Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T03:20:09.762Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

DIVIDED POWER AND ΕΥΝΟΜΙΑ: DELIBERATIVE PROCEDURES IN ANCIENT SPARTA

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 September 2017

Alberto Esu*
Affiliation:
The University of Edinburgh
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Spartan institutions were pictured as a model of political stability from the Classical period onwards. The so-called Spartan ‘mirage’ did not involve only its constitutional order but also social and economic institutions. Xenophon begins his Constitution of the Lacedaemonians by associating Spartan fame with the politeia set up by Lycurgus, which made the Laconian city the most powerful (δυνατωτάτη) and famous (ὀνομαστοτάτη) polis in Greece (Xen. Lac. 1.1). In Aristotle's Politics, in which the assessment of Sparta is more complex and nuanced, one finds a critique of contemporary Spartan institutions as well as praise for Lycurgus as a great lawgiver who established the laws of Sparta (Arist. Pol. 2.1269a69, 2.1273b20). Most other ancient sources often remark upon the unchangeable features of some Spartan institutions as a key aspect of Spartan εὐνομία. Thucydides maintains that, after a long period of war and stasis, the Dorians established excellent laws and Sparta employed the same constitution for more than four hundred years (Thuc. 1.18.1: τετρακόσια καὶ ὀλίγῳ πλείω ἐς τὴν τελευτὴν τοῦδε τοῦ πολέμου ἀφ᾽ οὗ Λακεδαιμόνιοι τῇ αὐτῇ πολιτείᾳ χρῶνται).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Classical Association 2017 

I. INTRODUCTION

Spartan institutions were pictured as a model of political stability from the Classical period onwards.Footnote 1 The so-called Spartan ‘mirage’ did not involve only its constitutional order but also social and economic institutions.Footnote 2 Xenophon begins his Constitution of the Lacedaemonians by associating Spartan fame with the politeia set up by Lycurgus, which made the Laconian city the most powerful (δυνατωτάτη) and famous (ὀνομαστοτάτη) polis in Greece (Xen. Lac. 1.1).Footnote 3 In Aristotle's Politics, in which the assessment of Sparta is more complex and nuanced, one finds a critique of contemporary Spartan institutions as well as praise for Lycurgus as a great lawgiver who established the laws of Sparta (Arist. Pol. 2.1269a69, 2.1273b20).Footnote 4 Most other ancient sources often remark upon the unchangeable features of some Spartan institutions as a key aspect of Spartan εὐνομία. Thucydides maintains that, after a long period of war and stasis, the Dorians established excellent laws and Sparta employed the same constitution for more than four hundred years (Thuc. 1.18.1: τετρακόσια καὶ ὀλίγῳ πλείω ἐς τὴν τελευτὴν τοῦδε τοῦ πολέμου ἀφ᾽ οὗ Λακεδαιμόνιοι τῇ αὐτῇ πολιτείᾳ χρῶνται).Footnote 5

This ancient invention of the ideal Spartan constitution and of its legendary lawgiver Lycurgus has been long recognized in scholarship.Footnote 6 Cartledge has pointed out how the ‘partly distorted and partly invented’ view of Sparta was due to non-Spartans.Footnote 7 In an essay published in 2002, however, Flower has shown that the Spartans themselves were not immune from inventing their own past during the Classical and the Hellenistic periods. This outcome was often reached by attributing contemporary institutional and social innovations to Lycurgus according to an ideological attitude that is also well known with regard to Solon and the πάτριος πολιτεία in fourth-century Athens.Footnote 8 Yet, Hodkinson has shown in several important studies how this view of Sparta as an exceptional and static society within the Greek world during the Archaic and the Classical periods is in need of revision.Footnote 9 In fact, most of the evidence about the institutions, the economy and the society of Sparta does not reflect the actual Archaic and Classical Spartan κόσμος but results from later invention, which is aimed at shaping collective memory about the past, and is consistent with reforms of the Hellenistic period.

This is especially true when it comes to studying the Spartan political institutions and deliberative practices. The preservation of the Great Rhetra, the alleged ‘founding’ constitutional document of Sparta, has given rise to a long debate about the origin of Spartan institutions. The text of the Rhetra, preserved in Plutarch's Life of Lycurgus (Plut. Lyc. 6.1–10), reports a document from the lost Aristotelian Constitution of the Lacedaemonians and an additional clause, the so-called ‘rider’, which Plutarch attributes to Kings Theopompus and Polydorus.Footnote 10 This document details the constitutional structure and the deliberative procedures of Sparta traditionally attributed to Lycurgus and based on the interaction between three institutions: the two kings, the Council of Elders (γερουσία) and the δᾶμος. Nafissi has recently demonstrated that the Rhetra does not, in fact, outline the original foundation of the Spartan constitution; rather, it is a piece of retrospective history elaborated and accepted by Archaic Spartan society.Footnote 11 The Rhetra marks the moment of institutionalization of the Spartan community between the seventh century and the sixth century, and is itself a first attempt of dating back their institutions to a remote past.Footnote 12

Although the Rhetra cannot be used for exploring the foundation of the Spartan political system, it is important evidence for the working of Spartan institutions at the time when it was composed. It provides a brief account of the three most important Spartan institutions, which are still attested during the Classical and the Hellenistic periods along with the fundamental office of the five ephors, not mentioned in the text of the Rhetra. Spartan deliberation was the result of a complex interaction between the Council of Elders (Gerousia), the ephors and the Assembly. The Gerousia and the ephors constituted the most important boards of officials in Sparta. They shared the probouleutic power and checked the legality of the enactments of the Spartan Assembly, which ratified the proposals of the γέροντες and the ephors.Footnote 13

There is, however, no consensus amongst scholars about the actual workings and the balance of power among deliberative bodies of ancient Sparta. Some scholars have stressed the fundamental oligarchic features of Spartan deliberation, in which the Assembly played a marginal role, whereas powerful officials made all the decisions.Footnote 14 By contrast, Ruzé has argued that the text of the Rhetra already envisaged a right of free speech for the δᾶμος, which could actively shape Spartan policy-making.Footnote 15 In particular, Ruzé’s approach dismisses the official role of the Gerousia in the probouleutic procedure, by arguing for an informal probouleusis (προβούλευσις) during which the δᾶμος debated preliminary proposals without however taking a formal vote. Conversely, in a recent monograph on the Homeric councils and the Spartan Gerousia Schulz has made the case for a prominent role of the Gerousia in Sparta's institutional system, and has provided a picture of the legislative procedure in which the γέροντες played a key role. Although Schulz recognizes that the decision-making process was achieved through interaction between the Gerousia and the ephors, he argues that, when there was no consensus amongst the γέροντες about a motion to submit before the δᾶμος, the ephor did not introduce the bill to the Assembly, but an advisory assembly was actually gathered to check the people's opinion informally, and only after this passage could the Gerousia either submit or veto the draft through their probouleutic power before an actual vote of the Assembly.Footnote 16 These approaches are, however, problematic, for several reasons. First, there is no evidence of informal or advisory meetings of the people's Assembly in Greek deliberative practice tout court, especially in non-democratic contexts, and this assumption is mainly based on the idea of Sparta's exceptionality. Second, Schulz's reconstruction fails to isolate the difference between the power of probouleusis and the power of nomophylakia (νομοφυλακία), which was performed by the Gerousia’s veto of decision after the debate in the Assembly.

It is my contention in this article that the Spartan decision-making process shared with the Athenian decision-making process the principle of ‘divided power’, as is clearly shown by historical evidence regarding the role of the Gerousia and the ephors in the deliberative procedures of Classical and Hellenistic Sparta. Pasquino has recently introduced the concept of ‘divided power’ to the study of ancient Greek institutions in his analysis of fourth-century Athenian democracy. He defines the Athenian constitution as a ‘divided power’ because of the absence of ‘monocratic governmental agencies’, as no single institution could run the entire decision-making process.Footnote 17 Although Pasquino's analysis is strongly reliant on Hansen's problematic claim of an institutional superiority of the law courts in the fourth-century Athenian constitution, the principle of ‘divided power’ conveys effectively the set of constitutional balances of the Athenian institutional system.Footnote 18 In Sparta, too, deliberation was the result of a complex interaction, and particularly regarding the institutional relationship between the Gerousia, the ephors and the δᾶμος. The balance of power and a sound legal order are key features of the Greek poleis since the Archaic period. Εὐνομία (eunomia) is the term that Spartans and other Greek communities used to refer to this kind of political system, which preserved freedom under the laws, and was regarded as typical of the Greek poleis in opposition to tyranny (Hdt. 1.65; 7.104; Thuc. 1.18.1).Footnote 19 Indeed, when Sparta's institutions were devised, they were not conceptualised as an oligarchy in opposition to a democracy. The opposing pair oligarchy–democracy became prominent in Greek politics and political thought only from the second half of the fifth century, and Spartan understanding of their regime as non-democratic emerged later, after the Peloponnesian War.Footnote 20 Just as in the other Greek poleis, the rule of law and ‘divided power’ were at the foundation of the Spartan constitution, defining the very aim of its institutions. These institutions and procedures, however, were marked (compared, for example, to those in Athens) by stronger devices to limit the power of the people, and to keep it in check, while, at the same time, recognising its formal authority. It was, as at Athens, a case of ‘divided power’, but one with explicit protection of the deliberative power of the elite vis-à-vis that of the δᾶμος—a power that was maintained, path-dependently, through complex procedures and institutional steps from the Archaic period to the Hellenistic period. Thus, the interplay between different governmental bodies followed these ideological patterns of the Spartan politeia, which gave the probouleutic bodies—the Gerousia and the ephors—the power to shape policy-making through the powers of probouleusis and nomophylakia. Neither of these governmental agencies, however, had exclusive control over these functions, which were in fact divided between the ephors and the γέροντες. The study of the practical workings of this constitutional mechanism underscores the complexity of Sparta's institutional equilibrium and the features of ‘divided power’ in practice within a non-democratic political system.

This essay examines the two most detailed ancient accounts (Diod. Sic. 11.50.2–7; Plut. Agis 8.1–11.1) concerning the workings of Spartan deliberation. It begins by sketching an overview of Spartan political institutions and their functions within the theoretical framework of New Historical Institutionalism (section II). I shall then focus on the analysis of the literary sources in order to reconstruct the interactive relationship between distinct governmental bodies, in particular the interplay between the two probouleutic bodies, the Gerousia and the ephors, and the Spartan Assembly in the process of deliberation (section III). This will shed light on the constitutional workings as well as on the ideological features of Spartan deliberation by focussing on the powers of probouleusis and nomophylakia shared by γέροντες and ephors.

