἔσπετε νῦν μοι Μοῦσαι Ὀλύμπια δώματ’ ἔχουσαι –
ὑμεῖς γὰρ θεαί ἐστε πάρεστέ τε ἴστέ τε πάντα,
ἡμεῖς δὲ κλέος οἶον ἀκούομεν οὐδέ τι ἴδμεν.
Tell me now, Muses, who dwell upon Olympus –
For you are goddesses, and are present and know everything,
While we hear only rumour, and know nothing.

So begins one of the most memorable and distinctive passages in the entire Homeric corpus, the Invocation of the Muses (Il. 2.484–93) that precedes the Catalogue of Ships (2.494–759).Footnote 38

Although it used to be commonly assumed that poets throughout the archaic period engaged with the Homeric poems in a detailed, textualized way, scholars now take a more cautious view regarding such early archaic poets as Archilochus, Mimnermus, and Alcman.Footnote 39 How best to assess the relationship between archaic poetry and Homeric epic remains one of the thornier problems occupying scholars of ancient Greek literature.Footnote 40 Even so, with Ibycus’ so-called ‘Polycrates Ode’, almost certain to have been written before Polycrates’ demise in 522 BCE (and perhaps dating from as early as c. 560 BCE),Footnote 41 even sceptical scholars have found firmer ground upon which to posit an intertextual engagement with Homer.Footnote 42 The Invocation of the Muses and Catalogue of Ships in Iliad 2 are widely agreed to be a major point of reference;Footnote 43 one finds Homeric resonances that run the gamut from Ibycus’ use of particles to his compressed treatment of the Catalogue of Ships.Footnote 44 Most pertinently here, as in the Invocation of the Muses, Ibycus juxtaposes the limited capabilities of the mortal poet to the superior powers of the Muses.Footnote 45

Similarly, Pindar’s Paean 6.50–61 and Paean 7b.10–20 seem to interact closely with the Iliad’s Invocation of the Muses.Footnote 46 Here Pindar, too, mirrors specific features of the Invocation’s phraseology and grammar, especially in Paean 6.54–57.Footnote 47 More notably here, in contrast to the omniscience attributed to the Muses, mortal men are in both cases expressly characterized by their fundamentally limited epistemic status.Footnote 48 As Pindar puts it (Pae. 6.51–53):Footnote 49

  … ταῦτα θεοῖσι [μ]ὲν
πιθεῖν σοφοὺ̣[ς] δυνατόν,
βροτοῖσιν δ’ ἀμάχανο[νεὑ]ρέμεν…
  … It is possible for the gods
To persuade wise men of these things,
But for mortals there is no means to discover them…

Similar dynamics define the scenario in Paean 7b.15–20.Footnote 50

Scholars have also found much in Simonides’ so-called ‘Plataea Elegy’ that echoes the Invocation of the Muses and the Catalogue of Ships, especially in different aspects of its apparent sequence and structure.Footnote 51 Most saliently for the present discussion, much of the oblique reference to Homer in lines 15–18 seems to be a summary of the Invocation of the Muses (15–17):Footnote 52

οἷσιν ἔπ’ ἀθά]ν̣ατον κέχυται κλέος ἀν̣[δρὸς] ἕκητι
   ὃς παρ’ ἰοπ]λοκάμων δέξατο Πιερίδ[ων
πᾶσαν ἀλη]θείην.
On them [sc. ‘the Danaan leaders in battle’ (14)] immortal kleos has been poured by the will of a man
Who received from the violet-tressed Pierians
The entire truth.

The foregoing cases, however briefly sketched, provide a programmatic set of examples supporting the view that in the late archaic period, poets working across a range of genres, from elegy to epinician to the paean, were engaged in a deep and fine-grained way with what seems to be a fixed text of Homer that resembled our own. More specifically, Iliad 2’s Invocation of the Muses, one of the very few places in Homer where the poet/narrator does identify himself (or herself) in the first person and speak directly in his (or her) own voice, seems to have been an object of unusual fascination for poets in this period.Footnote 53 We shall return to this point in the final section of this chapter (‘Parmenidean Strategies’).

2.2.2 Far from the Beaten Track of Men

First, however, it will be beneficial to entertain a brief digression contrasting Parmenides’ relationship to Homer with that of Solon’s so-called ‘Eunomia’ (3 G.-P.2 = 4 W2) to Od. 9.2–11. Most pertinent are lines 7–10:Footnote 54

δήμου θ᾽ ἡγεμόνων ἄδικος νόος, οἷσιν ἑτοῖμον
   ὕβριος ἐκ μεγάλης ἄλγεα πολλὰ παθεῖν·
οὐ γὰρ ἐπίστανται κατέχειν κόρον οὐδὲ παρούσας
   εὐφροσύνας κοσμεῖν δαιτὸς ἐν ἡσυχίηι.
And unjust is the noosFootnote 55 of the leaders of the dēmos, and they are certain
   To suffer many woes from their great hybris:
For they do not know how to restrain excess, nor
   To conduct in an orderly and peaceful manner the festivities
      of the banquet at hand.

It is not possible to pin down the precise relationship between Solon’s poem and the Odyssey with much confidence.Footnote 56 Be that as it may, the breadth and depth of this poem’s parallels with Od. 9.2–11 justify its inclusion in this discussion, as does the striking way this handful of lines presents many of the paradigmatic items of vocabulary and concerns of elegiac poetry.Footnote 57 As Odysseus establishes links between euphrosynē (Od. 9.6), the dēmos (Od. 9.6), and the orderliness of the banqueters (hēmenoi hekseiēs, Od. 9.8), so Solon’s poem links these elements in their absence from the disorderly city (cf. ll. 9–10).Footnote 58 In both cases, the feast and feast-like setting of the symposium frame reflections on man’s place in the world in respect to material abundance, good governance, society at large, and the question of justice more broadly.Footnote 59

In this, the relationship between these portions of the Odyssey and Solon’s ‘Eunomia’ (however we should understand it) provides a striking point of contrast with Parmenides. Too often, perhaps, we are in a hurry to pinpoint – or litigate – connections between passages of archaic poetry and Homer, rather than considering which specific portions of Homer may be connected to these passages – and, most importantly, why.

The similarities between Odysseus’ observations at the well-laid table of Alcinous and its negative image in the perverted feasts of the suitors and the disorderly tables of Solon’s city in turmoil are in every sense a world apart from Parmenides’ poem. This also suggests an important contrast between Parmenides’ poem and the genre of elegy of which Solon’s is so fine a specimen. With the heroic feast and the institution of the symposium, we arrive at the heart of archaic sites of reflection on well-ordered forms of human society and right relations between men. Unlike epic, elegy takes place not in the distant past of heroes but in the time of men; a common topic is the history of the symposiasts’ polis, and recounting this in the elite, aristocratic setting of the symposium consolidates a shared class identity by emphasizing the basis on which it is asserted.

One could hardly think of a topic or set of concerns more remote from Parmenides’ sphere of interest. His poem is precisely not grounded in the time of men; unlike elegiac poetry, its theme has precisely nothing to with the common past of any specific class, or any particular polis, its history, foundation myths and common heroes, or collective identity.Footnote 60 In fact, a considerable portion of the proem’s labours are dedicated to distinguishing the nature and context of the poem as emphatically as possible from the world of men in which the civically oriented poetry of the sympotic or ‘historical’ elegists is embedded. If the city is mentioned (Fr. 1.3), it is left behind immediately;Footnote 61 from the opening lines of the proem, the poem is located ‘far from the beaten track of men’ (ἀπ’ ἀνθρώπων ἐκτὸς πάτου, Fr. 1.27). Similarly, if any question concerning man’s fate arises in the proem, this is only for it to be dismissed quickly by the divinity into whose protective custody the kouros is taken (e.g. Fr. 1.26, where it is announced that no ‘evil fate’ [μοῖρα κακή] has brought the kouros this far). Similarly, Parmenides’ poem is untouched by words of, for example, the semantic fields of hybris (cf. ‘Eunomia’ 8), euphrosynē (cf. ‘Eunomia’ 9), the atē family, habrosynē, or any of the other terms used so ubiquitously in elegy to invoke the just calibration of cause and effect, behaviour and consequence, action and outcome. Parmenides’ grand but static Dike guards the entrance to the goddesses’ transcendental Beyond, her agency restricted to the domain of guardswoman and gatekeeper (Fr. 1.14–17) – a far cry from the vast supervisory and regulatory power she is arrogated by Solon, for example.Footnote 62 Though the greeting between goddess and mortal is warm, we find no hint of feasting, the drinking of wine, or anything that hints at sympotic practice or culture.Footnote 63 Similarly, there can be no question of the right relations between man and his city, or even man and his fellow man, for it is precisely to leave behind the world of men that the proem marshals its resources. Considering the portions of the Odyssey that archaic poets found useful for articulating their perspectives (or at least resembled when they did so) dramatically underscores that, by contrast, the world of Parmenides’ poem is a world specifically devoid of other men and their institutions, their division of wealth, responsibility in war, or the prerogatives of high status in the social order.

Equally telling is the portion of the Odyssey with which Parmenides does engage.Footnote 64 This, too, can be found in the stories Odysseus embarks upon in his speech to Alcinous: the first half of Odyssey 12, at just the moment when Odysseus finally prepares to depart from Circe’s never-never island paradise (to be discussed below in Chapter 4). As scholars have pointed out, this episode in many respects represents a climax of the fairy-tale ambience of the Apologoi, the Elsewhere par excellence against which the Odyssey articulates its conception of normal human relationships.Footnote 65 Arguably, no portion of Homer stands more aloof from the polis and its metonyms than this divine fantasy.

The inverse point can also be made. Though we are very largely dependent here on what the trash heaps of Egypt disgorge, the evidence we do have suggests that the Circe episode does not seem to have been tremendously popular in the archaic era.Footnote 66 Nor does the existing inventory of pottery (again, a regrettably fragmentary source of evidence) suggest that artists working in other media were more enthusiastic. This, too, is instructive. It is not difficult to discern why this passage should have held such little allure for elegiac poets at the same time as Parmenides found it so attractive, just as the reverse is true for Od. 9.2–11.

A similar set of points can also be made about Parmenides’ engagement with Hesiod.Footnote 67 Scholars of elegiac poetry have a long history of examining the importance of Hesiod for elegiac poets.Footnote 68 As the ‘Golden Verses’ of the Odyssey and other scenes from the world of mortals, such as Odysseus’ interactions with the wicked suitors, provided an appealing intertextual opportunity to reflect on the social order and the nature of justice human and divine, so it is Hesiod’s Works and Days that accounts for the lion’s share of archaic elegy’s engagements with Hesiod.

The Hesiod we find in Parmenides, however, is not the stern moralist of the Works and Days but the Muse-sponsored conduit of facts about the cosmos we find in the Theogony.Footnote 69 In the proem especially, scholars have observed a number of striking intertextual links between Parmenides and Hesiod.Footnote 70 As has been much discussed, lines 1.11–20 of Parmenides’ proem contain many points of contact with Theogony 736–66, where Hesiod describes the ‘great bronze threshold’ that leads to the Underworld.Footnote 71 The Hesiod that interests Parmenides, and whose words and images he reworks, is the Hesiod who sings the birth of gods and the structure of the cosmos, not the poet of well-tilled soil and the righteous hearth. What place could a discussion of an Iron Age, or a jeremiad lamenting its arrival, have in Parmenides’ poem?

2.3 Poetics and Epistemology

Homerizing, then, was a widespread phenomenon in the time of Parmenides, but Parmenides’ engagements with Homer are distinctive in ways that bring into sharp focus defining features of his poem. As we move now towards the larger stakes involved in Parmenides’ relationship to Homer, it is important to put the foregoing discussion of the importance of Iliad 2 for late archaic moments in its broader social and intellectual context. Of central importance will be the question of what kind of claim to truth – and made by whom – would have been possible in Parmenides’ time.

We discussed above the powerful currents of epistemological change, driven in part by thinkers such as Xenophanes, that swept through the mid- to late archaic world.Footnote 72 Into this world of changing knowledge entered a dizzying array of new men, each staking their claim to wisdom and the truth – statesman-sages, cosmologists, mythographers, physicians, as well as diviners, prophets, seers, and other clairvoyants claiming insight into the will of the gods.Footnote 73 Alongside these social and political developments, the more widespread advent of writing, as well as an increasingly pervasive process of the Panhellenization of myth, may well have resulted in the proliferation of incompatible versions of the same myths, whose differences, now being fixed in writing for comparison, were more conspicuous.Footnote 74 In short, Parmenides was born into a time of radical epistemological fomentation.

