We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Marmor considers the separation thesis, which he understands as saying that whether a given norm is legally valid depends on its sources, not its merits; and this means that he is concerned with the separation thesis conceived as a thesis about legal status, not as a thesis about the content of legal statements. Observing that the distinction between sources and merits is very close to the distinction between is and ought, he considers the objection that the separation thesis cannot be upheld because one cannot clearly distinguish between sources and merits, between is and ought. He responds to this objection, however, that the separation thesis can be upheld if it is seen as an answer to the question ‘What counts as law?’ rather than to the question ‘What is law?’, and that this response is in keeping with a common wish on the part of legal positivists to provide a reductive explanation of legal validity, that is, an explanation of legal validity exclusively in terms of social facts.
Baum Levenbook explores another criticism made against legal positivism. As she explains, Mark Greenberg objects to legal positivism, first, that it is a mistake to hold that legal facts are determined solely by social facts and, second, that the content of authoritative pronouncements, such as statutes, is determined by their linguistic content. But, she points out, Greenberg’s first objection is premised on the mistaken assumption that the nature of law requires the connection between legal facts and the determinants of legal facts to be, as Greenberg puts it, ‘rationally intelligible’, and the second objection is based on the equally unwarranted assumption that it is part of the nature of law to operate in such a way as to ensure that legal obligations are genuinely binding.
Recommend this
Email your librarian or administrator to recommend adding this to your organisation's collection.