II. SPARTAN DECISION-MAKING INSTITUTIONS: KINGS, GEROUSIA AND EPHORS

The two kings, the Gerousia and the ephors made up the three institutions that dominated Spartan political deliberation. The text of the Great Rhetra alludes to two of these institutions:Footnote 21 the γέροντες and the founders (ἀρχαγέται), a term interpreted by Plutarch as referring to the kings.Footnote 22 Although the Rhetra is a retrospective document, these references show that both the Gerousia and the Spartan kingship were already fully institutionalized in the early Archaic period.

During the Classical and the Hellenistic periods, the Spartan kings were formally limited in their power. In Xenophon's Constitution of the Lacedaemonians, one reads that the kings had to take an oath in which they swore to reign according to the established laws (Xen. Lac. 15.7: ὁ δὲ ὅρκος ἐστὶ τῷ μὲν βασιλεῖ κατὰ τοὺς τῆς πόλεως κειμένους νόμους βασιλεύσειν). Aristotle, in the Politics’ discussion of good kingship (1285a7), states that the Spartan constitution provides a kingship which is lawful and limited in its authority (ἡ γὰρ ἐν τῇ Λακωνικῇ πολιτείᾳ δοκεῖ μὲν εἶναι βασιλεία μάλιστα τῶν κατὰ νόμον, οὐκ ἔστι δὲ κυρία πάντων). He then defines the nature of Spartan kingship as a kind of supreme generalship for life (αὕτη μὲν οὖν ἡ βασιλεία οἷον στρατηγία τις αὐτοκρατόρων καὶ ἀίδιός ἐστιν). As recent studies have pointed out, although the two kings were limited in their constitutional power, they could enjoy significant charisma-based authority grounded in the mythical origin of the Heraclid dyarchy as well as in their wealth and broad powers during military campaigns, especially during the Hellenistic period.Footnote 23 Harris has noted that the Spartan military success was partly due to the balance between legal controls over the kings and the need of a centralized military command. This institutional design prevented the kings from acquiring too much power without interfering with the unity of command necessary for military efficiency on campaign.Footnote 24

More interestingly for our purpose, as the text of the Rhetra shows, the two kings along with the twenty-eight γέροντες constituted a collegial institution, the Gerousia.Footnote 25 The Gerousia, however, should not be interpreted as a ‘royal Council’. As several sources confirm, the kings’ votes had the same weight as those of the other γέροντες,Footnote 26 and, as I shall show in detail later, during the Hellenistic period the kings even needed the support of the ephors to introduce motions to the Gerousia.

Unlike the Athenian Boulē, made up of five hundred citizens appointed by lot every year, the Spartan Gerousia was constituted of only thirty members appointed for life (Aeschin. 1.180; Arist. Pol. 1270b39, 1272a36; Plut. Lyc. 6, 26.1; Paus. 3.5.2; Plut. Ages. 4.2.).Footnote 27 Ancient evidence confirms that the Gerousia was the most respected and prestigious Spartan institution, according to the typical values of aristocratic constitutions, such as καλοκἀγαθία, σωφροσύνη and ἀρετή.Footnote 28 According to Aristotle's Politics, the Gerousia represented the aristocratic element of the Spartan mixed constitution, and its members were the καλοὶ κἀγαθοί.Footnote 29 As Aristotle states (Pol. 1270b24–5), in Sparta the different parts (μέρη) of the city kept their relevant roles allowing the endurance of the constitution: the kings received their honour (διὰ τὴν αὐτῶν τιμήν), the people held the ephorate (διὰ τὴν ἐφορείαν), and the καλοὶ κἀγαθοί were entitled to the membership of the Gerousia as an award for their individual merits and virtues (οἱ δὲ καλοὶ κἀγαθοὶ διὰ τὴν γερουσίαν, ἆθλον γὰρ ἡ ἀρχὴ αὕτη τῆς ἀρετῆς ἐστιν), which the Spartan civic community highly respected, although the only formal requirement for appointment to the Gerousia was that the candidate had reached the age of sixty.Footnote 30 This is also confirmed by Xenophon, who states that Lycurgus was a good lawgiver for having established the Gerousia, which makes it possible for the γέροντες to show off their virtues (Xen. Lac. 10.1–3). In the speech Against Leptines (Dem. 20.107), Demosthenes employs an expression similar to that used in Aristotle's Politics, stating that the Gerousia is the master of the Spartan politeia and a reward for merit (τῆς ἀρετῆς ἆθλον). Such values played a very important role in shaping the institutional task of the γέροντες and the nature of their political decisions in the legislative and deliberative procedure.

This seems to be confirmed by the appointment procedure of the γέροντες—described by Plutarch—in which the δᾶμος played an important role in the election of the candidates by shouting (Plut. Lyc. 26).Footnote 31 They declared as elected whoever received the longest and loudest shouts (ὅτῳ δὲ πλείστη γένοιτο καὶ μεγίστη, τοῦτον ἀνηγόρευον). In the Politics Aristotle disapproves the voting procedure for electing the γέροντες and labels it as ‘childish’ (παιδαριώδης), a term that he employs also for the appointment of the ephors (Pol. 1270b28, 1271a10).Footnote 32 Aristotle does not justify his severe judgement, but it is likely that he is referring to the same acclamatory procedure described by Plutarch. In spite of Aristotelian criticism, the acclamatory shouts of the Spartan δᾶμος reflected a voting procedure embedded with precise ideological features. As Schwartzberg argues, by voting through acclamation, the Spartans in the Assembly secured a collective result for the election, in which the individual votes were not counted, because of the different levels of ‘epistemic dignity’ among the members of the civic community as a whole.Footnote 33 As already shown, the Gerousia voted by majority rule, because the political and epistemic weight of each γέρων—including the two kings—was the same but also higher than that of the common citizen of the Assembly. The δᾶμος, on the other hand, voted as a collective deliberative body, showing the will of the community through acclamation. This different voting system also had relevant consequences for the legislative process, as I will show later when analysing the veto powers of the Gerousia.

The collective vote of the whole citizen-community in selecting the γέροντες was an important acknowledgement of the moral and political virtues of the Elders as representatives of the δᾶμος within the Gerousia. Once elected by the δᾶμος, the γέροντες held several honours, which were broadly similar to those for the winners of athletic contests. A new γέρων wore a crown and visited the temples followed by a procession of young men and women praising him with songs. He then went to the common mess in which he received a double portion that he should offer to one of his female relatives, whom he esteemed the most.Footnote 34 Such considerable honours for the new γέροντες were not excessive in light of the broad powers of the Gerousia. The Council of Elders, including the kings, had exclusive judicial powers in lawsuits in which the penalty was death, ἀτιμία or exile (Xen. Lac. 10.1; Arist. Pol. 1294b29; Plut. Lyc. 26).Footnote 35 The Gerousia was also involved in trials of the kings, but in this case the law court was composed of twenty-eight γέροντες, the other king and the ephors.Footnote 36

Despite the fact that they are not mentioned in the Rhetra, the ephors were fundamental to the Spartan decision-making process. The ephorate was established after the Rhetra was composed, by the creation of a board of five officials.Footnote 37 Evidence for the origin of the ephorate is lacking, and the story about their origin in connection with Κing Theopompus is a later tradition (Arist. Pol. 1313a25–33). As Nafissi suggests, it is likely that the office was instituted during the sixth century reflecting the institutional consolidation of the political community.Footnote 38 Its members were the highest magistrates of Sparta—one of whom was the eponym—elected by the δᾶμος for one year, possibly with the same procedure used to elect the γέροντες.Footnote 39 As suggested by their name, the ephors had to oversee (ἐφορᾶν) the respect of nomoi as well as the behaviour of the individual citizens (Xen. Lac. 8.3). The kings were also subject to close control by the ephors, who accompanied one of the kings during military campaigns or, as we saw, could prosecute them in a trial. They also had jurisdiction over areas which in Athens were supervised by the Council, such as the mobilization of the army, public order, public finance, religion and the supervision of other officials (Arist. Pol. 1271a6–7).Footnote 40

The interaction between ephorate and Gerousia was not confined to the judicial sphere but was particularly prominent in political deliberation. As was typical of Greek institutional practice, the Council had probouleutic power, which in Sparta was shared between the Council of Elders and the ephors. If one compares Spartan probouleusis with its Athenian equivalent, it is immediately clear that Sparta shows a peculiar constitutional pattern. In Athens the probouleutic power was held by the Boulē, which submitted προβουλεύματα to the Assembly. There were no other institutions entitled to prepare the agenda or to submit formal proposals to the dēmos.Footnote 41 The Athenian Assembly could only discuss items put in the agenda by the Council. For example, when Nicias tried to have the πρυτάνεις put a motion to the vote about the expedition to Sicily, which was not on the agenda of the Assembly, he knew that he was doing something illegal, because his proposal did not follow the probouleutic procedure and was not in a προβούλευμα of the Council (Thuc. 6.14).Footnote 42 In Sparta, on the other hand, probouleusis was not exercised by a single institutional agency but by both the Gerousia and the ephors according to different procedures, which shows that this fundamental power was actually ‘divided’. Unlike in democratic contexts, however, the interplay between the deliberative institutions reflects different institutional values, embedded in the constitutional design and therefore in the non-democratic features of the Spartan politeia. Spartan institutions evolved from the archaic arrangement shown by the Rhetra, for example, by introducing the board of five ephors. Nevertheless, political institutions changed path-dependently—according to New Historical Institutionalism terminology—and preserved, to an extent, functions, features and values of the εὐνομία which originally shaped them. These values, embedded in the relevant institutions, preserved the balance of powers as well as the stability of the legal order, and were still found in the workings of the deliberative institutions in the Hellenistic period, with consequences for the workings of decision-making.Footnote 43 With this framework in mind, one can analyse the literary evidence from Diodorus and especially from Plutarch's Life of Agis. These sources offer an account of Spartan deliberation in practice in the Hellenistic period, and a careful analysis will reveal the institutional and ideological patterns of the Spartan decision-making process.

III. INTERACTION BETWEEN EPHORS AND GEROUSIA: ‘DIVIDED’ PROBOULEUSIS AND NOMOPHYLAKIA

In Aristotle's Politics one finds the theoretical description of the workings of probouleusis in oligarchic regimes. At 1298b26–35 he states that in oligarchies there are probouleutic magistrates, called πρόβουλοι or νομοφύλακες,Footnote 44 who put forward proposals to the dēmos, which can only discuss these motions. The dēmos cannot advance or debate proposals, except those already approved by these magistrates (ἔτι ἢ ταὐτὰ ψηφίζεσθαι τὸν δῆμον ἢ μηθὲν ἐναντίον τοῖς εἰσφερομένοις).Footnote 45 If one compares the Aristotelian account with the text of the Great Rhetra, it seems clear that Aristotle's statement matches the procedures envisaged in the Great Rhetra as well as in Spartan institutional practice. The text of the Great Rhetra is the following:

Διὸς Συλλανίου καὶ Ἀθανᾶς Συλλανίας ἱερὸν ἱδρυσάμενον, φυλὰς φυλάξαντα καὶ ὠβὰς ὠβάξαντα, τριάκοντα γερουσίαν σὺν ἀρχαγέταις καταστήσαντα, ὥρας ἐξ ὥρας ἀπελλάζειν μεταξὺ Βαβύκας τε καὶ Κνακιῶνος, οὕτως εἰσφέρειν τε καὶ ἀφίστασθαι δάμῳ <…> καὶ κράτος. […] αἱ δὲ σκολιὰν ὁ δᾶμος ἕλοιτο, τοὺς πρεσβυγενέας καὶ ἀρχαγέτας ἀποστατῆρας ἦμεν.