The various late archaic echoes of the Invocation of the Muses examined above provide a fascinating glimpse (albeit through the distinctive lens of poetry) into this changing conceptualization of knowledge by allowing us to trace the shifting contours of the relationship between poet and Muse. One way to tell the story of these shifting contours requires us to set matters against the backdrop of epic (or at least Homeric epic) as characterized by, and itself embodying, a maximalist conception of truth and truthfulness. Scholars have developed this conception through a variety of rubrics, which include a ‘poetics of truth’, complemented in turn by a ‘rhetoric of traditionality’ (and, alongside this, a ‘rhetoric of universality’ and a ‘rhetoric of indifference’), grounded in part within a ‘semblance of fixity’ of epic language and its status as ‘special speech’, and the ‘traditional referentiality’ characteristic of bardic practice.Footnote 75

According to the notion of a poetics of truth, the Muses are understood very literally to be eyewitnesses who have first-hand knowledge of the events to be narrated, and they convey these accurately, completely, and unproblematically to the bard via divine inspiration; he in turn acts as their mouthpiece, transmitting the information the Muses have witnessed first-hand directly through his song.Footnote 76 This poetics of truth is expressed through, and supported and complemented by, the rhetorical stances characteristic of Homeric epic listed above.Footnote 77 These stances have been discussed partly in terms of epic’s general reluctance to foreground the persona of the poet. If the poet’s persona is often introduced for the purpose of establishing a relationship with a specific audience, keeping the individual singer out of the picture allows epic to preserve a ‘notional equidistance from all audiences’;Footnote 78 by eliding their own presence, bards also emphasize that the song derives directly from the Muses. What is more, any new innovations to the story are added as subtly and discreetly as possible, and are even referred to as if they were already common knowledge.Footnote 79 The effect is immeasurably heightened for being expressed in the special repertoire of epithets, patronymics, and other formulae that make epic ‘special speech’ and, along with type scenes, familiar tropes, and plot points that are encompassed by the notion of epic traditional referentiality.Footnote 80

If parts of this argument draw heavily on the Invocation of the Muses in Iliad 2, this picture of the relationship between bard, Muse, and truth contrasts notably with the relationship to the Muses fashioned in the late archaic poems that, we have seen above, were indebted to this purple passage of the Iliad. Remarkably, in his ‘Ode to Polycrates’, Ibycus styles his Muses σεσοφισμέναι, ‘practical, technically skilled/clever’ (23).Footnote 81 Questions of truth (or falsity, for that matter) are conspicuously absent from this poem; what matters in the ‘Polycrates Ode’ is precisely that which the poet of the Iliad suggests is inferior to the Muses’ knowledge (cf. Il. 2.485–6): kleos – who gets it, who gives it, and how (46–48).Footnote 82 Simonides’ task in the ‘Plataea Elegy’, meanwhile, is not to transmit otherwise-unknowable information about the mythical past, but to transform the facts of a recent event into an account worthy of its magnitude.Footnote 83 Accordingly, the poet, who asks his Muse to serve as epikouros, a ‘(foreign) auxiliary’ (21), designates her share in the poetic labour as ‘preparing the charming adornment of our song’ (μελί̣φρονα κόσμον ἀοιδῆς | ἡμετέ̣ρης, 23–24).Footnote 84 Both poets allude to Iliad 2 to draw pointed contrasts that highlight the distinctiveness of their own themes, goals, and modes of expression from the Homeric predecessor whom they glorify at the same moment as they depart from him.Footnote 85 Similarly, on the reconstruction of the texts currently favoured, in Paean 6 and especially 7b, engagement with Homer becomes a site for Pindar to radically refashion his poetic persona.Footnote 86 The Invocation of the Muses in Iliad 2 seems to have offered later poets a powerful site for expressing claims about their social function and status as poets, articulating their aesthetic and epistemological positions, and crafting their own poetic identities.

This perspective accords with a popular view concerning Pindar’s epinicians. As in the case of praising a living patron, or valorizing in song a recent battle of great importance, celebrating a victor and his recent victory would seem to require no recourse to an apparatus of truth-telling – the fact of the victory is self-evident, the accuracy of what is being reported for celebration hardly in question. Even when he recounts myths, however, nowhere in the large corpus of his surviving epinicians does Pindar claim recourse to the Muses to vouchsafe the veracity of the account he provides.Footnote 87 Rather, not dissimilar to what we have seen Ibycus and Simonides do, Pindar appeals to them on matters concerning the beauty and propriety of his songs.Footnote 88 The late archaic Muses of Ibycus, Simonides, and Pindar’s epinicians cut rather a different set of figures from their epic sisters, more honey-voiced technicians or arbiters of propriety than guarantors of truth; their aegis bears the sign of poetic craft and social decorum, not epistemological absolutism.

2.3.1 Diachronic Change or Generic Difference?

What does this imply for the epistemological milieu within which Parmenides would have been composing his verse? Answering this question depends in part on whether we see the differences between Iliad 2 and subsequent reworkings of it as the result of being products of different eras or of different genres.

The former case has found many advocates. It is easy to set the differences between Homer, and Ibycus, Simonides, and Pindar’s epinicians against the backdrop of the enormous ‘revolution in wisdom’ that took place during the archaic period, largely as a result of, and in turn partly as a cause of, the many different features cited in the opening paragraphs of this chapter and this section, respectively.Footnote 89 Particularly pertinent would be the question of writing discussed above, whose effects we may already have observed in the discussion of Pindar’s Paean 6 and 7b.Footnote 90 Thus ‘both Pindar and Hecataeus … faced with multiple and contradictory versions [of myths] … acknowledge the impossibility of believing everything the tradition has handed down … Pindar argues for his modifications, while Hecataeus expects the reader to share his understanding of what is likely’.Footnote 91 On this view, Pindar ‘cannot use the Muse to support the truth of his claims, because poetry has already made claims that he wishes to reject’.Footnote 92 That is to say, in the world of late archaic poetry, ‘[t]he Muses do not bear witness or take an oath. The poet must stand by his own words.’Footnote 93

Not long after Ruth Scodel, an expert on archaic poetry, concluded her study of Pindar’s epinicians with the remarks quoted above, a more philosophically oriented scholar could cite the paeans of the same poet to argue for quite a different story of epistemological change in the mid- to late archaic period; thus Herbert Granger claims that ‘Pindar never gives up his reliance on the Muses for truths that are difficult to get at’.Footnote 94 The incompleteness of our evidence does not allow us to determine whether we should best understand a possible contrast between the Muse of Pindar’s epinicians and those of his paeans as a negative statement about the nature of the epinician – that, like the Muse of elegy,Footnote 95 the epinician Muse is not there to be a conduit of truth – or a positive statement about the (Pindaric) paean, or perhaps both. With respect to Paean 6 and 7b, at any rate, it is hard to imagine that the holy nature of the performance setting and the poetic genre are not important. The speaker of Paean 6 begins by appealing, by Zeus, to ‘Golden Pytho, famed for seers’ (1–2), to welcome him, ‘a prophatas of the Pierians, famed in song’ (5–6) in the sacred time (5) of the Delphic theoxenia (cf. lines 60–61);Footnote 96 this is not the occasion to entertain questions of fictionality, or lying Muses, or anything but the most sombre, most ardent commitment to the truth.Footnote 97 One can see why an allusion to the most epistemically aspirational portion of all epic would be valuable.

Even so, the dynamic described by Scodel does not seem to be ameliorated. In fact, the contrary seems to be true – local legends surrounding the origins of the festival apparently create a conflict with the cyclic (i.e. ‘Homeric’) account, and it is precisely this which appears to precipitate Pindar’s appeal to the Muses in the first placeFootnote 98 – one needs to undertake major strategic manoeuvres if one is to convince the audience to trust an account that contravenes Homer’s. Even in this unusually sacred context, however, the best one can do is be persuaded by the Muses and, having been persuaded, persuade other men who, for their part, display (or prove?) their wisdom by being persuaded in turn. A similar dynamic appears to be in play in Paean 7b. There, the best the speaker can hope for from the Muses is a ‘resource’ or ‘facility’ to ‘seek the deep path of wisdom’ (18–20) – a far cry from the direct transmission of knowledge depicted in Iliad 2. The stakes of the matter are brought to the fore clearly in line 42: before introducing two alternative stories concerning the origins of Delos that are hard to reconcile, the speaker of the poemFootnote 99 asks: τί πείσομα[ι]; (‘what will I believe?’).Footnote 100 In the end, invoking the Muses cannot resolve the problem of impossibly accreted accounts (some of them in the authoritative name of Homer) or of incompatibilities between local and Panhellenic traditions; all it can do, especially when bolstered by the holiness of time, place, and rite, is endow with a special gravitas the ethical criteria or political motivations that have shaped the poet’s account.Footnote 101 On this view, that is, the Muses are a strategy for coping with poetic belatedness and the narrative overdetermination that would be one of its primary symptoms; and, as the question at Paean 7b.42 emphasizes – ‘what will I believe?’ – it is a strategy with clear limits.

If anything, then, the examples of Paeans 6 and 7b seem to reveal precisely the limitations of the poet’s recourse to the Muses as guarantors of truth, even in a setting where getting the story right would be a matter of the utmost significance. Even in a poetic genre of direct appeal to a divinity at that divinity’s holy festival, truth is not transmitted directly from the all-knowing Muse but, rather, in the face of multiple and contradictory accounts and with no means to discover it (βροτοῖσιν δ’ ἀμάχανο[ν εὑ]ρέμεν), wise men must be persuaded, that they may in turn persuade others. Whatever μαχανία (Paean 7b.18, cf. Paean 6.53) one manages to get from the Muses, and however one understands this term,Footnote 102 the relationship between man and Muse is plainly far more mediated and circuitous than in Iliad 2.

More challenging to a strictly diachronic account, according to which a ‘poetics of truth’ was ‘superseded’ by a poetics of some other kind, may be the Homeric Hymns, and especially the Hymn to Apollo.Footnote 103 The dating of this poem is of course contested, though it is notable that three heavyweights of twentieth-century classical scholarship should converge on an account that would see portions of the Hymn to Apollo dated to Parmenides’ lifetime, or merely a handful of years before his birth.Footnote 104 As with Pindar’s Paean 6 and Delphi, if one envisions a performance in 523/22 on Delos, are we really to expect that a poem dedicated to the god at a grand festival celebrating him on his own holy isle is best understood within the frame of a ‘poetics of fiction’? This is a doubtful proposition.Footnote 105 However clearly self-aware the poem is, and however cleverly the poet constructs, or fabricates, his own identity, in the end this is serious stuff; one can only assume its story was proposed, and intended to be received, as fact.Footnote 106

By the same token, the dynamics of divine interaction and poetic identity in the Homeric Hymns differ fundamentally from those in the Iliad and the Odyssey. The Homeric Hymns begin with the speaker’s ‘I’ and close with a farewell to the divinity in the second person, thus ‘differentiat[ing] the hymn from epic recitation where the Muse is asked to sing and the speaker appears to submerge or meld his own voice with hers’.Footnote 107 A hymn’s second-person parting salutation to the divinity hymned contrasts notably with the naming of the god in the third person in the standard opening of the hymns;Footnote 108 over the course of a hymn itself, that is to say, the gap between human and divine has been bridged, the bard having ‘somehow precipitated an epiphany of the god’ in and through the very act of singing.Footnote 109 Once again, attention to genre is critical. Where Paean 6 and the Hymn to Apollo both address the same god at a sacred festival hosted at one of his major hubs of worship, the dactylic hexameter of the hymn goes hand in hand with a far more immediate relationship not only to the divinity, but to truth; the epistemic complexity we find in Paean 6.50–58 and Paean 7b.15–20 only underscores the immediacy of access presumed – or indeed effected – by the hymn.Footnote 110 However epistemically constrained a late archaic composer of paeans or epinicians might have been, a poet roughly contemporary with Parmenides could nevertheless still claim the kind of access to divinity presupposed by a poetics of truth – but only in the specific parameters of the hexameter Homeric hymn.

There is one final consideration to take into account before moving on to Parmenides. If a diachronic story about a ‘poetics of truth’ giving way to a ‘poetics of fiction’ has come under fire on the grounds that (in certain genres) a ‘poetics of truth’ persisted into the late archaic era, so, too, critics have challenged this paradigm from the other direction. As Stephen Halliwell has argued, to the extent that we can discern a Homeric poetics, it contains more than just truth.Footnote 111 No doubt Halliwell is correct to insist that even as far back as Homer we should see a more complicated dialectic between a ‘poetics of truth’ and an understanding of poetry as ‘a powerfully transformative agency which carries hearers … outside of themselves’;Footnote 112 indeed his arguments on this score provide an important corrective to the view that the Homeric Muses are only there to guarantee the truth of the bard’s story. That is not to say, however, that they cannot do both. Acknowledging the power of the Homeric Muses to ‘transmut[e] even the extremes of human unhappiness into an experience of intense beauty worthy of immortal minds’ need not necessarily imply that the old position – that ‘Homeric epic predicates of itself a mode of truth-telling which amounts to a kind of historical veracity, the full and accurate relating of a heroic past in songs performed by human bards but informed by the divine knowledge of the Muses’ – is in fact ‘far less secure than it is often taken be’.Footnote 113 This is a point we shall take up in the next section.

2.4 Parmenidean Strategies: A Culmination

We are now in a position to tie the three threads of the above sections together. As we saw in Section 2.1, in Hesiod’s epistemic framework, truth (because divinely disclosed) can come only as the result of an epistemically significant interaction with the divine; but, owing to the nature of their own limitations, mortals cannot be certain of the truth-value of the information they receive from this divinity. Xenophanes then flatly denies the possibility of any unmediated disclosure from divinity, and forcefully underscores the inability of mortals to know the truth, as opposed to merely believing the claims at which they arrive in the course of their inquiries. Meeting the challenge set down by Xenophanes thus involves, first, effecting an encounter with a Muse-like divinity, that she may disclose truth, and, second, finding a way to abolish any doubt as to whether what has been disclosed actually is the truth.

What resources would Parmenides have had at his disposal to meet these two challenges? In Section 2.3 (‘Poetics and Epistemology’) we examined the possibility that there was a bardic ideal that, couched in rhetorics of traditionality, universality, and indifference, operated according to a poetics of truth. What might this have meant in Parmenides’ time? We saw that Halliwell seemed to question whether there was any such ideal at all. Whether critics today accept this is an open question – but, crucially, that is a separate matter from whether late archaic poets and thinkers would have done so. In essaying an answer to this second question, one may observe that the analyses of Halliwell and Finkelberg suggest that much of one’s view of Homeric poetics depends on how much prominence one gives the Invocation of the Muses in Iliad 2, which provides the strongest evidence for the position Halliwell finds less secure than is assumed. Though she examines a number of episodes with metapoetic significance, Finkelberg (as is not uncommon in modern discussions of Homeric poetics)Footnote 114 invests Il. 2.484–93 with programmatic significance, citing it in full at two pivotal moments in her argument.Footnote 115 Halliwell, by contrast, begins his analysis with the opening lines of the Iliad, and relegates the Invocation of the Muses in Iliad 2 to a footnote.Footnote 116

The claim need not be that one position is correct and the other mistaken with respect to Homeric poetics itself. Rather, what matters, I suggest, appears to be which of the Homeric invocations to the Muses or other metapoetic moments one makes exemplary in forming one’s opinion of Homeric poetics; make Il. 2.484–93 your programmatic example, and it is unsurprising if you end up with a poetics of truth (and perhaps it would even be surprising if you did not).

If this is so, there would seem to be important implications for assessing how late archaic poets viewed Homer. Here the discussion in Section 2.2 (‘Archaic Receptions of Homer’) can help provide us with an answer. The recurring interest in Iliad 2’s Invocation of the Muses we have observed suggests that the answer to the question ‘Is the “poetics of truth” position less secure than thought?’ must, for the late archaic period, be at least a qualified ‘no’. The qualifications are important. There may indeed be gaps between Homeric theory and practice,Footnote 117 and whether the original audiences of Homer deemed all the poetry they heard to be truthful is a separate question. As ever, the patchiness of the evidence we do have, both in terms of the scarcity of poems that remain, and of the fragmentary state of the papyri we are lucky enough to possess, means that any conclusions we reach about them must be tentative. This does not mean, however, that we cannot make good use of the evidence we have. And what we appear to find, particularly in Ibycus’ ‘Polycrates Ode’ and Simonides’ ‘Plataea Elegy’, suggests that these archaic poets did in fact attribute a poetics of truth to Homer, even if – or perhaps precisely because – they wished to forge different generic and poetic paths. As Pindar’s reworkings of Iliad 2 in his Paeans appear to indicate, however, the possibility of realizing this ideal in full in one’s own poetry was by this time severely constrained, if not entirely foreclosed. Finally, we have seen that roughly contemporary with Parmenides were at least a few poets who maintained an implicit belief in the power of poetry to effect a more direct, less mediated relationship with the divine: the poets behind the Homeric Hymns, composed in a version of the dactylic hexameter Kunstsprache.

With this evidence in mind, here is the view of Parmenides’ task that I propose. Parmenides, product of the late archaic era, inherited an epistemological framework articulated by Hesiod and further developed by Xenophanes. Alongside this Hesiodic framework there was also an ideal, however inaccessible by this date, of a bardic poetics of truth. Constrained by the Hesiodic-Xenophanean framework but with the resources of the second tradition at his disposal, Parmenides’ aim was to reinstall (or even, perhaps, properly to install for the first time) a maximalist epistemological position and stake a credible claim to an iron-clad epic poetics of truth.Footnote 118

2.4.1 Contact with the Divine: Reinstalling the Muse

Parmenides’ proem represents a multipronged strategy designed to fulfil this aim.Footnote 119 The first task is to reinitiate contact with the divine, in order that an epistemically significant interaction with this divinity might occur. Hesiod’s Muses descended to earth to ambush Hesiod on his own turf. Perhaps this was the first sign of trouble for the poetics of truth – the divine truth-tellers lower themselves to the domain of mortals, ‘mere bellies’ though they are (cf. Th. 26). Not so with Parmenides, who, as we have seen, works overtime to locate his encounter with the divine as far as possible from the world of men, ‘far from the beaten track of men’ (ἀπ’ ἀνθρώπων ἐκτὸς πάτου ἐστίν, Fr. 1.27). The Homeric Hymns offered a strategy for making not the epic past but rather the divine present; through the hymn itself, the poet would effect an epiphany. But the hymns do so by summoning the gods into the world of men. Parmenides does one better: his proem does not appeal to the divine to be present in the world of mortals, but transports the human kouros to the extraordinary world of the divine.Footnote 120 Scholars have debated whether the proem depicts a katabasis or an anabasis.Footnote 121 As usual with Parmenides, there are reasons to think that the ambiguities are intentional and beneficial.Footnote 122 One proposal that has gained favour recently sheds light on the essence of what the journey in the proem accomplishes; namely, that it is best understood as an apobasis: a journey that goes not necessarily ‘up nor down, but away from and beyond appearances and the world of the senses’.Footnote 123 The proem thus dramatizes a journey to an Elsewhere, a literally transcendental ‘Beyond’ that can serve as the right place for divine disclosure to occur.

2.4.2 Whose Muse?

A journey to what kind of divinity? Scholars have long debated the identity of the goddess.Footnote 124 Again, one strongly suspects that Parmenides’ ambiguity is strategic.Footnote 125 Functionally, however, the goddess plays precisely the same role in Parmenides’ poem as the Muses do for the poet. That Parmenides’ goddess plays a role functionally similar to an epic Muse is not a new idea.Footnote 126 But, in contrast to most earlier forms of this claim, I think we should see Parmenides’ goddess as much closer in kin, not to Hesiod’s cunning Heliconides, but rather, in light of the above discussion, to the Homeric underwriters of an absolute and incontestable epistemological guarantee to a mortal who would otherwise be constrained by crippling epistemic limitations.Footnote 127

Consider the following comparison. Scholars have from time to time remarked on the similarities between Th. 27–28 and Parmenides’ Fragment 1.29–30.Footnote 128 Immediately preceding Fr. 1.29–30, the goddess has graciously received the kouros, and after a short preamble observing that the journey was ratified by Themis and Dike, informs him that ‘it is right that you should learn all things’ (χρεὼ δέ σε πάντα πυθέσθαι, Fr. 1.28). This is elaborated to mean (Fr. 1.29–30):

ἠμὲν ἀληθείης εὐκυκλέοςFootnote 129 ἀτρεμὲς ἦτορ
ἠδὲ βροτῶν δόξας, τῇς οὐκ ἔνι πίστις ἀληθής.
Both the unshaken heart of well-rounded reality
And the notions of mortals, in which there is no genuine trust.

The Hesiodic passage, which is indeed similar in important ways, is worth repeating (Th. 27–28):

ἴδμεν ψεύδεα πολλὰ λέγειν ἐτύμοισιν ὁμοῖα,
ἴδμεν δ᾽, εὖτ᾽ ἐθέλωμεν, ἀληθέα γηρύσασθαι.
We know how to compose many lies indistinguishable from things that are real,
And we know, when we wish, to pronounce things that are true.

Finally, consider again the Invocation of the Muses in Il. 2.485–86:

ὑμεῖς γὰρ θεαί ἐστε πάρεστέ τε ἴστέ τε πάντα,
ἡμεῖς δὲ κλέος οἶον ἀκούομεν οὐδέ τι ἴδμεν.
For you are goddesses, and are present and know everything,
While we hear only rumour, and know nothing.

Which of these earlier engagements with the epic Muses do Parmenides’ lines more closely resemble? Tor’s discussion is again instructive, though this time because it embodies the scholarly consensus on the answer to this question. In his discussion of these lines, he observes that ‘like Hesiod, and unlike Homer who remains more in the background, Parmenides makes central the figure of the mortal agent who is identified with the poetic voice’.Footnote 130 But this is mistaken in two ways: Tor’s dismissal of Homer is unjustified, and it is in fact Homer, and not Hesiod, who provides tighter parallels in several important respects.Footnote 131

In fact, as the dichotomy ἡμεῖς…/ὑμεῖς…θεαί underscores, we find here precisely in Il. 2.485–86 what Tor goes on to claim is missing, on account of which he relegates Homer to the background: namely, ‘a first-person encounter with an all-female divine apparatus’.Footnote 132 As has been suggested, one reason that Iliad 2’s Invocation of the Muses proved such a focal point for the early reception of epic is precisely because it is one of the few places in Homer where the poet/narrator does identify himself in the first person and speaks directly in his own voice (Ἔσπετε νῦν μοι Μοῦσαι, Il. 2.484);Footnote 133 and his addressee is none other than ‘an all-female divine apparatus’ (ὑμεῖς … θεαί). Placing Parmenides’ Fr. 1.29–30 alongside Il. 2.484–86 shows that the case for relegating Homer to the background is not a strong one.

In fact, the reverse is true: not only should we not relegate Homer to the background, but proper consideration of all three passages makes clear that we must rather place him even more squarely in the foreground than Hesiod. In Il. 2.485–86, we find a dichotomy between epistemic extremes (ἴστέ τε πάντα … οὐδέ τι ἴδμεν); these are mapped onto an ontological distinction between divine and (by implication) mortal (ὑμεῖς … θεαί ἐστε … ἡμεῖς). In Hesiod, the first dichotomy is transformed from an epistemological to a discursive statement (i.e. from knowledge of the truth to the accurate or specious communication of this knowledge); the distinction between gods and mortals, meanwhile, is no longer expressed.Footnote 134 In Parmenides, as in the Homeric Invocation of the Muse, we find the first dichotomy articulated in epistemic terms once again: the distinction is between true knowledge of reality (ἀληθείης εὐκυκλέος ἀτρεμὲς ἦτορ) and a lack, or defectiveness, of knowledge (δόξας, τῇς οὐκ ἔνι πίστις ἀληθής). Likewise, as in Il. 2.485–86, this also coincides with, or is mapped onto, a distinction between divine and mortal; the inferior option is expressly linked to the human (βροτῶν δόξας, Fr. 1.30), while, as Tor himself persuasively shows, the epistemically superior option is intimately linked to the divine.Footnote 135 The only respect in which Parmenides’ account more closely resembles Hesiod’s is that it is his unnamed goddess that announces these dichotomies (χρεὼ δέ σε πάντα πυθέσθαι, Fr. 1.28), as do Hesiod’s Muses (ἴδμεν ψεύδεα … λέγειν … ἴδμεν … ἀληθέα γηρύσασθαι, Th. 27–28); in Homer, the narrator speaks in his own voice to appeal to the Muses for the transmission of information (Ἔσπετε νῦν μοι, Il. 2.484).

What we find, then, are unquestionable commonalities across all three passages that make it valuable to consider Parmenides’ lines as being in dialogue with both his primary epic predecessors. All three passages establish an epistemically charged relationship between a mortal narrator, who speaks in the first person, and an epistemically privileged female divinity or divinities. Like Th. 26–28 (but not Il. 2.484–86), Parmenides’ lines issue from the all-female divine apparatus. What Parmenides’ Fr. 1.28–30 and Il. 2.484–86 have in common with each other (and not with Th. 26–28) is much more extensive, however: each (a) articulates a dichotomy between two epistemic extremes; (b) explicitly affiliates the epistemically inferior term with the mortal, and associates the epistemically superior term with the divine (expressly in the case of the Iliad, implicitly in Parmenides’ poem); and (c), grants the mortal, who speaks in the first person, apparently unproblematic access to the privileged divine knowledge of the female divinity/divinities in what follows.