Having founded a cult of Zeus Syllanios and Athena Syllania, having divided the people [or ‘kept the divisions’] in tribes and having divided it in obai, having appointed a council of thirty members, including the founders, regularly celebrate the Apellai between Babyka and Knakion. Bring forward and reject [proposals] as follows: to the people must go <…> and final decision, […] but if the people speaks crookedly [or ‘asks for something crooked’] the elders and the founders are to be rejecters. (trans. Nafissi)

The text of the Great Rhetra shows that, during the Archaic period, the Gerousia and the kings had the power of putting proposals before the Assembly (οὕτως εἰσφέρειν τε καὶ ἀφίστασθαι).Footnote 46 The ‘rider’ also implies that the Gerousia could veto motions of the Assembly in case the δᾶμος ‘speaks crookedly’, which means that the Assembly could not pass an enactment contrary to the Gerousia’s proposal without the possibility of being vetoed—a clear example of the power of nomophylakia of the γέροντες (Plut. Lyc. 6.3).

Evidence for the working of deliberation in Classical and in Hellenistic Sparta is scanty. The very same terms probouleusis and nomophylakia, used in accordance with Aristotle's usage, are not found in Sparta. The former, in Aristotle, indicates the power of the Council or of the probouleutic officials (or a collaboration between these two bodies) to set the agenda of the people's assemblies in order to achieve efficient deliberation. The latter function is the power to control the conformity of the motions of the Assembly to the general laws governing the life of the community. Both of these powers were fundamental to preserve balance between popular sovereignty and rule of law typical of the Greek poleis from the Archaic period onwards. In Greek normal institutional terminology, the two terms πρόβουλοι or νομοφύλακες (and cognates) were often used interchangeably to indicate special magistrates (and functions) with the power of drafting proposals and checking the legality of deliberations. For example, Plutarch uses the expression τὸ προβουλεύειν at Agis 11.1 to describe the powers of the Spartan γέροντες when vetoing Agis’ rhetra. In Plutarch's passage the term indicates that the γέροντες were acting as πρόβουλοι with their relevant powers of legislative review. In Aristotle's terminology that would constitute an exercise of nomophylakia. Despite the occasional terminological overlap, the Aristotelian classification shows that the two procedures were conceptually different, and they marked two different moments of the decision-making.Footnote 47 Even though neither term is found in Spartan practice, however, just as in most of the Greek poleis, the Spartan deliberative bodies performed those functions through the relevant legal procedures, and therefore the use of this terminology has significant heuristic value within a Greek perspective.

The only piece of evidence for the probouleutic procedure in fifth-century Sparta is provided by a slightly obscure passage in Diodorus. He describes a debate in Sparta in 475/474 b.c. after the conflict between the Greek poleis and the Persians (Diod. Sic. 11.50.1–7). The historical authenticity of these events seems dubious, even though recent scholarship accepts Diodorus’ account as trustworthy.Footnote 48 The historical events might be fictional, but it is hard to argue that the institutional framework is fictional: as Griffith pointed out, Ephorus—Diodorus’ source for this passage—can hardly be accused of ignoring Spartan deliberative procedures.Footnote 49 Diodorus narrates that the Gerousia was summoned (συναχθείσης δὲ τῆς γερουσίας) to deliberate on the possibility of making war against the Athenians (ἐβουλεύοντο περὶ τοῦ πολέμου), who had supremacy over the seas and had therefore become a threat for Sparta. Likewise, the Assembly was summoned (ὁμοίως δὲ καὶ τῆς κοινῆς ἐκκλησίας συναχθείσης) and the majority of the citizens agreed that Sparta had to gain leadership of the seas. Diodorus’ account seems at first glance to imply that a second meeting of the Gerousia was held (τῆς γερουσίας συνεδρευούσης περὶ τούτων), in which the γέροντες were about to make their decision by following the people's preference for war (Diod. Sic. 11.50.2–5). But Hetoimaridas, one of the γέροντες, persuaded both the Gerousia and the δᾶμος with his eloquence to change their mind. The problem with this account is that it excludes the ephors from the procedure, whereas other evidence pictures active interaction between the Gerousia and the ephors. As I argue below, in case of absence of unanimity within the Gerousia, the ephors could formally introduce a proposal to the δᾶμος for ratification, but this bill had then to be examined and voted again by a majority of γέροντες in order to be passed.

This is shown by the most detailed account of the political decision-making procedure in Sparta found in Plutarch's Life of Agis, which describes the legislative procedure during the Hellenistic period (Plut. Agis 8–11).Footnote 50 Plutarch's account is not immune from ideological bias, as it relies on the contemporary work of Phylarchus, who was fiercely criticized by Polybius for his dramatic historiographical style.Footnote 51 Yet, Polybius’ critiques should not be overestimated, as he himself adopted a biased perspective against Phylarchus because of his anti-Spartan attitude. In his analysis of the role of women in the Lives of Agis and Cleomenes, Powell shows how several details drawn from Phylarchus’ work are indeed plausible pieces of information from contemporary Sparta.Footnote 52 According to Plutarch, in 243/242 b.c. King Agis IV proposed an ambitious plan of reforms—remission of debts, distribution of land and extension of citizenship.Footnote 53 Agis succeeded in procuring the election of Lysander as ephor and through him the bill was put forward before the Gerousia (Plut. Agis 8.1: εὐθὺς εἰσέφερε δι᾽ αὐτοῦ ῥήτραν εἰς τοὺς γέροντας). The new rhetra, however, did not receive the unanimous favour of the γέροντες, who were divided in their opinions (γραφείσης δὲ τῆς ῥήτρας, καὶ τῶν γερόντων εἰς ταὐτὸ ταῖς γνώμαις οὐ συμφερομένων). Lysander thus summoned the Assembly (ἐκκλησίαν συναγαγὼν ὁ Λύσανδρος) to discuss the proposal (Plut. Agis 9.1). After a debate between Kings Agis and Leonidas, who supported the traditional κόσμος against Agis’ reforms, the Spartans backed Agis by passing his motion (τῷ μὲν Ἄγιδι τὸ πλῆθος ἐπηκολούθησεν). But the γέροντες eventually vetoed it through a majority vote (Plut. Agis 11.1), so that the reform never entered into force (τοὺς γέροντας, οἷς τὸ κράτος ἦν ἐν τῷ προβουλεύειν).

Building on these two literary accounts, several studies on Spartan legislative procedures have reconstructed it as characterized either by an unclear distribution of powers between ephors and Gerousia or by an ‘informal’ preparatory phase. Kelly, in his reconstruction of the procedure in Diodorus, highlights that the meeting of the Gerousia was held before the δᾶμος, which usually showed its mood through shouts, silence and applause.Footnote 54 As Diodorus makes clear (Diod. Sic. 11.50.5), the Gerousia was still in session when the δᾶμος expressed favour for war (πάντων δὲ σχεδὸν τῶν πολιτῶν πρὸς ταύτην τὴν ὑπόθεσιν ὡρμημένων, καὶ τῆς γερουσίας συνεδρευούσης περὶ τούτων). For this reason, Kelly argues that, when the γέροντες and the ephors—not mentioned by Diodorus—did not agree on a motion, they put their case before the Assembly and decided on the spot whether to put their motions to the vote in the Assembly. Thus, during the same meeting, Hetoimaridas persuaded the γέροντες to put his motion to the vote, which was passed by the δᾶμος. Kelly envisages the very same procedure in Plutarch's account on the reform of Agis IV without clearly identifying the relevant roles of the ephors and of the γέροντες in the decision-making procedure.Footnote 55 Other scholars have adopted views stressing the informality of Spartan deliberation. Following Ruzé, Richer argues that the literary sources show that both the Gerousia and the Assembly were not summoned to make an ultimate decision, because the γέροντες did not submit a formal proposal to the δᾶμος, so that the early stages of the procedure (the first meeting of the Gerousia and the first meeting of the Assembly) consisted of mere preparatory work before the final decision.Footnote 56 Schulz argues that these passages from Diodorus and Plutarch attest deliberative procedures in which the Assembly played an advisory role when there was no unanimity among the γέροντες.Footnote 57 According to Schulz, Plutarch's passage in particular illustrates a probouleutic procedure structured in two steps:Footnote 58 first, the Gerousia prepared the motions to be submitted to the Assembly; second, the Assembly was summoned and the motion was put to the vote. However, if the Gerousia could not make a unanimous decision, a meeting of the δᾶμος could be held in order to gauge the people's opinion without taking a formal vote. After hearing that, the Gerousia submitted a final προβούλευμα for the vote before the δᾶμος, approving it by majority rule.Footnote 59 These studies, however, provide accounts of the probouleutic procedure that does not fit the historical evidence of deliberative practice in non-democratic constitutions.Footnote 60 In reconstructing the Spartan deliberative procedure, all these scholars have drawn a forced analogy between Hetoimaridas’ debate in Diodorus’ Library and Plutarch's account of Agis’ reforms. Schulz's reconstruction, moreover, underestimates the role of the ephorate in the deliberative practice by implying that the Assembly did not discuss a formal proposal. There are several problems with these accounts.

First, one should clearly identify the specific procedural features of the two historical accounts. The problem with any simple juxtaposition is that the episodes are substantially different from a procedural point of view—not in the nature of the procedure but in how the procedure unfolds. We can see that Diodorus’ account, structured in two parts, shows a decision-making process that is conditioned by a key difference with that summarized by Plutarch. Initially, the Gerousia and the δᾶμος agreed on making war against Athens, then Hetoimaridas delivered his speech and persuaded both the γέροντες and the citizens to change their plans. Diodorus thus makes clear that there was an initial general consensus among the γέροντες, as well as among the citizens, and this is the reason why no one ‘dared to advance any other proposal’ (Diod. Sic. 11.50.5: οὐδένα τολμήσειν συμβουλεῦσαι ἕτερόν τι). In contrast to the case of Agis described by Plutarch, there is no dispute within the Gerousia, and this consensus in the Gerousia determines the next procedural step: a vote of ratification by the Assembly. Plutarch clearly shows that in the case of Agis’ reforms there was instead political dissent, organized into two factions: on one side, Agis, the ephor Lysander and the majority of the citizens, and, on the other side, the majority of the γέροντες and King Leonidas. This dissent was already expressed in the first meeting of the Gerousia and later in the debate in the citizens’ Assembly. By contrast, in Diodorus’ passage there is no contrast at all. Everyone agreed about the proposal for making war and an assembly was called to ratify the decision of the Gerousia. Hetoimaridas, at that point, delivered his speech by which he persuaded the γέροντες, still in session, and the Assembly, which rejected the proposal without any opposition from the γέροντες. This shows a probouleutic procedure that follows the usual pattern common in the Greek world. The Council of Elders, and possibly the unmentioned ephors, reached an agreement about a proposal, which was then submitted to the Assembly for ratification. In that case, the Assembly, influenced by a γέρων who spoke against the bill approved by the Gerousia, rejected the bill, with the endorsement of the rest of the Gerousia, that had by then also changed its mind.

Moving from Diodorus to Plutarch's Life of Agis, we find a more detailed description of the procedure, the steps of which are compatible with those identified in the case of Hetoimaridas. In Plutarch, the kings, the Gerousia, the ephors and the Assembly are all involved. First, Plutarch makes it clear that it was the ephor Lysander who drafted a formal written proposal (γραφείσης δὲ τῆς ῥήτρας) in the Gerousia (εὐθὺς εἰσέφερε δι᾽ αὐτοῦ ῥήτραν εἰς τοὺς γέροντας).Footnote 61 The use of written documents in Spartan public life is not surprising. As Millender has convincingly shown, the Spartans made wide use of written documents for their diplomatic activities, and already in the Classical period Sparta had an archive with copies of state documents, such as international treaties, lists of eponymous ephors and athletic victories.Footnote 62 This means that there was an official document containing the provisions of the bill, and only after (aorist participle) the presentation of the formal draft did the legislative procedure begin. The γέροντες did not reach unanimity about the provisions of the bill (καὶ τῶν γερόντων εἰς ταὐτὸ ταῖς γνώμαις οὐ συμφερομένων), which means that a proper draft was prepared after a discussion in the Gerousia (Plut. Agis 9.1). The two genitive absolute clauses are key here. The former genitive absolute shows a causal connection between the presentation of the rhetra by Lysander and the subsequent dissent of the γέροντες, which presupposes a formal debate in the Gerousia, after which the ephor prepared the relevant draft. The latter can be understood as having concessive meaning: ‘the rhetra was written, although the opinions of the γέροντες did not agree’. This confirms that the ephor could introduce a proposal, even if the γέροντες did not pass the proposal. The following sentence (ἐκκλησίαν συναγαγὼν ὁ Λύσανδρος αὐτός τε διελέχθη τοῖς πολίταις) is logically coordinated and implies that Lysander, in force of his ephoral power, summoned the Assembly to discuss the same written motion.

Thus, the role of the ephor Lysander in starting the decision-making process highlights a key feature: probouleusis was not the exclusive province of the Gerousia; rather, the power was actually divided between ephorate and Gerousia. Even without the unanimous vote of the Elders in the Gerousia, the ephor Lysander was able to summon an Assembly and to put the motion to the vote. This is also supported by the fact that Agis IV was very concerned with procuring the election of Lysander before presenting his bill to the Gerousia, in order to have a political ally for his revolutionary reforms. The king had clearly no power to introduce his rhetra to the Assembly without the fundamental support of the ephor who could bypass the γέροντες when initiating the deliberative process.Footnote 63

The ephors took part in the Gerousia meetings, and the eponymous ephor was in charge of presiding over the Assembly and supervising the voting of the δᾶμος.Footnote 64 This is consistent with the evidence concerning the power of the ephors to initiate legislation. In the Hellenica Xenophon says that in 400 b.c. the Spartan ephors and the Assembly resolved (ἔδοξε τοῖς ἐφόροις καὶ τῇ ἐκκλησίᾳ) to send ambassadors to Elis (Xen. Hell. 3.2.23). He employs the same expression when Sparta decides to go to war with the Achaeans against the Acharnanians (Hell. 4.6.3: ἔδοξε τοῖς τ᾽ ἐφόροις καὶ τῇ ἐκκλησίᾳ).Footnote 65 Ruzé rightly points out that this formula resembles the Athenian enactment formula, which shows a parallel between the probouleutic function of the Athenian Boulē and the probouleutic function of the Spartan ephors.Footnote 66 The ἔδοξε–formula in deliberative practice not only is similar to the Athenian version but also was widespread across the Greek world.Footnote 67 Thucydides reports the Spartan enactment formula by quoting two treaties in Doric dialect between Sparta and Argos (Thuc. 5.77.1, 5.79.1). The first text is a Spartan peace-treaty draft with the preliminary proposal to Argos (καττάδε δοκεῖ τᾷ ἐκκλησίᾳ τῶν Λακεδαιμονίων), the second document provides the final text of the alliance between the Spartans and the Argives (ἔδοξε τοῖς Λακεδαιμονίοις καὶ Ἀργείοις).Footnote 68 In both cases, the formula shows patterns similar to those found in Xenophon's Hellenica, even if the ephors are not mentioned.Footnote 69 These formulas are not in contradiction with each other. Indeed, Xenophon had direct access to Spartan institutional practice and the formulas he cited should therefore be taken to represent the normal deliberative practice in Classical Sparta. Thucydides instead reports the draft and the final version of a copy of an international treaty, which he perhaps consulted during the period of his exile.Footnote 70 In the Spartan proposal only the Assembly is mentioned, but it is clear that some unmentioned probouleutic body—in all probability the ephors—must have introduced the motion to the Assembly. It is interesting to note that, in early fifth-century Athens too, decrees could have only ἔδοχσεν το͂ι δέμοι without mentioning the Council in the enactment formula (for example, IG I3 1). In this case, Thucydides might have consulted an archival copy, because it seems implausible that the Spartans or the Argives had inscribed on stone a copy of the preliminary proposals. On the other hand, the second formula underlines the agreement procedure between the two communities without mentioning the respective deliberative bodies of the two cities. Another famous Thucydidean passage shows that the ephors were in charge of putting a matter to the vote even without the unanimous consensus of the Gerousia. When the Spartans were discussing whether they should declare war against Athens in 432 b.c., King Archidamus delivered a speech against war, while the ephor Sthenelaidas spoke forcefully in favour of war, and he himself put the question to the vote of the Assembly (τοιαῦτα λέξας ἐπεψήφιζεν αὐτὸς ἔφορος ὢν ἐς τὴν ἐκκλησίαν τῶν Λακεδαιμονίων), which passed it (Thuc. 1.79–87).Footnote 71 Yet, a comparison with other Hellenistic cities shows that the role of the Spartan ephors in the decision-making process has also a contemporary parallel in the function of the Iasian πρυτάνεις. Decrees from Hellenistic Iasos attest that, after the third century's reform, the Iasian Assembly could only examine motions passed by the Council after the prior consideration of the πρυτάνεις acting as πρόβουλοι.Footnote 72 Likewise, in Hellenistic Cyme, the στρατηγοί summoned the Council and introduced the προβουλεύματα to the Assembly.Footnote 73

The probouleutic power of the ephors and their relevant role in the deliberative procedure shows that there is no need to hypothesize any contio-like or advisory meeting of the Spartan Assembly.Footnote 74 As Nafissi rightly points out, the Great Rhetra does not mention any informal meeting of the δᾶμος.Footnote 75 An examination of the probouleutic practice in the Greek poleis shows no evidence of such advisory meetings of an assembly before or during probouleusis. Instead, Greek deliberative procedure shows that the people's assemblies were always gathered either to discuss a well-defined proposal drafted by the relevant probouleutic body—a Council or a board of officials—or to discuss an open προβούλευμα, which implies broad deliberative powers of the people's Assembly.Footnote 76 It is clear from the evidence that the Spartan Assembly had only the first of these prerogatives, and could only enact or reject a proposal submitted by the Gerousia and the ephors but could not deliberate on an open προβούλευμα.Footnote 77 In the passage from Diodorus, the Assembly is asked to vote on the Gerousia’s proposal for war, already approved by the γέροντες unanimously. Conversely, in the passage from Plutarch, Lysander opens the formal discussion in the Assembly about Agis’ reforms, which are then passed by the δᾶμος, but the bill had not been previously approved unanimously by the Gerousia. The text shows that, if the bill had not been unanimously pre-approved by the Gerousia, even after the Assembly's approval, it could be vetoed by the γέροντες with a simple majority vote.Footnote 78 This point should be stressed: it appears that the vote of the δᾶμος on a decree not pre-approved unanimously by the γέροντες was not final; but it was not meaningless either, as it gave the bill the chance to be approved by a simple majority of γέροντες, whereas at the normal probouleumatic stage it needed unanimity in order for the vote of the δᾶμος to be final.

Thus, a procedure structured in these three stages fits both the so-called ‘rider’ of the Great Rhetra and the Aristotelian account of oligarchic probouleusis already mentioned. At Pol. 1272a10–12 Aristotle describes the similarities between the Cretan and the Spartan constitutions by drawing analogies between the roles of the Cretan κόσμοι and the roles of the Spartan ephors, as well as between the role of the Councils of Elders.Footnote 79 He then states that in both constitutions every citizen attends the meetings of the Assembly, which has however no authority (κυρία δ᾽ οὐδενός ἐστιν)Footnote 80 except in ratifying the proposals (συνεπιψηφίσαι τὰ δόξαντα) of the Elders and of the κόσμοι.Footnote 81 Yet, at Pol. 1298b, when describing the institutional powers of πρόβουλοι and νομοφύλακες, Aristotle states that in the politeia-regimes—such as Sparta and Crete—the few have the authority to reject (οἱ γὰρ ὀλίγοι ἀποψηφισάμενοι μὲν κύριοι) but not to pass proposals (καταψηφισάμενοι δὲ οὐ κύριοι), which are always referred to the dēmos (ἀλλ᾽ ἐπανάγεται εἰς τοὺς πλείους αἰεί). The verb ἀποψηφίζεσθαι is the very same term that Plutarch employs to describe the vote of rejection by the Gerousia. As the literary evidence shows, this verb is often used in Athenian forensic speeches for penalties that needed to be approved (Antiph. 1.12, 5.96; Lys. 10.31, 12.90; Lyc. 1.149), therefore of proposals that had already been formally presented. In the case of Sparta, the verb marks the fact that the proposal had already been passed by the δᾶμος.Footnote 82 To push the parallel with the Athenian usage of the verb, the ἀπεψηφισμένοι were those Athenian citizens who lost their civic rights for not fulfilling the legal requirements and were therefore ‘rejected’ from the civic registers of the demes.Footnote 83 Thus, according to the Aristotelian account, in some oligarchic constitutions legislation is to be ratified by assemblies, but the probouleutic bodies can make them invalid a posteriori. In addition to the probouleutic power, which is used before a proposal reaches the Assembly, they have a veto power that can be used after the approval of a bill by the Assembly. This matches precisely the powers of the Spartan γέροντες: they clearly had probouleutic powers (exercised before a bill reached the Assembly) but also the power of nomophylakia through which they could stop the legislative procedure by invalidating those motions that contradicted the nomoi, which were therefore σκόλιον, as the Great Rhetra states.Footnote 84 A similar view is found in Aeschines’ Against Timarchus (Aeschin. 1.180–1).Footnote 85 When praising Sparta, Aeschines states that, during a debate, a dissolute but skilful speaker addressed the Assembly which was persuaded by his argument. A γέρων, however, stood up and said that they should not listen to that man, and asked a virtuous man to give the same advice, so that the Spartans could act according to the suggestions of a distinguished citizen. This anecdote is unlikely to be historically accurate, but it clarifies the Athenian understanding of the political decision-making in Sparta, and of the role of the Gerousia. A γέρων could stop the debate in the Assembly, if some basic principles embedded in the εὐνομία were not respected, performing therefore a nomophylakia role.