There is in fact another passage of Homer that cements even more firmly the case for bringing Homer from the background to make it the primary intertext for Parmenides; since exploring its connections to Parmenides’ fragments 1.21–8.49 will form much of the remainder of this book, however, I shall only gesture to it here. Comparing Parmenides’ goddess to Hesiod’s Muses, Dolin observes: ‘[t]o replace the specific, well-defined Muses of Hesiod, Parmenides has created an abstract blend of the sun-daughters of Thrinacia and Circe’.Footnote 136 Swap ‘Homer’ for ‘Hesiod’ and emphasize Circe a bit more strongly, and the statement captures the scenario masterfully. One hardly needs the semantic acrobatics of the phrase ‘all-female divine apparatus’ to point out that in Odyssey 12, and especially lines 27–141, a single female divinity with privileged access to knowledge (Circe) provides an urgently important, true, and trustworthy account of reality to her male, mortal charge (Odysseus).Footnote 137 Moreover, as we have also seen above, Odysseus’ speech to Alcinous – and indeed the entire Apologoi as a whole, of which Odyssey 12 forms so memorable a part – appealed to poets and thinkers over millennia in part for the very reason that ‘the figure of the mortal agent is identified with the poetic voice’.Footnote 138

2.4.3 Crossroads

There is another major advantage to seeing Parmenides’ goddess as resembling not Hesiod’s cunning Heliconides but rather a brilliantly crafted fusion of Homer’s trustworthy Muses and Circe. Recall point (iii) from Section 2.1 above, namely, that mortals have no way of knowing whether the accounts they get from the Muses are true or not. As Th. 27–28 makes clear (especially within the context of Hesiod’s conception of man and god, and male and female), mortals cannot ever really know what information they receive from divinity is the truth, and what is merely lies. Reading Parmenides against Homer’s Invocation of the Muses rather than Th. 27–28 reveals one of his most extraordinary strategies for addressing this issue. All three pairs of lines establish at least one fundamental dichotomy. The (mortal) speaker of the Iliad declares an essential distinction between absolute divine knowledge (ὑμεῖς … θεαί ἐστε, ἴστέ τε πάντα) and abject human ignorance (ἡμεῖς … οὐδέ τι ἴδμεν). Hesiod’s Muses cruelly exploit this ignorance by taking the superior information they can offer (ἴδμεν … ἀληθέα γηρύσασθαι) and a specious lookalike (ἴδμεν ψεύδεα … λέγειν ἐτύμοισιν ὁμοῖα) and mixing them up, polluting with lies like mud in the water of the Olympian spring the Muse-derived bardic poetics of truth. Here, however, Parmenides deploys an ingenious rhetorical stratagem: by rigorously filtering out the truthful distillate (in the ‘Route to Truth’), its epistemic purity personally guaranteed by the divine, and leaving the epistemic sludge (Doxa) to stand on its own, Parmenides’ Muse-like goddess sanitizes epic discourse once more.Footnote 139 She can begin her task of abrogating the Heliconian mischief of Th. 27–28 and undoing its epistemological damage by restoring the Olympian clarity of the interlinked dichotomies of Il. 2.485–86; these neatly differentiate between high and low epistemic positions and map them onto two separate ontological domains, the divine and the human, while giving the human (who is also the first-person narrator) otherwise-unobtainable access to the divine perspective.

In fact, this is only the first move of a multistep programme that Parmenides’ (Homeric-) Muse-like goddess undertakes to smelt out the epistemic alloy Parmenides inherits from Hesiod’s mischievous Muses and separate the pure ore of truth (ἀληθείης εὐκυκλέοςFootnote 140 ἀτρεμὲς ἦτορ) from doxastic slag (βροτῶν δόξας, τῇς οὐκ ἔνι πίστις ἀληθής). Unlike Hesiod’s Muses, who simply tell Hesiod what they wish and leave it for him to decide what is true and what merely resembles the truth, when she provides the kouros her account of reality, Parmenides’ goddess makes a point of ring-fencing trustworthy from untrustworthy discourse with a cordon sanitaire at Fragment 8.50–52 (cf. esp. Fr. 8.50: ‘here I end my pistis logos’). What is more, she also has her master manoeuvre: the hodos. Or rather, hodoi: for she will distribute the two stuffs, one pure and trustworthy, the other bankrupt or mixed (depending on how one interprets their relationship to fragments 6 and 7, and their relationship in turn to Doxa) to two different paths, the one no longer able to contaminate the other or confuse mortals as to its status. As we shall explore at length in chapters 4 and 5, the image of the forked hodos offers Parmenides’ goddess an extraordinary point of conceptual leverage to prise off the doxastic from the true.

2.4.4 Narrators and Voices

As we saw, this analysis does, however, bring to the fore one important distinction between Il. 2.484–86 and what follows it, and Parmenides’ Fragment 1.29–30 and what follows it. As in Theogony 27–28, the goddess(es) speak in her (or their) own voice, while in Il. 2.484 and following all we hear is the appeal of the first-person mortal narrator.Footnote 141 This only reaffirms the passage’s resemblance to Homer, however – though not necessarily with just Iliad 2. In the Theogony, all that we hear from the goddesses themselves is their taunt to the first-person narrator, who resumes in his own voice immediately after and in the remainder of what follows. Here again, Odysseus’ conversation with Circe at Od. 12.27–141 provides a much better parallel.

Even more strikingly, we see yet another benefit of reading Parmenides’ against the backdrop of Odyssey 12, a comparison that helps us see more clearly one of Parmenides’ most dazzling manoeuvres for establishing the trustworthiness of his account, and banishing any uncertainty about its veracity. Πολλὰ ψεύδονται ἀοιδοί, Solon is said to have warned: ‘the poets tell many lies’ (25 G.-P. = 29 W2).Footnote 142 And even if a poet can somehow be trusted not to lie, the foregoing discussion of Pindar hints at another major problem. We saw above the great gulf between the direct transmission from Muses to man in Il. 2.484–93 and the relationship to the Muses that Pindar depicts in Pae. 6.50–58 and Pae. 7b.15–20. In a best-case scenario, epistemically speaking, Pindar was to be given μαχανία by the Muses (Pae. 7b.17, cf. Pae. 6.53), but not even this would prevent him from confronting fundamental aporiai (cf. Pae. 7b.42–52) which he lacks the resources to surmount beyond what his own moral compass and sense of credibility can provide. The very asking of the question τί πείσομαι; (Pae. 7b.42) is deeply telling. Can one imagine the epic bard asking a similar question as he contemplates a dubious account of, say, the effects of Achilles’ wrath on the Trojan War? Even were a poet’s commitment not to lie were known to be absolute, how could an audience know that he or she, having to ask τί πείσομαι;, really had unmediated access to the truth?

The precise nature of this complex of problems becomes clear when one considers another moment in Paean 6, where the speaker characterizes himself as a προφάτας of the Muse (Pae. 6.6), and, likewise, when he (or perhaps a character?) declares μαντεύεο, Μοῖσα, προφατεύσω δ’ ἐγώ (Fr. 150 Maehler).Footnote 143 Both passages have provoked a number of interpretations, but even on the most epistemically optimistic reading of these fragmentary texts, such a relationship between poet and Muse would be of little use to someone trying to respond to the challenge set down by Xenophanes in his Fr. 18, which clearly includes a criticism of diviners.Footnote 144 This optimistic reading of Pae. 6.6 and Fr. 150 posits an analogy between, for example, the Delphic oracle and someone who interprets the meaning of the oracle, and the Muses and Pindar; just as the first ‘are never false … and only their interpretations may be true or false’, so the Muse never tells the poets anything false, but the poets sometimes misinterpret them.Footnote 145 But how does this guarantee the veracity of what poets say? This reading spares the poet from the accusation of lying, but that is not the same as saying he can always be relied upon to render the correct interpretation. More to the point, if Xenophanes rejects the possibility of precisely this kind of unerring interpretative trenchancy on the part of diviners, how could one hope to counter his critique by offering a model of access to the truth analogous to the very same one he questions?

By contrast, the more ‘humble’ reading of Pae. 6.6 and Fr. 150 has it that Pindar is merely the ‘spokesman’ or, quite literally, the mouthpiece of the Muses (viz. ‘one who speaks on behalf of others’) just as the ‘Delphic priests are the spokesman of the Pythia’.Footnote 146 Again, however, one must ask how such a relationship between poet and Muse could be of value to someone attempting to respond to Xenophanes’ scepticism. The problems come clearly into view in what remains of the body of the paean. As we saw, Pindar there contradicts the Odyssey in his own telling of the story of Neoptolemus; the implication is that the Pindaric speaker, not Homer, is the true ‘spokesman of the Muses’.Footnote 147 But what is to stop another poet from coming along in the future and playing the same game with Pindar’s Paean 6? And how does one know which mortal poet is the true spokesman of the Muses, and which merely a Homeric pretender? If Parmenides’ goal is to eradicate completely any confusion, uncertainty, or ambiguity surrounding the epistemic status of his message, being a Pindaric προφάτας of the Muse will not suffice, then, no matter how one interprets the phrase. We are no further than we were in Section 2.3.

Whether Pindar is to be understood as the interpreter of the Muse or her mouthpiece, Parmenides can go one better. His Muse needs no προφάτας: she speaks for herself, directly. We see here what is perhaps the most important upshot of Parmenides’ engagement with a portion of the Apologoi (viz. Od. 12.27–141), the one extended portion of epic narrated in the first person, which thus sits somewhere between the style of character speech and narration, whose speaker occupies a role between ‘storyteller and poet’, speaker of epos and purveyor of aidos.Footnote 148 Choosing the portion of the Odyssey that is presented by a (mortal) internal narrator, Odysseus, who narrates at length his interactions with, inter alios, figures with special access to knowledge (such as the divinity Circe or the seer Tiresias), allows Parmenides’ kouros to speak in the first-person ‘I’, as Odysseus does, while presenting his divinity in her own words, just as Circe and her epistemically privileged ilk are presented in the Odyssey. The result is hard truth presented in direct speech: Parmenides offers us alētheia straight from the source. A figure of privileged access to knowledge directly akin to the Muses speaks not through the poet as she might through an epic bard, in his voice and in his words: instead, the privileged source of knowledge is itself directly quoted by the speaker, and thus presented, immediately and unmediatedly, to the audience of the poem. The Muse no longer speaks through the mouth of the poet; rather, through an astonishing narratological sleight of hand, the Muse speaks for herself. By making Circe’s speech to Odysseus in Odyssey 12 the key intertext that he reworks, that is, Parmenides goes beyond the epistemic status implicitly asserted for the remainder of the Iliad by the Invocation of the Muses. His Muse needs no mouthpiece to give voice to the truth.

2.4.5 Argument

The goddess still has a final trump card to play, however. Her coup de grâce, an absolute guarantee rebutting Xenophanes and abolishing once and for all any uncertainty about the truth status of his claims, able to withstand the most gruelling and rigorous elenchus (as he puts it in Fr. 7.5) is an extended deductive argument, beginning from a point that all must accept.Footnote 149 As we shall see in the following chapters, she begins from a point that must be accepted (for who could reject it? cf. Parm. Fr. 2.7–8); moves on the rut road of argument (and who could swerve from it?); and ends at her fixed, final, ultimate, inevitable destination. Parmenides offers a better criterion for persuasion than the ethical canon of Pindar: iron-clad argument. We might be tempted to see here a Parmenidean version of the classic Homeric idea of ‘double motivation’.Footnote 150 On the one hand, the extended deductive argument is the proper complement of the unmediated divine disclosure that the kouros – and all of us, future listeners and readers – are party to. On the other, it comes straight from the mouth of the goddess, the very font of truth incarnate. Of late archaic poetry, Scodel wrote, ‘[t]he Muses do not bear witness or take an oath. The poet must stand by his own words’ (which could also be applied to early prose writers, like Hecataeus). In Parmenides’ poem, thanks to his spectacular mythifying (if not versifying) and his breathtaking narratological pas de deux, the poet does not need to bear witness or take an oath – the Muse stands by her own words. How could those words fail to persuade, beginning from a point all must accept and moving by way of extended deductive arguments to an inevitable conclusion (delineating, that is, the key outline of a demonstration)?

Incidentally, it bears emphasizing that the interpretation I have sketched out here is entirely compatible – or at least not a priori incompatible – with readings of Parmenides’ poem that focus on possible links with ritual or initiatory practices, language, or cults that may have been prevalent in Parmenides’ Elea.Footnote 151 Here we can benefit from Tor’s explosion of the dichotomy between reasoning and revelation,Footnote 152 and also from, for example, Ranzato’s use of Gernet’s notion of the ‘polysemy of myth’.Footnote 153 The benefit of these interpretative approaches becomes clear when comparing the conception of Parmenides’ goddess for which I advocate here with the views of, for example, Herbert Granger. As Granger puts it:

Parmenides is endeavoring to reshape the age-old practice of the appeal to a divine Muse into that which he takes to be the real value that lies behind the mythology of the Muse and of the whole tradition of divine revelation. The proem helps prepare us for the appreciation of the goddess as a persona who is symbolic of non-empirically based reason, and Parmenides is engaged in the demythologization of the Muse into a priori reason, the exercise of which yields truths without the aid of evidence provided by our perception.Footnote 154

Some similarities with the arguments made here will be obvious; Parmenides’ goddess is indeed a rhetorical device with the full weight of Homeric authority behind her. But she need not only be this. We may therefore part ways with Granger on two fundamental points. First, in keeping with Ranzato, Miller, and others, we should embrace the notion of a Parmenidean poetic discourse that allows for the goddess to occupy more than one role in more than one network of mythical or ritual associations at the same time; this interpretative flexibility would exemplify one kind of major pay-off that comes from reading Parmenides’ poem as a poem. Second, liberated from the need to see a tension between the goddess’s divinely disclosing a revelatory truth or making an a priori extended deductive argument, we need not be compelled to claim that Parmenides demythologizes anything. Instead, rather than seeing him as stripping old symbols of their meaning, we should see in Parmenides a virtuoso myth-maker who marshals together meaning-making symbols from different discourses and, activating their individual powers at different points and in different ways, harnesses each of these within one supercharged but unified, coherent whole. Parmenides’ goddess need not be reducible to any single ‘real’ value, but can have many different faces that she reveals at different times, or even at the same time depending on where one stands. So (if the historical Parmenides did indeed know the cults he is sometimes claimed to have known, or even if the discourse of his community was strongly affected by them) she can be like Demeter, Persephone, or Mnemosyne, depending on one’s preferred ritual context;Footnote 155 so she can also be like a Homeric Muse guaranteeing the absolute truth of the poem; so she can also, as we will discuss in chapters 5 and 6, be like Circe in Odyssey 12; and, provided one can make the cases for historical legitimacy and poetic relevancy properly, so can she also, perhaps, be like other characters as well. Parmenides loses nothing on this view except his status as a proto-analytic philosopher, an Enlightenment voice crying out in the archaic wilderness. And what he gains is the power of the poet, a thinker and user of language who taps the power of linguistic polysemy and polyvalence, socially and religiously charged imagery, pre-existing poetic traditions and the cultural institutions of his time and channels them all to the same end.

2.4.6 Dactylic Hexameter

Finally, we may also observe that the foregoing discussion also bears on Parmenides’ use of verse. As noted above, one consequence of the overwhelming tendency of scholars to read Parmenides as a philosopher rather than a poet – or, to make a slightly different point, of the tendency of scholars of ancient philosophy, but not of ancient poetry, to read Parmenides – has been to make it peculiar, at best, and a ‘grievous scandal’, at worst, for him to have composed in verse.Footnote 156 It is here that we see clearly how placing Parmenides within a chronology that does not begin with the Milesians, and includes or abuts not only Xenophanes, Heraclitus, or Zeno, but also the likes of Ibycus, Simonides, Pindar, and the Hymn to Apollo, grants us access to a new face of the kaleidoscope of his poem.

What has relocating Parmenides in the context of late archaic poetry added to this topic? Three insights. First, we see even more clearly how inappropriate the Muse-less form of prose would have been for his endeavours.Footnote 157 If overcoming the obstacles established by Xenophanes was of major importance for Parmenides’ project, and if this in turn required effecting an encounter with the divine, what possible use could prose, the medium of the new men of Ionian empiricism, have been? From this perspective, it would have been no more appropriate for Parmenides to have written in prose, one might think, than for a modern-day logician to undertake a proof in sonnet form.

But, second, and on the one hand, relocating Parmenides in the context of late archaic poetry should also make his choice of dactylic hexameter seem even more radical than has usually been acknowledged. The critics who have denigrated Parmenides’ poetic abilities universally wish he had opted for prose instead. Rowett is right to suggest that verse was the default form for the elevated and authoritative kind of speech act undertaken by Parmenides.Footnote 158 However, as the discussion above has also made clear, if by the late archaic period verse was still the authoritative medium in which to convey important ideas of some length, the ‘special speech’ of dactylic hexameter does not seem to have been. As we touched on above in our discussion of Od. 9.2–11 and later elegiac congeners, elegy seems to have been far and away the preferred medium for examining or announcing vitally important truths during Parmenides’ time.Footnote 159 It is true, as Sider points out, that Xenophanes, who wrote long compositions in elegy, ‘reserves his more scientific and philosophic writings for hexameters’.Footnote 160 These are all extremely short, however; whereas his elegiac fragments 1 and 2 clock in at twenty-four and twenty-two lines, respectively, his longest surviving hexameter composition is four lines (Fr. 34), and it does not seem that this was part of a longer continuous treatise.Footnote 161 By Parmenides’ time, the great boom in hexameter poetry represented not only by the Iliad and Odyssey but also, inter alia, the Cyclic Epics, the Hymn to Aphrodite and the Hymn to Demeter, and other poems such as the Catalogue of Women and the Shield of Heracles, seems to have slowed to a trickle; this is often taken to go hand in hand with the development of new modes of poetic expression to treat the topics of epic myth, often while making liberal use of epic diction, such as Stesichorean choral lyric.Footnote 162 Those who did continue to use dactylic hexameter for compositions of more than just a few lines often seem to have been associated with special guilds of rhapsodes particularly comfortable dealing with the artificial language of epic.Footnote 163

In short, we should entertain the possibility that the gap between the end of the oral hexameter tradition and Parmenides is a chasm more expansive than is often acknowledged; to speak the ‘special speech’ of epic was neither obvious, nor, I suggest, was it easily accomplished in a socially or intellectually persuasive way. That a thinker should have used verse to express his urgently important ideas in the late archaic period should come as a surprise to no one; that he should have done so in dactylic hexameter – and at such length, and at this late moment in the archaic period – appears bold. Just as for Pindar it was apparently quite a radical act to depart from the authority of the ‘well-trodden track’ of Homer when it came to matters of poetic content, so for Parmenides – who, to the best of our knowledge, was not a member of any kind of rhapsodic guild or the like – to return to the authority of Homer’s dactylic hexameters in choosing the poetic form in which to compose a poem of more than 160 lines (and perhaps up to around 500 or 600 lines)Footnote 164 was also, so it would seem, quite radical.Footnote 165

Third, and on the other hand, the foregoing discussion should also make dactylic hexameter seem even more desirable for Parmenides’ purposes in ways that extend beyond what the critics mentioned above have already proposed.Footnote 166 The discussion of Ibycus, Simonides, Pindar’s Paean 6 and 7b, and the Homeric Hymn to Apollo make clear how much the medium dactylic hexameter had to offer a thinker labouring to respond to Xenophanes’ challenge. If in Simonides’ day, the bard of the Iliad could be said to have ‘received the whole truth [πᾶσαν ἀληθείην]’ from the Muses, what could be more useful to Parmenides’ purposes than to assimilate himself to that tradition and claim that same possibility for himself? If, for Ibycus, the Muses could ‘embark upon’ what ‘no living mortal man could tell’,Footnote 167 what could be more valuable for Parmenides than to reinitiate contact with their kind? Conversely, if the surest connection to the divine that even so grand and numinous a figure as Pindar could claim (and at the Delphic theoxenia no less!) is μαχανία, and if the most this amounts to is to be persuaded by the Muse (if one is wise) and to persuade other wise men in turn; or to have one’s blindness eased (but how much?) as one seeks out the deep paths of wisdom, we see in the gulf between these positions and the scenario depicted in Il. 2.484–93 just how much Parmenides had to gain from earning access once again to the use of dactylic hexameter. The one genre that managed to maintain direct, immediate contact of a kind with the divine, the Homeric hymn, pointed to a strategy for reanimating the special speech of epic and reactivating the old rhetorics of traditionality, indifference, and universality en route to reclaiming a poetics of truth.

2.5 Conclusion

One of Parmenides’ most urgent aims was to resurrect (or, depending on how much one wishes to concede to Halliwell’s interpretation, properly to install for the first time) a poetics of truth. From the perspective of the late archaic era, at least, Iliad 2’s Invocation of the Muses was seen to set out an ideal of epistemological absolutism. The deep ambiguities inscribed into the foundations of Hesiod’s epistemology (and indeed his entire conception of the cosmos and the place of mortals within it) both expose the tensions that may always have been inherent in the epic tradition of the bards (otherwise, why should a rhetoric of traditionality have been necessary in the first place?), and also articulate the framework that would define subsequent conceptions of epistemology. The other poets of Parmenides’ late archaic era, whether they looked back on the ideal of Iliad 2 with nostalgia or playfully rejected it, seem both to have entertained this ideal and accepted that matters of truth and falsity were, in their time at least, more complex. A revanchist Parmenides set out to revitalize – or realize for the first time – an ideal that may or may not ever have been unambiguously in circulation. His Muse would speak the absolute truth – and, like Circe to Odysseus, she would do so directly, in her own voice.

In crafting a socially and intellectually compelling response to Xenophanes’ challenge, Parmenides was faced with the task of speaking many languages, telling many stories, producing many texts at the same time. Reinstating a poetics of truth, invested with the extraordinary weight of the epic past and its canonical bard (who had received the whole truth from the violet-tressed Muses) was a task that only the most rarefied maker of myths – a poet in the etymological sense – could tackle. In Parmenides’ poem and in his goddess, we can discern a new kind of ‘double motivation’ (double at the least): to dramatize an effective reunion with an all-knowing divinity, and in her own domain, her own proper and carefully guarded site of truth, that a poetics of truth might be (re)instated once and for all; and, to be absolutely certain, through the Doom-ful, Fate-ful, unyielding power of necessity, movement via the path of argument (no turns, no swerves, no other routes permitted) that no voyager on the ‘Route to Truth’ could fail to achieve anything short of full knowledge of the truth. The most elegant versifier to have plied hexameter fields Parmenides may not have been. But the foregoing analysis reveals a poet whose dexterous command of mythical and religious imagery can match even the most brilliant of his near contemporaries. In fact, the case presents perhaps the finest adjunct of all to the Muses’s diademFootnote 168 – not the clear-voiced, honey-tongued Muse of elegy or lyric, but the Muse who speaks an irrefutable truth in her own voice, directly to her audience.

Footnotes

1 Parmenides’ dates are notoriously controversial. The two main possibilities for his birth are 544–541 or c. 515 BCE, and in many ways the question comes down to whether one finds greater reason to doubt the timeline provided by Diogenes Laertius (9.21–23), likely on the authority of Apollodorus (see e.g. Reference CorderoCordero (2004) 5–6 and footnotes), or Plato in his Parmenides (esp. 127a–c).

One can undermine the historical accuracy of both sources with unnerving ease. As has been pointed out, the earlier date creates a suspiciously tidy chronology of events related to Parmenides; thus his birth would coincide neatly with the foundation of Elea and the floruit of Xenophanes, and his own floruit precisely with Zeno’s birth; see e.g. Reference BurnetBurnet (1930) 170; Reference Coxon and McKirahanCoxon (2009) 40; Reference Kirk, Raven and SchofieldKirk, Raven, and Schofield (2007) 240.

On the other hand, if one takes Plato to be a virtuoso dramatist, it is tempting to see motives other than strict historical accuracy behind his account. Plato clearly has much to gain from staging a contest between, for example, a young Socrates, who presents a well-developed Theory of Forms (something which should in itself make us suspicious), and the venerable old master who critiques it; as has been observed (see e.g. Reference MansfeldMansfeld (1990) 64–68 and esp. Reference CorderoCordero (2004) 5–8), it is attractive to see Plato as undertaking a (philosophically Parmenidean) revision of his own Theory of Forms by ventriloquizing his self-criticism through the suitably august figure of Parmenides. What is more, the precision of Plato’s dating need not imply, as Guthrie had it, that Plato ‘had no reason to give such exact information about their ages unless he knew it to be correct’ (Reference GuthrieGuthrie (1965) 2); as Thanassas, who observes that such precise datings are more or less unparalleled in the Platonic corpus, suggests, ‘the reverse is actually the case: Plato would have had no reason to provide such trivial details unless he wanted to present as credible something that in reality could not have taken place’ (Reference ThanassasThanassas (2007) 10 Footnote n. 5). There are of course other instances where Plato’s dates are notably unreliable; in Timaeus 20d, Solon is presented as twenty to thirty years younger than is possible; see Reference UntersteinerUntersteiner (1958) 19.

Finally, scholars of archaic poetry have also found the earlier date attractive for reasons entirely unrelated to doubts about the strict historicity of Plato’s account; see here Reference D’AlessioD’Alessio (1995), whose primary interest is Pindar’s relationship to Parmenides. Another striking feature of this debate is that some of those who plump for the later date, including Reference WestWest (1983) and West (2011b), still date Parmenides’ poem to about 490 BCE on the premise that the figure of the kouros is autobiographical and the poem composed shortly after the event it describes. Conversely, if one is inclined to doubt Plato’s dating, but sees in the kouros nothing more than a literary construction, one easily ends up at a similar date of composition.

4 Usually credited to Anaximander or Pherecydes of Syros. Notable discussions in e.g. Reference GoldhillGoldhill (2002), Reference Kahn and YunisKahn (2003), and Reference GrangerGranger (2007); for Pherecydes, see Reference SchibliSchibli (1990).

5 See table at Reference OsborneOsborne (2009) 239–41 with accompanying discussion at 237–45, more generally von Reden (1995), Kurke (1999), Schapps (2004), and Reference SeafordSeaford (2004).

6 Though I should emphasize that by no means do I wish to minimize the effect of other influences, much less to rule them out entirely; my interest lies in making the case for a significant interaction with Homer, rather than against the influence of others.

7 For Parmenides and Hesiod, see Introduction, Footnote n. 80. One of the most important developments in Presocratic scholarship in the last few decades is the rehabilitation of Xenophanes’ reputation and the new perspectives this has opened on Parmenides’ work; see Introduction, n. 15.

8 Reference TorTor (2017), with 61–103 devoted to Hesiod and an excellent discussion of lines Th. 27–28 at pp. 62–64. I will not attempt a bibliography of the vast discussion on these vexed lines, especially since a comprehensive, systematic account can be found at Reference TorTor (2017) 62–64, with extensive bibliography in the footnotes, of the ‘truths only’, ‘lying Muses’, and ‘ambiguous’ interpretations. I have also been influenced by Reference ClayClay (2003) 49–80, and I express my gratitude to the author of Reference VogelVogel (2019) for discussing this passage with me. For a different view, see e.g. Reference HeidenHeiden (2007).