Finally, a comparison between Plutarch's account and other non-democratic deliberative practices may also shed light on this issue. Demetrius of Phalerum introduced magistrates called νομοφύλακες in Athens between 317 and 307 b.c. during the oligarchic government following the peace between the Athenians and the Macedonian king Cassander.Footnote 86 The powers of the Athenian νομοφύλακες are described in an entry of the Lexicon Rhetoricum Cantabrigiense (s.v. νομοφύλακες), based on Philochorus’ evidence, which states that the νομοφύλακες sat at the meetings of the Council and the Assembly next to the πρόεδροι with the task of stopping inexpedient deliberations.Footnote 87 This shows a clear analogy with the role of the γέροντες in Spartan decision-making procedures. The Gerousia indeed was present and gathered during the Assemblies of the δᾶμος,Footnote 88 as were the Athenian νομοφύλακες, but not to gauge ‘informally’ the δᾶμος; rather, their role involved checking the legality of deliberation and potentially vetoing illegal enactments. This is the reason for which, after Agis’ rhetra had been enacted by the Assembly, a simple majority vote of the γέροντες would have sufficed for the bill to be carried, instead of the unanimity required at the probouleutic stage. Agis must have known that he could not obtain a unanimous vote from the γέροντες but must have hoped that, faced with the overwhelming favour of the δᾶμος, at least a simple majority of γέροντες would decide to let the bill stand. Agis claimed to represent the Lycurgan tradition, but similarly his opponents among the γέροντες could maintain that his rhetra was contrary to the established nomoi. The Gerousia therefore exercised its prerogative to halt the legislative procedure safeguarding the traditional order—the majority vote at nomophylakia–stage sank his reform.

What was the ideological rationale of this decision-making procedure? In democratic Athens, for example, the Assembly could delegate power to the Council to enact a further decree, in order to complement the decision-making by exploiting the expertise of the βουλευταί in particular matters and displaying a ‘divided power’ in deliberation between Council and Assembly (SEG 10, 40; IG I3 136; IG II2 204; RO 53; IG II2 1629).Footnote 89 That procedure was rooted in the democratic ideological framework according to which the deliberative power did not belong exclusively to one governmental agency. Democratic ideology was alien to Sparta, but one can nevertheless find patterns of ‘divided power’, though essentially non-democratic in their nature. The ēthos of the Spartan deliberative procedures was to constrain deliberation within the boundaries of the traditional nomos. As the evidence has shown, the probouleutic procedure in Sparta limited free debate in the Assembly. Probouleusis therefore assumes a prominent role in the constitutional equilibrium, since every matter discussed in the Assembly was put forward through this procedure without allowing further changes. The Spartan institutional system, however, shows that this fundamental power was shared between ephors and Gerousia, because neither of these two bodies had an exclusive role in bringing motions before the δᾶμος. A προβούλευμα thus needed the unanimous vote of the Gerousia in order to be submitted for ratification before the Assembly, but the ephors, being in charge of initiating the legislative process, could also present a motion directly to the δᾶμος. This institutional mechanism allowed the ephors to run the legislative process by giving voice to the people, in case of opposition by the γέροντες. As a consequence, the Spartan system gave a prominent role to the voice of the Assembly in case of dissent between the γέροντες and the ephors and when the γέροντες could not reach unanimity. The standard legislative procedure was therefore based on the need for general consensus within and between those bodies of government that held the probouleutic powers. No single institution had a more prominent role in the decision-making process, as the constitutional system was designed to achieve balance and stability. Ephors and γέροντες, therefore, had to play a joint role in managing an effective probouleusis, in order for a decision to be finally enacted by the Assembly.

On the other hand, when there was no consensus between the two probouleutic bodies, or within the Gerousia, a bill could go to the Assembly anyway but with the proviso that it would still need to be ratified by the γέροντες by simple majority. The alleged ‘rider’ of the Rhetra provided the legal foundation for this by allowing a decision of the γέροντες after a vote of the Assembly was taken. In Athens, the Boul ē could be legally empowered through a delegation-clause to enact a new decree to integrate the decision passed by the Assembly. Just as in Athens, therefore, in Sparta a decision could be reconsidered by the probouleutic body, but there was no need of ad hoc delegation, because the γέροντες were in charge of checking whether the decisions of the Assembly conformed to the nomoi, rather than integrating the people's decisions with new enactments. Thus, the Gerousia played the role of a judicial-review body that in Classical Athens was performed by the law courts. Athenian law courts democratically scrutinized the legality of Assembly decrees through the γραφὴ παρανόμων, which could be brought by any Athenian citizen (ὁ βουλόμενος). By contrast, in Sparta the same institutional task was performed by a restricted body according to different procedures but addressing the same need to conform to the laws.

In order to be performed, this nomophylakia did not require the unanimity of the Elders, who rejected the rhetra of Agis with a vote by simple majority. The different voting procedure adopted by the Gerousia at the two different stages reflects the different roles it was called to perform—in one case probouleusis, in the other nomophylakia. Through its use of majority vote in the veto procedure, the Council of Elders was able to render invalid a decision of the δᾶμος, which voted by acclamation, because of their higher status in the community in terms of the institutional knowledge, values and prestige that the office of γέρων carried.Footnote 90 More remarkably, it is worth stressing that the Gerousia itself employed two different voting systems in performing probouleusis and nomophylakia, which had relevant implications for the nature of deliberation. The difference in the voting system not only is a matter of institutional technique but also was supported by strong connections with two distinct ideological approaches. When voting a draft to be sent for ratification to the Assembly, the Gerousia did not use majority rule but a unanimous vote, which was a deliberative mechanism favouring the creation of consensus within the political body, in this case the narrow gathering of the Elders. This consensus-based mechanism was typical of deliberative settings in the Greek world and tried to shape decision-making through the inclusion, rather than the exclusion, of dissent.Footnote 91 By contrast, when the γέροντες acted as guardians of the laws, performing a legislative review over deliberation, they adopted the principle of majority rule. In this case, the task required by the decision-making procedure was different. When vetoing a decision of the δᾶμος, the γέροντες were checking the consistency of that decision with the traditional Spartan nomos. What was at stake was not a political decision and the creation of consensus but rather the safeguarding of the laws. Again, this is consistent with the practice of other Greek poleis in which legislative or judicial review is attested. In democratic Athens, most of the time, the Council and the Assembly passed their decrees with overwhelming consensus or unanimity, very rarely by a bare majority (for example, Thuc. 3.37.3–4 during the Mytilenean debate).Footnote 92 The law courts, however, when adjudicating the legality of decrees and laws through the γραφὴ παρανόμων and the γραφὴ νόμον μὴ ἐπιτήδειον θεῖναι voted by majority rule because of their distinct institutional task. Each voting procedure was thus designed to answer the distinctive ideological and institutional goals of probouleusis and nomophylakia.

In addition to this, it is important to underscore that the features of ‘divided power’ applied not only to probouleusis but also to the practice of nomophylakia, which was also shared between γέροντες and ephors. The νομοφύλακες, as we find them attested in other poleis and as their function is described by Aristotle, not only exercised control over deliberation but also supervised the application of the rule of law. While the Gerousia was in charge of supervising the legality of the debate in the Assembly, the ephors had the task of overseeing the observance of the laws by public officials as well as the individual behaviour of citizens according to the traditional custom. As the ancient evidence shows, like the Athenian νομοφύλακες during the Demetrian oligarchy, the ephors had broad powers over the other magistrates, who had to perform their duties according to the laws in order not to be subject to the severe sanctions of the five ephors.Footnote 93 Xenophon states that the ephors did not (as in other poleis) leave the elected magistrates to rule as they liked throughout the year (τοὺς αἱρεθέντας ἀεὶ ἄρχειν τὸ ἔτος) but immediately punished those who broke the laws (τινα αἰσθάνωνται παρανομοῦντά τι, εὐθὺς παραχρῆμα κολάζουσι), in the manner of tyrants and supervisors of athletic games (Xen. Lac. 8.4). Aristotle says that the ephors have the power to perform the εὔθυναι over the other magistrates (Arist. Pol. 1271a4–6). The kings themselves were supervised by the ephors during their military campaigns, and every month the kings and the ephors took an oath.Footnote 94 The kings swore to rule respecting the established nomoi (κειμένους νόμους βασιλεύσειν) and the ephors swore to preserve the kingship (Xen. Lac. 15.7).Footnote 95 The ancient sources therefore illustrate that both the power of nomophylakia and the power of probouleusis were shared between the Gerousia and the ephors, who worked jointly in running the deliberative process as well as in preserving Spartan laws according to the ideology of the Spartan politeia. This conservative ideology required a permanent control of the elected magistrates regarding deliberation, which was strictly constrained within the limits of the traditional nomoi. Institutions and legal procedures were therefore shaped according to these ideological values, which, in the institutional sphere, favoured in practice the dominant role of the elite within the restricted group of Spartan citizens.