9 See esp. Reference TorTor (2017) 72–94, 102.

11 Reference TorTor (2017) 310; see Reference TorTor (2017) 83–93 for the Theogony, and pp. 97–103 for Works and Days and general conclusions.

14 See Reference TorTor (2017) 10–60, esp. 10–19.

15 Translation mine, influenced by Reference TorTor (2017) 128–31; see Reference LesherLesher (1992) 156–57, Reference TorTor (2013) 10 Footnote n. 23, Reference TorTor (2017) 128–29 and notes. See also Fragment 18.

17 Though, as we shall discuss in Ch. 6 below, Fr. 18 does allow for a temporally extended process by which human understanding can be developed and improved.

18 See above and Footnote nn. 15–17 regarding Fragment 18. For the evidence of Parmenides’ engagement with Xenophanes, see esp. Reference BryanBryan (2012) 97–100; for verbal echoes, see discussions in Reference Coxon and McKirahanCoxon (2009) [1986] 18–20; Reference LongLong (1996) 143; Reference PalmerPalmer (2009) 329–30; Reference TorTor (2017); 314–26.

19 Depending, of course, on how one dates both Parmenides and certain events in the reception, conceptualization, and performance of Homer; see Footnote n. 1 above and the scholarship cited in Footnote n. 27 below. More generally, see esp. Reference Burkert and CairnsBurkert (2001), Reference WestWest (1999), Reference Cassio and MontanariCassio (2002), Reference GraziosiGraziosi (2002), Reference Graziosi, Marmadoro and HillGraziosi (2013), Reference Graziosi and HauboldGraziosi and Haubold (2015). See also remarks in Reference Graziosi, Marmadoro and HillGraziosi (2013) 10 Footnote n. 6 and Reference ClayClay (2011a) 14–15.

20 See also Xenoph. Fr. 11.

21 See also Heraclitus B 56. For the implications of these fragments from both Xenophanes and Heraclitus for our understanding of Homer, see esp. Reference Burkert and CairnsBurkert (2001) 45; Reference GraziosiGraziosi (2002) 57–60; Reference Graziosi, Hardwick and StrayGraziosi (2008) 28.

22 Simon. 11.15–18 (discussed below), 19.1–2, 20.13–15; PMG 564; Pind. frs. 264, 265, Pyth. 4.277, 3.112–15, Nem. 7.20–23, Isth. 4.37–42, Pae. 7b.11 (discussed below); Bacchyl. Fr. 48, 1.92. For discussion, see Reference WestWest (1999) 377–82, esp. 378–79; for Pindar and Homer, see Reference GraziosiGraziosi (2002) 57–60 and Reference West, Rutherford and ObbinkWest (2011a), esp. 51–56. West also notes an epigram on a herm in the Athenian agora which names Homer; this was set up following the capture of Eïon in 475 (Aeschin. In Ctes. 183; Plut. Cim. 7.6; FGE, 257 ll. 841–42).

23 See discussions in Reference ErcolesErcoles (2013) and Reference Finglass and DaviesFinglass and Davies (2014) 6–18 for Stesichorus’ dates and location.

24 See e.g. Reference Burkert and CairnsBurkert (2001) and Reference Kelly, Finglass and KellyKelly (2015) (the adjective recherché is his: p. 39); also, from a slightly different perspective, Reference Carey, Finglass and KellyCarey (2015), esp. 54.

27 The event is given a position of definitive importance by scholars who otherwise find little to agree on in matters Homeric, including e.g. Reference WestWest (1999); Reference JankoJanko (1998) 13; Reference Janko and KirkJanko (1992) 29–32; Reference NagyNagy (1996a) 66–67; and Reference Cassio and MontanariCassio (2002), esp. 115. See M. Reference Finkelberg, Tsagalis and MarkantonatosFinkelberg (2017) for an up-to-date discussion (with bibliography) of this large and contested topic.

28 For the interesting possible connections between the Ionic colony of Elea and the Doric outpost of Rhegium, see Cassio (1996) Reference Cassio and MontanariCassio (2002).

29 Tatianus, Ad Gr. 31 (= DK 8.1). See Reference WestWest (1999) 378 Footnote n. 41 for discussion; also Reference Cassio and MontanariCassio (2002).

33 Reference Ford, Bakker and KahaneFord (1997) 101. That is, should a unit of text be ‘adduced and accepted as Homer’s words’, it ‘demands attention in itself because of its source’. Notably, this presupposes some kind of fixed and canonical Homeric text.

34 Rather, I shall claim that certain elements of Parmenides’ poem – and, most importantly, its discursive architecture (discussed in Ch. 3) – are inherited from, and rework, Odyssey 12. See also discussion above in the ‘Aims’ section of the Introduction.

35 For claims that Stesichorus engaged with Homer in this way, see Reference Kelly, Finglass and KellyKelly (2015), esp. 43. For a good discussion of evidence for Pindar’s literate engagement with Homer, see e.g. Reference West, Rutherford and ObbinkWest (2011a) and Reference SpelmanSpelman (2018a) 101–110 with notes.

36 Incidentally, one could support this position equally well with an account of the Homeric poems’ influence that emphasized either a process of canonicity or a process of textualization, provided one accepted that by the late archaic period this process was already well underway. See Reference NagyNagy (2014) for a good recent summary of his views; for criticism of Nagy and his school, see e.g. Reference JankoJanko (1998), Reference FinkelbergFinkelberg (2000), Reference Cassio and MontanariCassio (2002), Reference Graziosi and HauboldGraziosi and Haubold (2015), and Reference ReadyReady (2017) 500–04, many of whom focus on increasing canonicity.

37 Not coincidentally, Dr Henry Spelman has used these poems by Ibycus, Pindar, and Simonides as case studies for examining late archaic intertextual engagements with Homer; I am most grateful to Dr Spelman for sharing unpublished work with me, and commend to the reader his forthcoming publication on the topic, my debt to which will be very clear.

38 For the distinctive features of the ten-line invocation, see esp. Reference KrischerKrischer (1965) and Reference de Jongde Jong (1987).

39 See comments in e.g. Reference WestWest (1999) and Reference Kelly, Finglass and KellyKelly (2015) for Mimnermus, Reference SwiftSwift (2012) and Swift (2019) – where further bibliography can be found – for Archilochus.

40 For a summary of the current state of play, see e.g. Reference Kelly, Finglass and KellyKelly (2015) and Reference CurrieCurrie (2016), esp. 33–36.

41 For the possibility of the early date, see Reference WilkinsonWilkinson (2013) 8–12, esp. 12. For a date between the late 530s and 522 BCE, see Reference HutchinsonHutchinson (2001), esp. 231–32, and Reference HutchinsonHutchinson (2001) 257–59; for an extended discussion of Ibycus’ dates in general, see Reference HutchinsonHutchinson (2001) 228–35.

42 Notable here are the remarks of Reference FowlerFowler (1987) 36–37.

43 For detailed analysis of the poem alongside the Catalogue of Ships, see Reference BarronBarron (1969) 133–34; Reference WoodburyWoodbury (1985); Reference FowlerFowler (1987) 36–37; Reference GoldhillGoldhill (1991) 116–17; Reference HutchinsonHutchinson (2001) 235–36, 244–46, 253–56; Reference WilkinsonWilkinson (2013) 55–58, 71–73; Reference HardieHardie (2013); Reference BudelmannBudelmann (2018) 172; and n. 37 above.

45 This is true whether one takes the first word of line 25 to be thnatos, as advocated by Reference HutchinsonHutchinson (2001) 244–46 and Reference WilkinsonWilkinson (2013) 71–73, or autos, as suggested by Reference WestWest (1966b) 152–53 and Reference 353WestWest (1975) 307. For further discussion, see Reference WoodburyWoodbury (1985) 197 Footnote n. 10; also Reference HardieHardie (2013) 10 Footnote n. 2. Following Reference WilkinsonWilkinson (2013) 50–52, the key portion of the text is (lines 23–26):

καὶ τὰ μὲν̣[ἂν] Μ̣οίσαι σε̣σοφι̣[σμ]έναι
εὖ Ἑλικων̣ίδ[ες] ἐ̣μβαίεν †λόγ̣ω[ι,
θνατ[ὸ]ς† δ’ ο̣ὔ̣ κ[ε]ν̣ ἀνὴρ
διερ[ὸς … . .]. τὰ ἕκαστα εἴποι …
These things the skilled Heliconian Muses could embark upon (?) in speech well, but no living mortal man (?) could tell every detail …

47 If one accepts SM ii, 27–32, Pae. 6.54–55, ἴσθ̣’ [ὅ]τ̣[ι], Μοῖσαι, | πάντα is a clear echo of ἴστέ τε πάντα (Il. 2.485). Spelman (n. 37) will provide a detailed analysis of this point, and also grammatical similarities; for a different view on how to punctuate Pae. 6.54–57, see Reference RutherfordRutherford (2001a) 309 Footnote n. 13.

48 See for now Reference WoodburyWoodbury (1985) 197–98 for a comparison of these four passages.

49 Following Reference RutherfordRutherford (2001a) 299. The antecedent of tauta in line 51 is missing; though supplements have proliferated, what is required of Pindar is to recount an episode from the mythical past, and it is to this – be that the episode itself, or the labour of telling it – that tauta almost certainly refers; what is at stake in both cases is the accuracy of the account that follows.

50 As e.g. Reference West, Rutherford and ObbinkWest (2011a) does, I follow the text of Reference RutherfordRutherford (2001a) 243–45:

ἐ]πεύχο[μαι] δ’ Οὐρανοῦ τ’ ἐϋπέπλωι θυγατρὶ
   Μναμ[ο]σύ[ν]αι κόραισί τ’ εὐ-
   μαχανίαν διδόμεν.
τ]υφλα̣[ὶ γὰ]ρ ἀνδρῶν φρένες,
ὅ]στις ἄνευθ’ Ἑλικωνιάδων
βαθεῖαν ε..[..].ων ἐρευνᾶι σοφίας ὁδόν.
I pray to the well-robed daughter of Uranus,
Mnemosyne, and her girls
To provide a resource.
For blind are the minds of men
Whoever without the Heliconians
… seeks out the deep path of wisdom.

See discussion of these lines at Reference RutherfordRutherford (2001a) 247–49 and Reference StamatopoulouStamatopoulou (2017) 43–45. A primary debt here is to Reference D’Alessio and El-MosalamyD’Alessio (1992) and Reference D’AlessioD’Alessio (1995), with further debates in Reference FerrariFerarri (2002), Reference Di BenedettoDi Benedetto (2003), and Reference D’AlessioD’Alessio (2004).

51 For the relationship between Simonides’ ‘Plataea Elegy’ and Homer generally, see Reference WestWest (1993), esp. 9; Reference Clay, Boedeker and SiderClay (2001); Stehle (2001); Reference KowerskiKowerski (2005) 100–06; Reference RawlesRawles (2018) 78–106; and n. 37 above. For discussions about Homer’s Muses and Simonides’ Muse: Reference Rutherford, Boedeker and SiderRutherford (2001b) 45–46; Reference Aloni, Boedeker and SiderAloni (2001) 94–95; Reference Stehle, Boedeker and SiderStehle (2001); Reference Clay, Boedeker and SiderClay (2001); Reference KowerskiKowerski (2005) 123–26. For the ‘Plataea Elegy’ and Iliad 2 in particular, see Reference Obbink, Boedeker and SiderObbink (2001), esp. 69; Reference SchmidtStehle (2001), esp. 108, 111.

52 Text from Reference WestWest (1993). The supplement πᾶσαν ἀλη]θείην, offered by Parsons in the editio princeps, is widely (though not universally) accepted.

54 Translation adapted from Reference GerberGerber (1999) 113.

56 See Footnote n. 30 above for scholarship on the larger question of the relationship between elegy and Homer.

58 On similarities between these two passages, see Ford (1999) 9–10; Ford (2002) 35–37; Irwin (2005) 126–32, esp. 126–28.

59 See e.g. Reference JaegerJaeger (1966), 77–99, esp. 82–90. See also Reference AdkinsAdkins (1985) 114; Reference AnhaltAnhalt (1993) 74–78, 110–13; Reference MülkeMulke (2002) ad loc.; Reference IrwinIrwin (2005), esp. 113–18; Reference Noussia-FantuzziNoussia-Fantuzzi (2010) 226. For the relationship between sympotic and political orderliness more generally, see e.g. Bielohlawek (1940); West (1978) 56; Slater (1981) 205–15; Slater (1990), esp. 216–19; Murray (1983) 262–65; Schmitt-Pantel (1992); Ford (2002) 46–60, esp. 54–58; Hobden (2013); Gagné (2013), esp. 226-249.

60 Also noted by Reference Nightingale and ShapiroNightingale (2007) 191, who addresses a similar nexus of topics in classical philosophy in Reference NightingaleNightingale (2004). In light of Parmenides’ influence on Plato, and thus, at least indirectly, later thinkers, I consider the following paragraphs to have major implications for the later tradition that Reference NightingaleNightingale (2004) examines; many aspects of the conceptual footprint of philosophic theoria that Plato develops would seem to be a very clear Parmenidean legacy.

61 For the textual crux at Fr. 1.3, see e.g. Reference Coxon and McKirahanCoxon (2009) [1986], Reference LesherLesher (1994b), Reference CosgroveCosgrove (2011), Reference PalmerPalmer (2009) 376–78, where further discussion and bibliography can be found, also Ch. 5, n. 8 below.

62 See Reference BurkertBurkert (1969) 13, Reference Furley, Lee, Mourelatos and RortyFurley (1973)Footnote n. 10, and, with further bibliography, Reference BryanBryan (2012) for the former, Reference Noussia-FantuzziNoussia-Fantuzzi (2010) 148–49 and Reference GagnéGagné (2013) 238–49 (with good further bibliography) for the latter.

63 See Ch. 5 n. 35 below for the significance of the hand gesture, which echoes an interaction between divinities and a mortal, not mortals and mortal, in Homer.

64 See chs. 5 and 6 below for an extended discussion of the similarities between Parmenides’ poem and Odyssey 12.

66 Of course, we must be wary here of the ‘what you see is what there is’ fallacy discussed by Reference Kelly, Finglass and KellyKelly (2015).

67 For Parmenides and Hesiod, see Footnote n. 8 above.

69 Reference JaegerJaeger (1948) 93: ‘That we need consider only the Theogony as Parmenides’ model, and need not concern ourselves with the Works and Days, is evident upon closer comparison.’

70 See Section 2.4.2, ‘Whose Muse’, below.

71 See esp. Reference Pellikaan-EngelPellikaan-Engel (1978) 6–10 (and 51–58 for further discussion) for a catalogue of similar passages in Parmenides’ proem and Hesiod’s Theogony, especially the passage discussed above. See also Reference MorrisonMorrison (1955) 59–60; Reference DolinDolin (1962) 96; Reference SchwablSchwabl (1963); Reference BurkertBurkert (1969) 8, 11–13; Pfeiffer (1975) 52–56; Reference Furley, Lee, Mourelatos and RortyFurley (1973) 3–4; Reference Tulli and ArrighettiTulli (2000); Reference MillerMiller (2006) 7–9; Reference RobbianoRobbiano (2006)150–55; Reference Most, Bierl, Wesselmann and LämmleMost (2007) 80–84; Mourelatos (2008b) 15; Reference PalmerPalmer (2009), esp. 54–55; Kraus (2013) 454; Reference RanzatoRanzato (2015); Reference TorTor (2017) 254–56, 351–54.

72 See esp. R. Osborne (1997), also Reference LloydLloyd (1979), esp. 257–59; Reference LloydLloyd (1987); and works cited in Footnote n. 73 below.

74 Reference Scodel and WatsonScodel (2001), esp. 125. For a detailed study of this question in regard to Pindar, see Reference West, Rutherford and ObbinkWest (2011a). As he concludes: ‘Pindar acknowledges that these poetic sources have an authority that he cannot simply ignore but must re-evaluate by insight into the nature of the tradition’ (p. 67). Scodel is responding in part to Nagy (1990b) 52–81. See also Reference 324FinkelbergFinkelberg (1998) 166–67 and Reference ThomasThomas (1992) 115.

75 For the ‘poetics of truth’, see Reference 324FinkelbergFinkelberg (1998); for the rhetorics of traditionality, indifference, and universality, Reference ScodelScodel (2002); for the ‘semblance of fixity’, Reference Kahane, Bakker and KahaneKahane (1997) and Reference BakkerBakker (1997); for ‘special speech’ see Reference BakkerBakker (2005) 47–55 (who builds on Reference NagyNagy (1990a)); for ‘traditional referentiality’, esp. Reference FoleyFoley (1999).

76 See esp. Reference 324FinkelbergFinkelberg (1998) 68–73. (Put differently, ‘for Homer, everything in poetry is truth’: Reference 324FinkelbergFinkelberg (1998) 73.) As she observes, the seriousness with which we should take idea that the Muses were conceived of as literal eyewitnesses is underscored by the way Hesiod and other theogonists handled the issue of describing affairs that occurred before the Muses themselves were born (p. 72). See also e.g. Reference FordFord (1992) 80–82; Reference ThomasThomas (1992) 115; Reference PrattPratt (1993); also discussed in Reference GrangerGranger (2007), but with problems – see below.

78 Reference GriffithGriffiths (1983) 44; Reference Graziosi, Haubold and BudelmannGraziosi and Haubold (2009) 107. This also ensures that what the poet says can be trusted, since it has not been distorted by the pressures of tailoring the story told to this or that specific audience and its social demands (viz. it adheres to ‘a rhetorics of indifference’; see Reference ScodelScodel (2002) 65–89, esp. 70–73). See esp. Nagy (1990b) 52–81, esp. 68–69, for a discussion of this question in terms of rejecting the local and epichoric in favour of the Panhellenic.

79 Reference Scodel and WatsonScodel (2001) 111–12. As Reference ScodelScodel (2002) 88 points out, this practice ‘could not be sustained if other versions were directly available for comparison’. See also Reference Scodel, Tsagalis and MarkantonatosScodel (2017); Reference Graziosi, Haubold and BudelmannGraziosi and Haubold (2009) 107–08.

82 For what is at stake in lines 46–48, see esp. Reference GoldhillGoldhill (1991) 117–19; for a different view, see Reference SammonsSpelman (2018a).

84 For an intriguing comparison with Parmenides Fr. 8.53, see Reference Rutherford, Boedeker and SiderRutherford (2001b) 46.

86 See esp. Reference D’AlessioD’Alessio (1995) 178–81; 170; Reference RutherfordRutherford (2001a) 248–49 (who bases his argument on content, not form); and, from a slightly different angle, Reference StamatopoulouStamatoupoulou (2017) 45–47. D’Alessio’s interpretation of Pindar’s relationship to Homer would take on an ironic cast in light of the relationship between Parmenides and Homer that I propose below. As I shall argue, Parmenides responds to an epistemological crisis, precipitated in part by those who reject Homer as an authoritative source of truth, by – among other things – returning to Homer’s epic hexameters, his use of mythical narrative (including specific Homeric dramatic scenarios), and his close relationship to the omniscient Muse(s); on D’Alessio’s view (Reference D’Alessio and El-Mosalamy(1992) 369–73; (1995) 178–180), it is precisely Homer’s verses that Pindar rejects. Parmenides is ‘far from the beaten track of men’ in that he rejects the answers offered by e.g. his Milesian predecessors, or perhaps Xenophanes, and partly due to his conservatively rebellious return to Homer; the ‘beaten path’ Pindar travels far from, by contrast, would be none other than Homer’s own. This also highlights the importance of genre and the traditions in which each poet works; the trope by which one poet-thinker cloaks his return to Homer can just as easily be the trope another poet-thinker uses to reject him.

87 Reference Scodel and WatsonScodel (2001); nor, for that matter, does he appeal to them regarding any other matter involving truthfulness.

88 Reference Scodel and WatsonScodel (2001) 123–37, esp. 123–25 (she cites in particular Ol. 6.19–21; one could also look at N. 1–19). See also Reference PrattPratt (1993) 123–28; Reference 324FinkelbergFinkelberg (1998) 160–71.

89 See nn. 2–5, 72–73 above.

90 See esp. Footnote n. 74 above.

91 Reference Scodel and WatsonScodel (2001) 136. See also West’s study ‘Pindar as a Man of Letters’ in Reference West, Rutherford and ObbinkWest (2011a) 66.

93 Reference Scodel and WatsonScodel (2001) 124; the same holds true for other ostensibly truth-seeking and truth-recording endeavours, such as those undertaken by Hecataeus.

94 Reference GrangerGranger (2007) 410; he cites the two paeans discussed above and a non-epinician fragment (Fr. 150 Maehler, also Bacchyl. Fr. 9.1–6).

96 On the Delphic theoxenia, a Panhellenic festival for Apollo (cf. lines 60–62) see e.g. Reference RutherfordRutherford (2001a) 310–11; Reference KurkeKurke (2005) 97–101, esp. 97 with footnotes.

97 One could extend the argument to the genre of paeans generally. What little consensus there is suggests that this is an important expression on behalf of society at large; see the slew of excellent studies on the topic since 1990, including Reference KäppelKäppel (1992), esp. 13, 34, 62–66, 341–49; Reference SchröderSchröder (1999), esp. 22–31; Rutherford (2001b), esp. 85–86, 183–185; Ford (2006). Useful, too, are these scholars’ reviews of each other’s work, including Rutherford (2001c) on Schröder, and Reference KäppelKäppel (2002) on Rutherford; see also Reference D’AlessioD’Alessio (1994) and Reference D’AlessioD’Alessio (2000).

100 One alternative, involving an attempted rape by Zeus, the speaker quickly deems incredible (ἄπιστά μ[ο]ι, line 45); other details gesturing to another story – one that stands at odds with key portions of the Hymn to Apollo – are then asserted, some of them, it would seem, simply on the poet’s own authority. See Reference RutherfordRutherford (1988) 68–70 and Reference RutherfordRutherford (2001a) 250–52 for analysis of Pindar’s accounts vis-à-vis the Homeric Hymn to Apollo. Just how difficult it is to reconcile the different versions presented by Pindar and the Hymn to Apollo is up for debate; see e.g. Reference RutherfordRutherford (2001a) 252 and n. 37 above (also pertinent for other matters in this paragraph).

102 Reference D’AlessioD’Alessio (1995) 170–71 observes the relationship between the εὐμαχανία for which Pindar appeals to the Muses (Pae. 7b.16–17, cf. Pae. 6.53) and the condition of ἀμηχανίη that plagues mortals in Parm. Fr. 6.5 – in both cases, mortals are afflicted by blindness (τυφλοί at Parm. Fr. 6.7; [τ]υφλα̣[ὶ] … φρένες at Pae. 7b.18) and struggle to find the correct hodos. See also Reference RanzatoRanzato (2015) 128–29, 142 Footnote n. 56. Finally, some scholars reject that μαχανία has any epistemological valence; for Reference StamatopoulouStamatopoulou (2017) 47, the term denotes poetic competence instead.

103 See esp. Reference RutherfordRutherford (2000), and also Reference HalliwellHalliwell (2011), ch. 2. Interestingly, the Homeric Hymns are not discussed by Finkelberg or her critics, such as Rutherford or Halliwell.

104 Reference Burkert, Bowersock, Burkert and PutnamBurkert (1979) 62; Reference Burkert and CairnsBurkert (2001) 110–12; Reference JankoJanko (1982) 112–13; Reference WestWest (2003) 9–12; Reference West, Andersen and HaugWest (2011b) 241. See also Reference AloniAloni (1989) and Reference AloniAloni (1998) 65–78. It is striking to see West and Janko so closely in agreement, though they disagree on which portion came first (notably, others, including Reference ClayClay (1989), assert that the poem was composed all at once; see Reference Chappell and FaulknerChappell (2011) for further discussion). Reference Burkert, Bowersock, Burkert and PutnamBurkert (1979) 42 points out that the Delian portion of the poem presupposes the construction of a temple to Apollo and Delos, which has been dated to 540–530.

105 The more so if one accepts the view that the Homeric Hymns fill the gap between Hesiod’s Theogony and the age of heroes recounted in Homeric epic and that ‘[e]ach hymn describes an epoch-making moment in the mythic chronology of Olympus and, as such, inaugurates a new era in the divine and human cosmos’ (Reference ClayClay (1989) 15). For a useful overview of scholarship on this topic, see Reference Chappell and FaulknerChappell (2011).

109 Reference 320Clay and FaulknerClay (2011b) 235. Put differently: ‘if epic makes the heroic past present, the Hymns make the divine present’ (Reference 320Clay and FaulknerClay (2011b) 236).

110 Finally, if the Hymn to Apollo we have was formed by merging two pre-existing poems, or by adding a second portion to an older hymn to Apollo, we would see one example of the epic rhetoric of traditionality in action; unlike Pindar, who highlights a number of different versions of the same myth, and then evaluates the veracity, or at least the merits, of each, the poet responsible for the Hymn to Apollo would have found an ingenious way of incorporating both into a single, true, whole.

112 Reference HalliwellHalliwell (2011) vi and 67, respectively.

113 Reference HalliwellHalliwell (2011) 67 and 54, respectively.

114 The pattern is hardly limited to fellow travellers: see e.g. Reference LedbetterLedbetter (2003), who gives the Greek and the English in full twice (pp. 17, 21) and translates the English again at p. 47; likewise Reference PrattPratt (1993) 47–52. Reference ClayClay (2011a), who begins her discussion of Homeric poetics by quoting Il. 2.484–93 in full, observes that this is the locus classicus ‘from which every discussion of Homeric poetics takes its start’ (16); see, since then, Reference Graziosi, Marmadoro and HillGraziosi (2013) 71–72, and earlier classics such as Reference NagyNagy (1979) 16, Reference FordFord (1992) 60–62, Reference Scodel and WatsonScodel (2001) 109, and Reference ScodelScodel (2002) 71–72.