IV. CONCLUSION

To sum up: the analysis of ancient evidence concerning deliberative procedure in Sparta shows that a decision could go back to the Gerousia because of the permanent legal and political control of its officials over the δᾶμος, which regulated the decision-making interplay between Gerousia, ephors and Assembly. As in the rest of the Greek world, the Assembly in Sparta played an important role in deliberation, but the people's deliberation was strictly controlled by probouleutic officials. The Gerousia and the ephors shared the role of probouleutic bodies as well as that of νομοφύλακες within the Spartan decision-making process, according to the patterns of ‘divided power’. As literary evidence from Plutarch demonstrates, the ephors had the power of initiating the legislative procedure, both in the Gerousia and in the Assembly, but a unanimous vote of the γέροντες was needed in order to submit a προβούλευμα to the δᾶμος for final ratification. The ephor could introduce a motion in the Assembly with no need of unanimity among the γέροντες, but in this case the procedure required the bill to be revised by the Gerousia, which could veto the motion with a majority vote by employing the power of nomophylakia granted by the Great Rhetra. The deliberative procedure therefore required a third passage in the Council of Elders, when there was a lack of consensus among the probouleutic bodies (or even within the Gerousia alone). The ideology of Spartan institutions granted the power to officials to shape decisions through probouleusis and nomophylakia, and the aim was to avoid innovation in legislation and institutional practice, as well as to maintain balance in the decision-making process, even if Spartan society was remarkably unequal even with its very narrow citizen body.Footnote 96 Such a decision-making process combines the need to gain popular consent with a strict control over legislation in accordance with conservative values and practices.Footnote 97

References

1 For Sparta as model for modern republicanism, see Nippel, W., ‘Ancient and modern republicanism: “mixed constitution” and “ephors”’, in Fontana, B. (ed.), The Invention of the Modern Republic (Cambridge, 1994), 626 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 For the expression mirage spartiate, see Ollier, F., Le Mirage Spartiate. Étude sur l'idéalisation de Sparta dans l'antiquité grecque de l'origine jusqu'aux Cyniques (Paris, 1933)Google Scholar.

3 On Xenophon's Constitution of the Lacedaemonians, see Tuplin, C., ‘Xenophon, Sparta and the Cyropaedia ’, in Hodkinson, S. and Powell, A. (edd.), The Shadow of Sparta (London, 1994), 127–82Google Scholar; Lipka, M., Xenophon's Spartan Constitution (Berlin, 2002), 36 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Gray, V., Xenophon On Government (Cambridge, 2007)Google Scholar.

4 For a careful analysis of Sparta in Aristotle's works, see Bertelli, L., ‘La Sparta di Aristotele: un ambiguo paradigma o la crisi di un modello?’, RSA 34 (2004), 971 Google Scholar.

5 See also Lys. 33.7.

6 For studies about the myth of Sparta, see e.g. Tigerstedt, E.N., The Legend of Sparta in Classical Antiquity, vols. 1–3 (Stockholm, 1965–1978)Google Scholar; Powell, A. and Hodkinson, S. (edd.), The Shadow of Sparta (London, 1994)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Cartledge, P., Agesilaos and the Crisis of Sparta (London and Baltimore, 1987), 118 Google Scholar.

8 Flower, M., ‘The invention of tradition in Classical and Hellenistic Sparta’, in Powell, A. and Hodkinson, S. (edd.), Sparta beyond the Mirage (London, 2002), 191217 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For first lawgivers, see Hölkeskamp, K.J., Schiedsrichter, Gesetzgeber und Gesetzgebung im archaischen Griechenland (Stuttgart, 1999), 4459 Google Scholar; Camassa, G., Scrittura e mutamento delle leggi nel mondo antico: dal Vicino Oriente alla Grecia di età arcaica e classica (Rome, 2011), 71177 Google Scholar; Canevaro, M., ‘Making and changing the laws in ancient Athens’, in Canevaro, M. and Harris, E.M., The Oxford Handbook of Ancient Greek Law (Oxford, 2015) (DOI 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199599257.013.4)Google Scholar.

9 Hodkinson, S., ‘“Blind ploutos”? Contemporary images of the role of wealth in Classical Sparta’, in Powell, A. and Hodkinson, S. (edd.), The Shadow of Sparta (London, 1994), 183222 Google Scholar; S. Hodkinson, ‘Was Sparta an exceptional polis?’, and Hansen, M.H. and Hodkinson, S., ‘Spartan exceptionalism. Continuing the debate’, in Hodkinson, S. (ed.), Sparta: Comparative Approaches (Swansea, 2009), 417–22 and 473–98Google Scholar respectively. For a concise but effective history of modern scholarship about Sparta, see in the same volume pages ix–xxxiii (Introduction with bibliography).

10 The noun ῥήτρα shows an oral origin of the archaic text. The division of the text of the Rhetra and the ‘rider’ are in fact later antiquarian distinctions; see Nafissi, M., La nascita del kosmos: studi sulla storia e la società di Sparta (Perugia, 1991), 6771 Google Scholar.

11 Nafissi, M., ‘The Great Rhetra (Plut. Lyc. 6): a retrospective and intentional construct?’, in Foxhall, L., Gehrke, H.J., Luraghi, N. (edd.), Intentional History. Spinning Time in Ancient Greece (Stuttgart, 2010), 89119 Google Scholar (with full bibliography on the Great Rhetra at 93 n. 20), pace Schulz, F., Die homerische Räte und die spartanische Gerusie (Düsseldorf, 2011), 154 Google Scholar. For intentional history, see Gehrke, H.J., ‘Myth, history, and collective identity: uses of the past in ancient Greece and beyond’, in Luraghi, N. (ed.), The Historian's Craft in the Age of Herodotus (Oxford, 2001), 286313 Google Scholar. See also Maffi, A., ‘Studi recenti sulla Grande Rhetra ’, Dike 5 (2002), 195235 Google Scholar; and Lupi, M., ‘Testo e contesti. La Grande Rhetra e le procedure spartane di ammissione alla cittadinanza’, Incidenza dell’ Antico 12 (2014), 941 Google Scholar, who controversially maintains that the Great Rhetra is not a constitutional document but provides an archaic procedure for the admission of new members in the Spartan civic body during the religious festival of the ἀπέλλαι.

12 Nafissi, M., ‘Sparta’, in Raaflaub, K. and van Wees, H., A Companion to Archaic Greece (London, 2009), 117–37, at 127CrossRefGoogle Scholar; on the relationship between the Great Rhetra and Tyrtaeus’ Εὐνομία, see van Wees, H., ‘TyrtaeusEunomia: nothing to do with the Great Rhetra’, in Hodkinson, S. and Powell, A., Sparta: New Perspectives (London, 1999), 142 Google Scholar; van Wees, H., ‘Gute Ordnung ohne grosse Rhetra: noch einmal zu TyrtaiosEunomia’, GFA 5 (2002), 89103 Google Scholar, who argues that it is very difficult to identify clear cross-references between the two texts contra Raaflaub, K.A., ‘Athenian and Spartan eunomia, or: what to do with Solon's timocracy?’, in Blok, J.H. and Lardinois, A.P.H.M. (edd.), Solon of Athens: New Historical and Philological Approaches (Leiden, 2006), 390428 Google Scholar.

13 See section III below.

14 Andrewes, A., ‘The government of Classical Sparta’, in Badian, E. (ed.), Ancient Societies and Institutions. Studies Presented to Victor Ehrenberg on his 75th birthday (Oxford, 1966), 120 Google Scholar, at 5 n. 8; de Ste. Croix, G.E.M., The Origins of the Peloponnesian War (London, 1972), 127Google Scholar n. 99; Jeffrey, L.H., Archaic Greece: The City-States 700–500 B.C. (London, 1976), 249 Google Scholar.

15 Ruzé, F., Déliberation et pouvoir dans la cité grecque de Nestor à Socrate (Paris, 1997), 150–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 Schulz (n. 11), 196–201.

17 Pasquino, P., ‘Il potere diviso. Dalla graphé paranomon nella democrazia ateniese a John Locke e James Madison’, in Conflitti (Naples, 2005), 8999 Google Scholar; Pasquino, P., ‘Democracy ancient and modern: divided power’, in Hansen, M.H. (ed.), Démocratie athénienne – démocratie moderne: tradition et influences (Geneva, 2010), 1–50, at 27–8Google Scholar.

18 Harris shows that there was no shift from popular sovereignty in the fifth century b.c. to the sovereignty of law in the fourth century b.c. In both periods it was the role of the courts to implement the rule of law and for the Assembly to uphold popular sovereignty. See E.M. Harris, ‘From democracy to the rule of law? Constitutional change in Athens during the fifth and fourth centuries b.c.e.’, in Tiersch, C. (ed.), Die athenische Demokratie im 4. Jahrhundert. Zwischen Modernisierung und Tradition (Stuttgart, 2016), 80–5Google Scholar, pace Hansen, M.H., The Athenian Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes: Structures, Principles, Ideology (Oxford, 1991), 150–5, 300–4Google Scholar.

19 For Spartan εὐνομία and the spirit of archaic law, see Harris, E.M., Democracy and Rule of Law in Classical Athens. Essays on Law, Society, and Politics (Cambridge, 2006), 328 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

20 Harris, E.M., ‘The flawed origins of ancient Greek democracy’, in Havlíček, A., Ch. Horn, Jinek, J. (edd.), Nous, Polis, Nomos. Festschrift Francisco L. Lisi (St. Augustin, 2016), 113 Google Scholar.

21 The incorrect identification of the ephors in the Rhetra and in Tyrtaeus’ ἄνδρες δημόται is based on weak interpretations of literary evidence from Plut. Lyc. 6.10 and Diod. Sic. 7.12.6, and on arbitrary assumptions that Diodorus’ lines come from Tyrtaeus’ poem (cf. Nafissi [n. 11], 98–102), pace Richer, N., Les éphores. Études sur l'histoire et sur l'image de Sparte (VIIIe – IIIe siècle av. J. C.) (Paris, 1998), 98106 Google Scholar; Link, S., Das frühe Sparta. Untersuchungen zur seiner staatlichen und gesellschaftichen Entwicklung im 7. und 6. Jh. v.Chr. (St. Katharinen, 2000), 1930 Google Scholar; Luther, A., Könige und Ephoren. Untersuchungen zur spartanischen Verfassungsgeschichte (Frankfurt am Main, 2004), 4459 Google Scholar.

22 See Plut. Lyc. 6.3. Nafissi (n. 11), 104–7 points out that this is a retrospective word, normally used for oikists and founders of cults.

23 Nafissi, M., ‘Forme di controllo a Sparta’, Il pensiero politico 40 (2007), 329–44, at 331–2Google Scholar; Millender, E., ‘The Spartan dyarchy: a comparative perspective’, in Hodkinson, S. (ed.), Sparta: Comparative Approaches (Swansea, 2009), 3140 Google Scholar. On Spartan kingship, see Carlier, P., La royauté en Grèce avant Alexandre (Strasbourg, 1984)Google Scholar; Cartledge, P.A., Spartan Reflections (London, 2001), 5567 Google Scholar.

24 Harris, E.M., ‘Military organization and one-man rule in the Greek polis ’, Ktèma 40 (2015), 8390 Google Scholar. For the legal controls of military leadership in the Greek poleis, see Harris, E.M., ‘The rule of law and military organization in the Greek polis ’, in Thür, G. (ed.), Symposion 2009: Vorträge zur griechischen und hellenistischen Rechtsgeschichte (Vienna, 2010), 405–17Google Scholar.