115 Reference 324FinkelbergFinkelberg (1998) 48, and esp. 71, where Il. 2.484–93 provides the foundation for her discussion of Homeric poetics in the crucial third chapter of her book.

116 Reference HalliwellHalliwell (2011) 58, and see 61 Footnote n. 49 for the sole discussion of Iliad 2’s Invocation of the Muses in its own right; it is downgraded on Halliwell’s telling to one of five ‘localized’ ‘invocations … tied to particular narrative details’ (p. 61). See also 57 Footnote n. 39, a section on invocations in general.

117 Reference 324FinkelbergFinkelberg (1998) 131–50. See also Reference RutherfordRutherford (2000) and Reference HalliwellHalliwell (2011) 57 Footnote n. 40; for bardic practice and bardic self-presentation, see e.g. Reference FordFord (1992) 90–130.

118 Less pressing would have been the challenges facing Pindar or even Hecataeus, that of being crowded out by competing and incompatible versions of myths, some of them already in Homer’s name; rather, it is Xenophanean scepticism, and perhaps Ionian enantiomorphism, that would have provided his chief obstacles and targets. For enantiomorphism and adjacent concepts, see esp. Reference CurdCurd (1998b), also Mourelatos (1973), Reference 340MourelatosMourelatos (1999), Reference MillerMiller (2006), and Reference TorTor (2017).

119 Reference RobbianoRobbiano (2006) 62–74 makes good use of Genette’s notion of a ‘paratext’ to characterize the proem. A paratext is ‘a zone not only of transition but also of transaction’ where one deploys ‘pragmatics and a strategy’, a ‘threshold’, a ‘vestibule’ or ‘“undefined zone” between the inside and the outside’ (Reference GenetteGenette (1997) 1–2; emphasis original). One could hardly find a more apt description of the proem’s function.

120 Also noted by Reference TorTor (2017) 313. For another discussion of Parmenides and the genre of the hymn – with some characteristically sharp insights – see Reference CalameCalame (2013).

121 See Ch. 5 below, also Reference TorTor (2017) 347–59 for a systematic analysis of scholarship on the proem.

122 See n. 125, also Section 2.4.5 below; for an example of this logic applied to the proem in a fruitful way, see e.g. Reference MillerMiller (2006).

123 Reference CosgroveCosgrove (2011) 38–39. Cosgrove (38 Footnote n. 65) attributes the term to Mourelatos, who first suggested a similar interpretation in print in 1970; he also cites approvingly Boeder’s conclusion that the goddess ‘empfängt ihn dem “Jenseits” zu allen Erscheinungen’ (Reference Boeder(1962) 121). This view accords with what Reference TorTor (2017) 359, following Curd, styles the ‘we’re not in Kansas anymore’ view. Reference SchofieldSchofield (1987) 357 frames the matter well: ‘[t]he implicit question tackled in Fr. 1 is: “What puts someone in the position to raise and understand the goddess’s questions of Fr. 2?”’

125 See e.g. Reference TaránTarán (1965) 15–16, 31; Reference MourelatosMourelatos (2008b) [1970]; Reference Coxon and McKirahanCoxon (2009) 280–81; Reference FloydFloyd (1992) 255; Reference MillerMiller (2006); Reference TorTor (2017) 355 Footnote n. 25. If, as I shall discuss below, Parmenides’ situation requires him to mobilize as fully as possible the resources of myth, religious ritual, and extended deductive argument, why close doors to any powerful registers of meaning-making and cultural practices that could be of service in this great struggle to announce truth? See also pp. 109–110, 241–47 below.

127 Reference Nightingale and ShapiroNightingale (2007) 190, and Reference GrangerGranger (2008), to be discussed at greater length below, are welcome exceptions to the tendency to focus solely on Hesiod’s Muses at Homer’s Muses’ expense.

129 See e.g. Palmer (2009) 378–380 for discussion and e.g. Mourelatos (2008b) xxxiv for a counterpoint.

131 It should be acknowledged that asserting a strong set of links between Hesiod and Parmenides is one of the core planks of Tor’s thesis, and it is thus understandable that Hesiod should be the main point of bardic reference (as indeed Homer is in this book). It is nevertheless still wrong to relegate Homer to the background and ignore the closer connections between Il. 2.485–86 and Od. 12.27–141 and Parm. Fr. 1.29–30 and what follows.

134 Of course, the dichotomy between gods and mortals suffuses the general ambience of the opening passage of Hesiod (and may be implied by the derogatory comments of Th. 26), but it is not stated, and it is not a constitutive feature of the dichotomy articulated that Hesiod’s Muses do articulate.

137 See esp. Ch. 5, also Ch. 6 for a much deeper elaboration of the many linguistic, dramatic, conceptual, and discursive connections between the tissue of Parmenides’ fragments 1.21–32, 2, 6, 7, and 8.1–49 and Od. 12.27–141.

138 Reference TorTor (2017) 312. Some have even gone so far as to suggest that the birth of historiography cannot be understood otherwise; see e.g. Reference MarincolaMarincola (2007) 35–37, 55–57 for the influence of Odyssey 9–12 on historiographers from Hecataeus onwards. See also Reference GrangerGranger (2008) 10.

139 And, as in Homeric invocation of the Muse, there is one line for the complete truth of the immortals and one for the low ignorance of men. Or as in the cave of the Nymphs, where there are two hodoi, one for the immortals, one for men (Od. 13.109–12); or as there are two gates for dreams, ivory for the deceptive, horn for the etuma (Od. 19.560–69).

140 See Reference PalmerPalmer (2009) 378–80 for discussion; see also e.g. Reference MourelatosMourelatos (2008b) xxxiv for a counterpoint.

141 The Muses are appealed to, but they register no expressly stated presence, be it in bodily or vocal form, in the text; see Reference de Jongde Jong (1987), esp. 45–53; Reference RichardsonRichardson (1990) 181–82.

142 See Reference Noussia-FantuzziNoussia-Fantuzzi (2010) 393–98 for a survey of recent interpretations of the line.

143 See discussion in Maehler (1975), Reference RutherfordRutherford (2001a), Reference LedbetterLedbetter (2003), and Reference MaslovMaslov (2015) 197–200. As we saw above, Fr. 150 is also cited by Reference GrangerGranger (2007) in support of his argument. See here also Bacchylides Fr. 9.1–6 (Maehler). How one translates the phrase depends in part on how one interprets the relationship in question; Race gives: ‘Give me an oracle, Muse, and I shall be your prophet’, Maslov (2015) 197: ‘Muse, be a seer, and I will be a prophatas (“prophet/promulgator”).’

144 Reference TorTor (2017) 104–30, esp. 104–16, for discussions of divination in the time of Xenophanes; Reference Dillery, Johnston and StruckDillery (2005) and Reference FlowerFlower (2008) provide an important backdrop here.

145 Reference GrangerGranger (2007) 410, with full argument at 409–11; cf. Pl. Ap. 21b.

146 Reference MaslovMaslov (2015) 201, more generally 197–201. Note that this sense of ‘mouthpiece’ is thus very different from e.g. Finkelberg’s discussion of Homer’s Muses.

147 See Reference MaslovMaslov (2015), n. 37 above.

148 The dichotomies are to be found in Reference de Jongde Jong (1992), esp. the concluding remarks on p. 10, with reference to categories explored in the Reference GriffinGriffin (1986), Reference BeckBeck (2005), and Reference BakkerBakker (2013).

151 E.g. Reference KingsleyKingsley (1999) and Reference KingsleyKingsley (2003), Reference RobbianoRobbiano (2006), Reference Gemelli MarcianoGemelli Marciano (2008), Reference Gemelli Marciano, Rossetti and PulpitoGemelli Marciano (2013), Reference RanzatoRanzato (2015), Reference TorTor (2017), and earlier proposed or adumbrated by Reference BurkertBurkert (1969), Reference FeyerabendFeyerabend (1984), and Reference SassiSassi (1988). Of course, to the extent that these readings, such as Reference Gemelli Marciano, Rossetti and PulpitoGemelli Marciano (2013), are deemed to be incompatible with an account of Parmenides that emphasizes the role of extended deductive argumentation, there is indeed ipso facto an incompatibility, but this is imposed from the other side, as it were.

152 Reference TorTor (2017), esp. 11–60, 338–46.

153 Reference RanzatoRanzato (2015), esp. 15–16; see Introduction, Footnote n. 28 for important predecessors.

154 Reference GrangerGranger (2008) 14; he then goes on to discuss this phenomenon in relation to the Invocation of the Muses in Iliad 2 (Reference GrangerGranger (2008) 15); see, for similar dynamics, Reference Laks, Humphreys and WagnerLaks (2013), who differentiates between ‘phenomena’ and ‘references’, and a process of rationalization (an analogue of Granger’s demythologization) in the transition from the first to the second.

155 See Footnote n. 124 above.

156 Reference Most and LongMost (1999a) 350. See discussion in the Introduction, esp. pp. 5–6.

157 See Footnote n. 4 above.

159 As Reference Kahn and YunisKahn (2003) 156 observes in his discussion of Xenophanes’ use of verse, ‘[i]n the sixth century, elegiac verse was used for the pamphleteering function that was served by the funeral oration in Plato’s day’; see also e.g. Reference SiderSider (2006) and Reference GagnéGagné (2009) esp. 28–30.

160 Reference SiderSider (2006) 338–39. For reference, Reference West, Finglass and KellyWest (2015) 66 imagines the length of Mimnermus’ elegiac Smyrneis and Simonides’ elegies on the battles of Artemesium and Plataea to have been of ‘considerable length’, possibly running into the hundreds of lines; Stesichorus’ Geryoneis is estimated to be 1,300 lines at a minimum (Reference Kelly, Finglass and KellyFinglass and Kelly (2015) 7).

161 For the debate about whether his histories of the founding of Colophon and Elea are in elegiac or epic metre, see Reference LulliLulli (2011) 42–46. The key question concerns the best interpretation of epē in Diogenes Laertius 9.20. The increasing scholarly interest in elegy has shifted opinion away from the older idea that Xenophanes composed in hexameter to the view the composed in elegiacs; see esp. Reference BowieBowie (1986) 31–32.

163 For discussions of the shadowy guild of bards, such as the Homeridae, see Reference Burkert and CairnsBurkert (2001) 102–03; Reference Cassio and MontanariCassio (2002). Such figures as Panyassis and Cheorilus, later to be elevated by Hellenistic scholars to the all-star club of epic poets including Homer and Hesiod, should also be taken into account; see here esp. Reference LulliLulli (2011).

164 The most recent edition of Parmenides’s poem includes 161 lines attributed to Parmenides; LM 3–4. Scholars have long imagined Doxa to be longer than Alētheia; according to Diels’s influential reconstruction, the seventy-eight surviving lines of Alētheia represent nine tenths of the whole section, while ‘according to a less certain appraisal, perhaps 1/10 of the Doxa’ is represented by the forty-four verses that survive (Reference DielsDiels (1897) 25–26). This adds up to thirty-two lines of the proem, roughly eighty-five lines for Alētheia, and ~400–450 for Doxa, or around 510–560 lines in total (or perhaps even substantially less: LM 4 reckon the poem’s total length to be 300–400 words). For a different view, see Reference KurfessKurfess (2016).

165 While it would be an overstatement to compare this act to Pierre Menard’s twentieth-century edition of Don Quixote – the lengthy Hymn to Hermes, for example, is often dated to ~480 BCE (see e.g. Reference West, Andersen and HaugWest (2011b)) – it is not unhelpful to spend at least a bit of time examining it in such terms, especially when considering other arguments advanced to explain Parmenides’ use of verse. This is especially true for what we might dub an ‘anchoring innovation’ school who suggest, first, that the perplexities of radical new material are rendered more easily digestible by anchoring it in the familiar old garb of epic; and, second, that the new points thus stand out more clearly, the better to be brought to the audience’s attention for further examination; see here Reference PfeifferPfeiffer (1975) 61; Reference Wright and AthertonWright (1997); Reference Wöhrle, Kullmann and AlthoffWöhrle (1993), esp. 173–74; Reference Most and LongMost (1999a) 355; Reference GrangerGranger (2008) 14; and for anchoring innovation, Reference SluiterSluiter (2017). The effect of using dactylic hexameter to expound one’s physical or metaphysical theories will have been far less radical, of course, for anyone (Empedocles, for example) writing in the shadow of Parmenides.

166 For strong arguments that dactylic hexameter is precisely what one would expect from a Parmenides who puts his message in the mouth of his goddess, see esp. Reference Kahn and YunisKahn (2003) 157; Reference Most and LongMost (1999a) 355; Reference MansfeldMansfeld (1964) 273; Reference TaránTarán (1977) 654; Reference TorTor (2017); also Reference ReinhardtReinhardt (1916) 301–02.

167 For this translation of the problematic lines 24–26 of Ibycus’ ‘Polycrates Ode’ and for a discussion of other alternatives, see n. 45 above.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×