25 The regular Doric word was γεροντία (Xen. Lac. 10.1).

26 See Nafissi (n. 23), 331; Schulz (n. 11), 237. For the voting powers and the epistemic status of the γέροντες, see Schwartzberg, M., Counting the Many: The Origins and Limits of Supermajority Rule (Cambridge, 2014), 25–7Google Scholar. See also Lupi, M., ‘Il voto dei re spartani’, Quaderni di Storia 79 (2014), 3841 Google Scholar. Cf. Hdt. 6.57; Thuc. 1.20.3; Pl. Leg. 692a2 (δύναμις ἰσόψηφος).

27 For the life appointment, see David, E., Old Age in Sparta (Amsterdam, 1991), 18 Google Scholar; Ruzé (n. 15), 138–9.

28 Schulz (n. 11), 106–8.

29 For καλοκἀγαθία in Sparta, see Wankel, H., Kalos kai Agathos (Frankfurt, 1961)Google Scholar; Davies, P., ‘ Kalos kagathos and scholarly perception of Spartan society’, Historia 62 (2013), 259–79Google Scholar, pace Bourriot, F., ‘ Kaloi kagathoi, kalokagathia à Sparte aux époques archaïque et classique’, Historia 45 (1996), 129–40Google Scholar. Cf. Cairns, D.L., ‘Review of F. Bourriot, Kalos Kagathos—Kalokagathia: D'un terme de propagande de sophistes à une notion sociale et philosophique: Étude d'histoire athénienne (Zürich and New York, 1995)’, CR 47 (1997), 74–6Google Scholar.

30 Schulz (n. 11), 121–2 calculated that the average office term for a γέρων was roughly 7.5 years, with a turnover of 3.73 new γέροντες every year.

31 See also Hdt. 9.28.1; Thuc. 1.87.

32 Schulz (n. 11), 114–15. For the election of the ephors, see Richer (n. 21), 296–307.

33 Schwartzberg (n. 26), 25–6.

34 For an analysis of the ritual, see Jordan, B., ‘The ceremony of the helots in Thucydides IV 80’, AC 59 (1990), 3769 Google Scholar; David (n. 27), 18–19; Schulz (n. 11), 117–19.

35 For death penalty and exile, cf. Schulz (n. 11), 180–1.

36 For instances of trials of Spartan kings, see Hdt. 6.82, Paus. 3.6.8, Xen. Hell. 3.3, 8–11, Plut. Agis 19. The legal procedure for capital trials began before the ephors, who conducted the ἀνάκρισις and brought the charge before the Gerousia. See also Vat. Gr. 2306 fr. A 1–30 and Keaney, J.J., ‘Theophrastus on Greek judicial procedure’, TAPhA 104 (1974), 179–94Google Scholar.

37 Ephors are also called by sources as: ἀρχή, ἄρχοντες, τὰ τέλη, οἱ ἐν τέλει. See Richer (n. 21), 265–70.

38 Nafissi (n. 12), 130–1.

39 It is possible that an ephor could be elected only once to that office. On ephors, see also Sommer, S., Das Ephorat. Garant des spartanischen Kosmos (St. Katharinen, 2001)Google Scholar.

40 For the mobilisation, see Richer (n. 21), 324–34; for the religious role, 157–257; for finance, 477–9; for εὔθυναι, 442–4 with Fröhlich, P., Les cités grecques et le contrôle des magistrats (IVe –Ier siècle avant J.-C.) (Geneva and Paris, 2005)Google Scholar.

41 For probouleusis in Athens, see Rhodes, P.J., The Athenian Boule (Oxford, 1972), 5281 Google Scholar; de Laix, R.A., Probouleusis at Athens: A Study of Political Decision-Making (Berkeley, 1973)Google Scholar; cf. Dem. 22.5–7; [Arist.] Ath. Pol. 45.4.

42 See Harris, E.M., ‘Nicias’ illegal proposal in the debate about the Sicilian expedition (Thuc. 6.14)’, CPh 109 (2014), 6672 Google Scholar.

43 March, J.G. and Olsen, J.P., ‘The New Institutionalism: organizational factors in political life’, APSR 78 (1984), 734–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and id. ‘Elaborating the “New Institutionalism”’, in Rhodes, R.A.W., Binder, S.A. and Rockman, B.A. (edd.), The Oxford Handbook of Political Institutions (Oxford, 2006), 320 Google Scholar; Fioretos, O., Falleti, T.G., Sheingate, A., ‘Introduction: historical institutionalism in political science’, in Fioretos, O., Falleti, T.G., Sheingate, A. (edd.), The Oxford Handbook of Historical Institutionalism (Oxford, 2016), 423 Google Scholar.

44 On πρόβουλοι or νομοφύλακες, see Arist. Pol. 1323a; πρόβουλοι were elected in Athens soon after the defeat in the Sicilian expedition. See Thuc. 8.1.3; [Arist.] Ath. Pol. 29.2–31.3. Cf. Rhodes, P.J., A Commentary to the Aristotelian Athenaion Politeia (Oxford, 1981), 362415 Google Scholar; Harris, E.M., ‘The constitution of the Five Thousand’, HSPh 93 (1990), 243–80Google Scholar.

45 Cf. M. Canevaro, ‘Aristotele, Politica IV, capitoli 14–16’, in Bertelli, L. and Moggi, M. (edd.),  Aristotele. La Politica. Introduzione, traduzione e commento (Rome, 2014), 279377, at 314Google Scholar.

46 A late sixth-century probouleutic Council of Elders (πρείγα) is also attested in an unknown city of Western Locris. It played a role along with the assembly (πόλις) and the ἀποκλεσία in overriding an entrenchment clause about division of the land (IG IX I2 609).

47 Cf. Arist. Pol. 1299b–1300a4 with Canevaro's commentary (n. 45), 336–7.

48 On the historicity of the event, see in particular the good analysis of Vattuone, R., ‘Hetoimaridas: note di politica interna a Sparta in età classica’, in Bearzot, C. and Landucci, F. (edd.), Partiti e fazioni nell'esperienza politica greca (Milan, 2008), 131–51Google Scholar. See also Green, P., Diodorus Siculus. Books 11–12.371. Greek History, 489–431. The Alternative Version (Austin, TX, 2006), 111 n. 190Google Scholar; see also Zaccarini, M., ‘The case of Cimon: the evolution of the meaning of philolaconism in Athens’, Hormos–Ricerche di Storia Antica 3 (2011), 287304 Google Scholar, at 291 n. 15 contra Fornara, C.W. and Samons, L.J. II, Athens from Cleisthenes to Pericles (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1991), 122–4Google Scholar.

49 Griffith, G.T., ‘Isegoria in the assembly at Athens’, in Badian, E. (ed.), Ancient Society and Institutions. Studies presented to Victor Ehrenberg on his 75th birthday (Oxford, 1966), 115–38Google Scholar, 134 n. 10; see also Kelly, D.H., ‘Policy-making in the Spartan Assembly’, Antichthon 15 (1981), 4761, at 59 n. 45CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

50 Plut. Agis 8–11.

51 Gabba, E., ‘Studi su Filarco’, Athenaeum 35 (1957), 355 Google Scholar, especially 15; Africa, T.W., Phylarchus and the Spartan Revolution (Berkeley and Cambridge, 1961)Google Scholar; cf. Polyb. 2.56; Pédech, P., Trois historiens méconnus: Théopompe, Duris, Phylarque (Paris, 1989), 403 Google Scholar. For a recent study on Polybius and Phylarchus’ dramatic historiography, see Schepens, G., ‘Polybius on Phylarchus’ “tragic” historiography’, in Schepens, G., Bollansée, J. (edd.) The Shadow of Polybius. Intertextuality as a Research Tool in Greek Historiography. Proceedings of the International Colloquium, Leuven, 21–22 September 2001 (Leuven-Paris-Dudley, 2005), 141–64Google Scholar.

52 Powell, A., ‘Spartan women assertive in politics? Plutarch's Lives of Agis and Kleomenes ’, in Hodkinson, S. and Powell, A., Sparta: New Perspectives (London, 1999), 401–15Google Scholar.

53 For the reforms of Agis IV, see Cartledge, P. and Spawforth, A., Hellenistic and Roman Sparta (London and Berkeley, 1991), 6872 Google Scholar.

54 Diodorus’ text does not mention shouts and applauses, but this practice is attested in Sparta. For voting by shouting, see n. 35.

55 Kelly (n. 49), 60.

56 Richer (n. 21), 349–51; cf. Ruzé (n. 15), 150; Ruzé, F., ‘Dire le droit: retour sur la grande rhètra’, in Legras, B. and Thür, G. (edd.), Symposion 2011: Études d'histoire du droit grec et hellénistique (Paris, 7–10 September 2011) (Vienna, 2012), 515 Google Scholar has recently reasserted her interpretation through a controversial reading of the Rhetra. Cf. Gagarin's reply: M. Gagarin, ‘Observations on the Great Rhetra: a response to Francoise Ruzé’, in Legras and Thür (this note), 17–20.

57 Schulz (n. 11), 198–200 substantiates his thesis by including other pieces of evidence. In particular, the passages in Plut. Agis 5.3–5 about the rhetra introduced by the ephor Epitadeus and the passages in Plut. Lys. 16–17 about the prohibition of silver and gold seem clearly to highlight the wide probouleutic power of the ephors rather than the primacy of the Gerousia. Yet, Schütrumpf and Hodkinson have clearly demonstrated that the Epitadeus episode in the Life of Agis is an unhistorical account, and that it is based on Plato's Republic (555c–e). See Schütrumpf, E., Aristoteles, Politik: Buch II und Buch III (Berlin, 1991), 317 Google Scholar; Hodkinson, S., Property and Wealth in Classical Sparta (London, 2000), 90–4Google Scholar. See also Nafissi, M., ‘Asteropos e Epitadeus. Storie di due efori spartani e di altri personaggi dai nomi parlanti’, Incidenza dell’ Antico 6 (2008), 49–89, at 72–84Google Scholar.

58 For previous reconstructions, see Forrest, W.G., ‘Legislation in Sparta’, Phoenix 21 (1967), 1119 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

59 Schulz (n. 11), 196–201. Schulz singles out two distinct kinds of assemblies: an advisory assembly (beratende Volksversammlung) and a decision-making assembly (entscheidende Volksversammlung).

60 Ruzé (n. 15), 154 argues that the ‘spécificité’ of the Spartan polis made it difficult for the ancient author to describe the decision-making by using ordinary institutional terminology. For examples of oligarchic practice, see pp. 17–18 below.

61 Plut. Agis 8.1, 9.1. Schulz (n. 11), 200. For the use of writing by the ephors, see Richer (n. 21), 436–7, 446–7, 479–80; for the Spartan σκυτάλη, see Richer (n. 21), 483–90; on literacy in Sparta, see Boring, T.A., Literacy in Ancient Sparta (Leiden, 1979)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

62 Millender, E.G., ‘Spartan literacy revisited’, ClAnt 20 (2001), 127–41Google Scholar.

63 For the Boulē–Dēmos opposition in the narrative of Plutarch's Lives, see Pelling, C., ‘Plutarch and Roman politics’, in Pelling, C., Plutarch and History. Eighteen Studies (London, 2009), 211–17Google Scholar.

64 Kennell, N.M., Spartans: A New History (Chichester, 2010), 169 Google Scholar. Cf. Xen. Hell. 2.3.34; the decisions of the board of ephors were binding for all its members.

65 Cf. Plut. Lys. 14.4, which reports the decree of the ephors stating: ‘this is resolved by the authorities of the Lacedaemonians’ (τὸ δ᾽ ἀληθινὸν δόγμα τῶν ἐφόρων οὕτως εἶχε: τάδε τὰ τέλη τῶν Λακεδαιμονίων ἔγνω).

66 Schulz (n. 11), 212 explains that the formula mentions only the ephors and the Assembly, because of an ellipsis of the term ‘Gerousia’, since it was in-between these two institutions in the decision-making. The ephors started the legislative procedure by putting forward the motion in the Gerousia and the Assembly ratified it. However, the enactment formula usually shows the enactment bodies of a decree or of a law, and Schulz's explanation is forced.

67 There are 3,692 occurrences of this clause on the PHI database of Greek inscriptions. However, cf. Rhodes, P.J. and Lewis, D.M., The Decrees of the Greek States (Oxford, 1997), 258 Google Scholar e.g. on Mytilenean probouleumatic formulas, which are very different from this model.

68 On the treaty in Thucydides, see Canfora, L., ‘Trattati in Tucidide’, in Canfora, L., Liverani, M., Zaccagnini, C., I trattati nel mondo antico. Forma, ideologia, funzione (Rome, 1990), 193216 Google Scholar.

69 Richer (n. 21), 339.

70 On Thucydides’ autopsy of these documents, see Schepens, G., L'autopsie dans le méthod des historiens grecques du Ve siècle avant J.-C. (Brussels, 1980), 184 Google Scholar.

71 Schulz (n. 11), 206–7 interprets this passage as evidence for the lack of probouleusis between the two speeches and the vote of the Assembly. It is possible that no written draft was discussed, but it is clear that the ephor was legally empowered to use his probouleutic power by putting the item to the vote of the δᾶμος. Similarly, in Polyb. 4.34–5 the ephors allowed the Aetolian ambassador to address the Assembly and to discuss the alliance, even if there was no unanimity amongst the γέροντες.

72 Fabiani, R., ‘ Dedochtai tei Boulei kai toi Demoi: protagonisti e prassi deliberativa a Iasos’, in Mann, C. and Scholz, P. (edd.), Demokratie im Hellenismus. Von der Herrschaft des Volkes zur Herrschaft der Honoratioren? (Mainz, 2012), 156 Google Scholar.

73 Hamon, P., ‘Kymè d’Éolide, cité libre et démocratique, et le pouvoir des stratèges’, Chiron 38 (2008), 63–106, at 70Google Scholar.

74 For the Spartan Assembly as contio, see n. 15 above.

75 Nafissi (n. 10), 364.

76 Rhodes and Lewis (n. 67), 484–91 with many examples of probouleusis in practice in the Greek poleis.

77 Nafissi (n. 23), 335, pace Ruzé (n. 56). For the prohibition on emending proposals drafted by magistrates in the Spartan assembly, see Arist. Pol. 1272a10–12 below, pace Andrewes (n. 14), 4, who drew an analogy with the Athenian practice of open προβουλεύματα. It is worth noting that even in fourth-century Athens, where the Assembly had broad powers, in the period from 403/402 b.c. to 323/322 b.c. the number of preserved decrees on stone that were verbatim ratifications of the Council's προβουλεύματα is higher than non-probouleumatic decrees amended by the dēmos (52%–48%); see Oliver, G., ‘Oligarchy at Athens after the Lamian War: epigraphic evidence for the Boule and the Ekklesia ’, in Palagia, O. and Tracy, S. (edd.), The Macedonians in Athens 322–229 BC. Proceedings of the International Conference held at the University of Athens, May 24–26 2001 (Oxford, 2003), 40–51, at 46Google Scholar.

78 Kennell (n. 64), 110.

79 For Cretan Councils of Elders, see M. Youni, ‘Councils of Elders and aristocratic government in the Cretan poleis’, with the answer of Maffi, A., ‘Il consiglio degli anziani e le istituzioni politiche delle città cretesi: risposta a Maria Youni’, in Gagarin, M., Lanni, A. (edd.), Symposion 2013: Vorträge zur griechischen und hellenistischen Rechtsgeschichte (Cambridge MA, 26.–29. August 2013) (Vienna, 2015), 13–26 and 27–30Google Scholar respectively. Against a view of powerful Councils of Elders in Crete, see Gagarin, M. and Perlman, P., The Laws of Ancient Crete: 650–400 b.c.e. (Oxford, 2016), 62–4Google Scholar.

80 The term kyrios (κύριος) indicates both in the documentary sources and in philosophical language a legally recognized power that does not need to refer to a higher authority. Cf. Miller, F.D., ‘Aristotle's philosophy of law’, in Miller, F.D. and Biondi, C.A. (edd.), A History of the Philosophy of Law from the Ancient Greeks to the Scholiastics (Dordrecht, 2007), 106–7Google Scholar.

81 Cf. Nafissi (n. 10), 363–5; Bertelli (n. 4), 40–3; cf. the use of the same expression in Polyb. 21.32.1 to indicate the ratification vote of the motion of the συνέδριον by the dēmos (δόξαντος δὲ τῷ συνεδρίῳ, καὶ τοῦ δήμου συνεπιψηφίσαντος, ἐκυρώθη τὰ κατὰ τὰς διαλύσεις).

82 Canevaro (n. 45), 315–17. Cf. also IG II2 1237 (lines 31, 38, 90, 95, 98, 101–3).

83 Poddighe, E., ‘Ateniesi infami (atimoi) ed ex Ateniesi senza i requisiti (apepsephismenoi). Nuove osservazioni in margine al fr. 29 Jensen di Iperide sulle diverse forme di esclusione dal corpo civico di Atene’, AFLC 61 (2006), 524, at 16Google Scholar.

84 David (n. 27), 33—contra Schulz (n. 11), 155–7—recognizes that the Gerousia was empowered of nomophylakia but does not include it in his reconstruction of the probouleutic and deliberative procedure.

85 Cf. Fisher, N., Aeschines Against Timarchos (Oxford, 2001), 329 Google Scholar.

86 For the legislation of Demetrius of Phalerum, see O'Sullivan, L., The Regime of Demetrius of Phalerum in Athens, 317–307 b.c.e. (Leiden, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Banfi, A., Sovranità della legge. La legislazione di Demetrio del Falero ad Atene (317–307 a.C.) (Milan, 2010)Google Scholar; Canevaro, M., ‘The twilight of nomothesia: legislation in early Hellenistic Athens (322–301)’, Dike 14 (2013), 55–85, at 66–9Google Scholar.

87 Bearzot, C., ‘I nomophylakes in due lemmi di Polluce (VIII 94 νομοφύλακες e VIII 102 οἱ ἕνδεκα)’, in Bearzot, C., Landucci, F. and Zecchini, G. (edd.), L'Onomasticon di Giulio Polluce: tra lessicografia e antiquaria (Milan, 2007), 4368 Google Scholar; id. Nomophylakes e nomophylakia nella Politica di Aristotele’, in Talamo, C. and Polito, M. (edd.), Istituzioni e Costituzioni in Aristotele tra storiografia e pensiero politico (Tivoli, 2012), 2947 Google Scholar; Canevaro (n. 45), 315–17. For nomophylakes in Athens, see Canevaro (n. 86), 66–7; Faraguna, M., ‘I nomophylakes tra utopia e realtà istituzionale delle città greche’, Politica Antica 5 (2015), 141–55Google Scholar. Cf. also Harp. s.v. νομοφύλακες and Pollux (8.94), who confirms the information in the Lexicon Rhetoricum Cantabrigiense, pace Morrow, G.R., Plato's Cretan City: A Historical Interpretation of the Laws (Princeton, 1960), 199 Google Scholar n. 108, who argues that there is no evidence of νομοφύλακες acting as probouleutic officials apart from Aristotle's statement.

88 Kelly (n. 49), 60.

89 Cf. Harris (n. 18), 76–80.

90 For the institutional values of the office of γέροντες, cf. p. 6 above.

91 Cf. a list of forty-one epigraphical examples of voting figures in Todd, S.C., ‘The publication of voting figures in the ancient Greek world’, in Legras, B. and Thür, G. (edd.), Symposion 2011: Études d'histoire du droit grec et hellénistique (Paris, 7–10 September 2011) (Vienna, 2012), 3348 Google Scholar. Consensus was also used by boards of officials: cf. Thuc. 6.46.5–6.50.1; Plut. Nic. 14.3; Alc. 20.2–3 and see Harris (n. 24), 410. For consensus in Greek deliberative practice, see now Canevaro, M., ‘Majority rule vs consensus: the practice of deliberation in the Greek poleis ’, in Canevaro, M., Erskine, A., Gray, B. and Ober, J. (edd.), Ancient Greek History and the Contemporary Social Sciences (Edinburgh, forthcoming)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

92 Cf. Canevaro (n. 91).

93 Fröhlich (n. 40), 294–7: in democratic regimes, ὁ βουλόμενος could bring a charge against magistrates who were usually supervised by larger bodies, such as the Council or the Assembly. For the ephors as supervisors of magistrates, see Fröhlich (n. 40), 373–5.

94 Harris (n. 24), 87.

95 See Lipka (n. 3), 246; cf. Plut. Cleom. 9.2, who, reporting Aristotle, says that the ephors taking office told the citizens ‘to shave their moustaches and to obey the laws’ if they wanted to avoid their sanctions.

96 For analysis of property and wealth in Sparta, see Hodkinson (n. 57).

97 In writing this essay I have incurred numerous debts of gratitude. I would like to thank Dr Benjamin Gray and Dr David Lewis for reading and commenting on a previous draft of this essay, Professor Edward Harris for his extensive and valuable feedback, and the anonymous referee at CQ for many thorough and helpful suggestions. I also would like to thank those who proofread this essay. Most of all, I am grateful to Dr Mirko Canevaro who read and commented on various drafts and helped me at every stage, through long conversations, providing invaluable suggestions and encouragement. Finally, I would like to thank the AHRC and the School of History, Classics and Archaeology of the University of Edinburgh for supporting the work for this essay. Any remaining errors are my own.